Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T02:07:27.480Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - Normative Approaches to Technology and Human Rights

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 April 2018

Molly K. Land
Affiliation:
University of Connecticut School of Law
Jay D. Aronson
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania

Summary

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2018
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

The essays in Part I focus on the relationship between human rights law and technological developments – specifically what human rights law requires when new technologies are introduced and disseminated in society, and how new technologies have the potential to fragment the very legal authority needed to address the negative impacts of technology.

The first two chapters consider how human rights law applies to technology. In Chapter 2, “Safeguarding Human Rights from Problematic Technologies,” Lea Shaver explores what the emerging right to science requires of states when new technologies are introduced in a way that significantly impacts human rights. Using South African litigation over restrictive water meters as her lens, she argues that human rights activists and institutions need to be conscious of the technological element of human rights violations. She proposes looking to human subjects protection as a framework for legal accountability for what may amount to involuntary and harmful technological experiments. In Chapter 3, “Climate Change, Human Rights, and Technology Transfer: Normative Challenges and Technical Opportunities,” Dalindyebo Shabalala focuses on state obligations to engage in technology transfer through a human rights lens. Shabalala argues that human rights provides a stronger basis than development approaches for making claims to climate change technology transfer. Human rights emphasizes the needs of vulnerable populations within countries and provides a basis for differentiating between and prioritizing particular technologies.

The next two chapters consider the introduction of new technologies through the frames of ethics and the law of war. In Chapter 4, “Judging Bioethics and Human Rights,” Thérèse Murphy considers the intersection of human rights law and bioethics, which addresses ethical issues associated with medical and biological technology. She examines leading cases in the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights on the regulation of reproductive technology in order to bring bioethics and human rights into deeper conversation. In Chapter 5, “Drones, Automated Weapons, and Private Military Contractors: Challenges to Domestic and International Legal Regimes Governing Armed Conflict,” Laura Dickinson considers how the automationFootnote 1 and privatizationFootnote 2 of war interact with each other to exacerbate the effects on human rights. Dickinson argues that these developments undermine domestic limits on the power of the US president to declare war, and also obscure and fragment decision-making authority on the use of deadly force in ways that diminish existing mechanisms of accountability under international law.

One of the clearest contributions of the chapters in Part I is their dramatic illustration of the variety of ways in which technology can affect rights. New technological innovations have significant consequences for human rights, in terms of both the opportunities they offer for the fulfillment of rights and the harms they can cause. States and non-state actors can use technology to limit rights in unanticipated and often invisible ways, as Shaver’s and Dickinson’s chapters make clear. These consequences are not limited to civil and political rights. Part I reveals that technology is just as central to the enjoyment of economic and social rights – health, water, and the environment – as it is to the rights to association, privacy, family, and expression.

The application of technology alters cultural understandings around concepts like privacy and family in ways that affect the application of international human rights norms to these problems. As technology expands the possibilities available for forming and extending families, it also puts tension on what it means to have a right to found a family – how far that right extends and the role that human rights law should play in reconciling competing claims regarding reproductive decisions.Footnote 3 These essays demonstrate that the relationship between human rights law and technology is not unilateral, but mutually constitutive. Just as international human rights law is transformed by the introduction of new technologies, technology is also affected by international human rights law. As legal regimes generate new rights and transform others, they also shape the path of technological development.Footnote 4 As Shabalala’s chapter (Chapter 3) illustrates, for example, the international rules regarding intellectual property affect the path of green technology development and transfer in developing countries.

The chapters in Part I also consider the obligations that human rights law puts on the regulation of technology itself. Human rights law is technologically neutral on its face, not anchored to any particular form of technology or system of knowledge production. At the same time, the human rights corpus, especially the right to science, requires states to ensure that the introduction of new technology does not harm rights and to create an enabling environment that facilitates rights promotion in the face of new technology. States also have obligations to individuals in other countries to promote the transfer of knowledge when this knowledge is necessary for those individuals to enjoy their fundamental human rights. This duty becomes ever more important as technological development exacerbates global inequalities and technology plays an increasingly prevalent role in fulfilling economic and social rights.

The essays in Part I also grapple with the question of how international human rights law ought to respond to technological change, including how technology can better incorporate human rights into its design. Two aspects of international human rights law help it to be robust enough to respond to the challenges presented by new technologies. First, as a product of political compromise and an attempt to articulate rules that apply across widely diverging national systems, human rights law is, in general, ambiguous and underdeveloped. Although this can be a source of frustration for many, it also helps ensure that human rights law can be interpreted in ways that meet new challenges.Footnote 5 For example, Shaver’s chapter (Chapter 2) demonstrates how human rights law might be interpreted and adapted to respond to the threat some technologies pose to the enjoyment of human rights.

Second, human rights treaties generally allow, either directly or indirectly, a fair measure of discretion for states in terms of how they implement their treaty obligations. Although human rights law does at times prohibit particular conduct on the part of the state, states have leeway to determine how best to achieve certain outcomes.Footnote 6 This discretion also enables human rights law to evolve in ways that meet technological challenges, including challenges that require the state to undertake new initiatives to meet their international obligations.

At the same time, while the broad discretion and ambiguity that characterize human rights law allow it to evolve with technology, new interpretations must retain a focus on the core values of international human rights. This is achieved not by “updating” the law, but rather by consciously engaging with questions of risk, harm, and social disruption that inevitably accompany the introduction of new technology. Thus, a core value of a human rights-based approach to technology is attention to the consequences of technological innovation. Further, this attention must be focused on distribution of power and resources. As the chapters by Shaver (Chapter 2) and Shabalala (Chapter 3) make clear, the effects of technological innovation on human rights are not experienced equally along lines of race, class, gender, or other status. Instead, technology is deployed in uneven and unequal ways that often have a negative impact on the most vulnerable. Moreover, the inequitable distribution of technology along national, regional, and socioeconomic lines also has consequences that can reinforce power imbalances, particularly global power imbalances.

2 Safeguarding Human Rights from Problematic Technologies

Lea Shaver Footnote *

“Water is life. Life without water is not life. One cannot speak of a dignified human existence if one is denied access to water.”

High Court Decision (2008), Para. 124

“[T]he right of access to sufficient water … does not require the state … to provide every person with sufficient water … [R]ather it requires the state to take reasonable legislative and other measures progressively to realise the achievement of the right of access to sufficient water, within available resources.”

Constitutional Court Decision (2009), Para. 50

Beginning in 2004, impoverished black residents of Phiri township, in South Africa’s Soweto area, began to encounter a previously unknown technology: the prepaid water meter. Phiri residents had previously enjoyed a standard piped water supply billed at a flat monthly rate. The majority of these desperately poor households could not afford to pay their water bills. Because it is illegal under South African law to disconnect water services as a penalty for debt, however, the water supply had long been, in effect, free. The new technology was installed on each home’s water line in order to restrict this free water supply. Each household was allotted a monthly ration of free water. Additional amounts could be released only by purchasing tokens to insert into the meter.

This “demand-management” technology was hailed by the City of Johannesburg’s water utility as an ideal technical solution to a persistent financial problem. Large amounts of water were being consumed yet never paid for in very poor neighborhoods. The water meters achieved the intended goals of conserving water and exacting greater payment. They also led to intense hardship for desperately poor residents, who had to redirect already scarce resources or go without water for days or weeks at a time. (As an example of the extreme poverty prevalent in Phiri, one resident, Lindiwe Mazibuko, testified that her household of fourteen subsisted on a combined income of under $100 per month.)Footnote 1 The prepaid meters quickly became a detested symbol of material deprivation, political marginalization, and the long shadow of apartheid.

Popular frustration with the prepaid water initiative led to community demonstrations and an organized social movement, led by the populist left-wing Anti-Privatization Forum (APF). Massive resistance initially delayed installation of prepaid meters in Phiri. Johannesburg Water obtained court orders forbidding residents from interfering with the work, and a campaign of arrests and punitive water disconnections followed. Organized resistance then weakened, and installations continued. At this point, human rights lawyers heard about the situation and recommended constitutional litigation. With the support of the APF and a mass meeting of Phiri residents, the lawyers agreed to bring suit on behalf of the residents, challenging the installation of the water meters as unconstitutional.

Throughout the resulting litigation, the Phiri prepaid meter conflict was evaluated primarily in terms of the right to water. This right is explicitly recognized in the South African Constitution.Footnote 2 Mazibuko and Others v. City of Johannesburg and Others led to a victory for the human rights plaintiffs at the trial court. That result was largely upheld at an intermediate appellate level. The rights-favorable outcome was dramatically reversed, however, upon final appeal to the nation’s highest court. South Africa’s Constitutional Court approached the Mazibuko case through the lens of its increasing skepticism of judicial enforcement of social and economic rights. Emphasizing the difficulties of adjudicating rights subject to progressive realization, the Constitutional Court declined to find a violation of the right to water.

Since that time, however, human rights scholars and United Nations bodies have developed a fuller understanding of another human right implicated by prepaid meters: the right to science. Both the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights assert that everyone has a right to share in the benefits of scientific progress and its applications.Footnote 3 This has been referred to as “the right to enjoy the benefits of scientific progress” or, even more simply, “the right to science.” The right to science entails both a positive right of access to technologies essential for a life with dignity, and a negative right to protection from the imposition of technology in ways detrimental to human rights and human dignity.

This chapter revisits the Mazibuko case to consider how the conflict over prepaid meters might be analyzed through the lens of the right to science. I suggest that we should understand the rollout of prepaid water meters as a vast technological experiment that was conducted on vulnerable people, at significant risk to their health and well-being. Characterized in this way, the crucial question becomes whether the experiment was conducted with adequate human rights safeguards. Following widely accepted principles of ethical research, such safeguards should include free and informed consent, careful risk-benefit assessments, and appropriate selection of subjects. This new perspective on the prepaid meter controversy offers several forward-looking contributions:

First, this chapter offers a detailed case study of how a seemingly innocuous or even beneficial technology can operate in a context of unequal power to seriously endanger human rights. Various policy and design decisions made around the prepaid water meter technology created a situation that resulted in serious harm. These decisions were made in the context of a certain technological naiveté, bureaucratic carelessness, and/or corporate disinterest in the human rights of the end users. As this case study reveals, technology is not neutral to social injustice. People who are vulnerable by virtue of poverty, lack of education, or social discrimination are also uniquely vulnerable to the harmful application of new and potentially problematic technologies.

Second, this chapter helps to develop the still sparse legal framework of the right to science and proposes a violations approach to understand state duties regarding the right to science. Specifically, I argue that the right to protection from being subjected to technology in ways detrimental to human rights and dignity is immediately justiciable. The chapter uses the Phiri fact pattern to illustrate how human rights advocates can frame a claim in these terms. I also provide guidance as to how courts can evaluate the merits of such claims and fashion appropriate remedies. Even in jurisdictions where the right to science is not legally recognized, it remains possible and productive to rhetorically frame a problematic application of technology as an illegal experiment. This approach can complement invocation of the rights to health, life, and privacy, or any other right impacted by the particular technology at issue.

Third, and most ambitiously, it is my hope that engineers and others responsible for designing and implementing technical interventions can take lessons to avoid similar errors in the future. The framework of human rights safeguards should inform internal processes and policies around other new and potentially problematic technologies. The principles set forth and illustrated here can be applied by designers, technologists, in-house counsel, corporate social responsibility teams, and user communities to evaluate any proposed technological application or intervention. Building a pragmatic approach to conducting human rights impact assessments as a matter of routine is likely to be more impactful, in the end, than any campaign of human rights litigation. This is crucial to advancing the ultimate goal: to protect people from harm by anticipating and avoiding potential human rights missteps.

I “Demand Management Devices”

From 1948 to 1991, South Africa practiced an extreme form of racial discrimination known as apartheid. Between 1960 and 1983, millions of nonwhite South Africans were forcibly removed from their homes and resettled in racial enclaves under the Group Areas Act. Black South Africans could not vote and were denied basic civil rights. At one time, it was forbidden to publish newspapers in black languages or to teach black students in any language other than the language of the white Afrikaner minority that controlled the country. Decades of internal resistance and international pressure finally propelled the country to end apartheid in the 1990s.

Emerging from its first free election in 1994, the new democracy articulated bold goals for racial and economic inclusion. The new constitution was widely hailed as the most progressive in the world, committing to a long list of human rights. At the same time, South African policy-makers fully embraced capitalist development and modernization. South Africa needed to borrow money and attract foreign investment. This led to strong pressure to privatize public utilities as part of the Washington Consensus list of economic policies then viewed as essential for developing countries. An internal political struggle resulted in a compromise: the country would partially, but not fully, privatize key public services.

The political context of the introduction of prepaid water meters in South Africa has been thoroughly analyzed by Patrick Bond and Jackie Dugard.Footnote 4 In the wake of partial privatization, Johannesburg Water continued to be fully owned by the City of Johannesburg. Its operation, however, was largely contracted out to a French company, Suez. From that point forward, Johannesburg Water increasingly emphasized cost recovery as a fundamental principle, notwithstanding the constitutional commitment to water provision as a basic human right. An important component of this strategy was “water demand management,” which focused on reducing the amount of water consumed by households too poor to pay standard fees. One component of demand management involved shifting very poor neighborhoods that had enjoyed piped water on credit to more limited water service.

One way this was accomplished was through the installation of prepaid meters in black areas. These meters did not simply measure the amount of water delivered to homes. Their more significant function was to limit the amount of water delivered. The devices were programmed to let through a set ration of free water each month, a nod to the national and constitutional commitment to water as a human right. To access additional water, however, residents had to purchase tokens in advance. The killer feature of the technology was its ability to ensure stricter water conservation and financial discipline. All this was accomplished while bypassing normal legal procedures for discontinuing water service to a property.

Like any technology, prepaid water meters should not be understood as inherently negative or positive from a human rights standpoint. In theory, interruptive water meters could be deployed in a manner supportive of human rights. The technology undoubtedly made it more cost-effective to provide free water to low-income households. The savings might have been reinvested in expanding access to improved water sources for families with no connection at all. Interruptive water devices could also have been used to create shared access points in water-scarce regions, with water tokens distributed like wartime ration coupons. This point is particularly important to appreciate: the practical impact of a technology depends almost entirely upon the myriad particular decisions made by individuals and organizations implementing the technology in a specific social context.

For example, the human rights impact of prepaid water meters depends significantly on the pricing of additional water supply in relation to the resources of each household. If the household has substantial disposable income and tokens are priced very cheaply, it would be merely inconvenient to maintain a supply of tokens to regularly unlock the water supply. However, if the tokens are quite costly compared to the household’s limited resources, then the introduction of a prepaid meter imposes a new financial hardship. And if the household is truly desperately poor, then the monthly free water ration can become an oppressive ceiling rather than a supportive floor. From a human rights perspective, prepaid meters would have been least problematic in wealthier households. In practice, however, demand management devices were never introduced in areas where residents could easily afford to pay their water charges. The bureaucratic imperative that led to the adoption of this technology was to reduce unpaid water consumption by the extremely poor.

Another crucial design choice is what amount of free water to permit before restriction begins. With a very generous free water allowance, the devices might have no impact on existing water consumption patterns. With a moderate allowance, families might find that they had sufficient water for sanitation, bathing, drinking, cooking, and washing, but perhaps not enough to raise a kitchen garden, mop their floors, or allow children to play with water. With a meager allowance, residents might find that they faced frequent interruptions in water service and significant new pressure on household budgets already inadequate to meet basic needs.

In Phiri, the free water allowance proved to be meager. Johannesburg Water allotted each household just 6 kiloliters (kL) of free water per month. This was a steep 70 percent reduction from the previous estimated consumption of 20 kL per household. This should not be understood as an oversight or unintended consequence. Johannesburg Water deployed the devices specifically to dramatically reduce water consumption by nonpaying households. To achieve this goal, bureaucrats logically chose a ration well below current usage. Johannesburg Water defended the 6 kL figure as designed to provide a household of eight residents with 25 liters (6.6 gallons) of water per person per day. However, the average property in Phiri housed not eight, but sixteen residents. Thus, the free basic water ration actually worked out to a daily allowance of less than 15 liters (4 gallons) per person, on average. This level of water consumption is considered meager even within the setting of a desert refugee camp. Studies have found that limiting consumption to this level significantly increases the risk of disease.Footnote 5 Typical Americans use around 333 liters (88 gallons) of water per person per day for home uses.Footnote 6 Phiri residents were permitted only 5 percent of this amount.

Apart from the central question of whether water policy allocated enough free water to very poor households, the installation of prepaid meters impacted access to water in other ways. As might be expected with any new technology, the devices did not always work. Some households complained that their meters behaved erratically, accepting tokens but failing to release water. The devices also had not been well designed to allow residents to monitor their usage and estimate how long the remaining supply would last. Instead, the water supply would be cut off with very little warning. This could happen in the middle of cooking, or while caring for children, or at night, when it was not safe to leave the home to purchase additional tokens. Thus, water might not be available when urgently needed, even if the household was willing and able to pay. In one particularly tragic incident, two small children died when the monthly water supply ran out while residents were attempting to put out a shanty fire.Footnote 7

Another policy decision surrounding the technology was the degree of information and autonomy provided to residents. Although the water company sought consent from each household prior to installing the prepaid meters, the consent was neither free nor informed. Residents were not given an accurate picture of the risks and benefits of prepaid water devices in advance, and they had no ability to withdraw their consent after experiencing the technology firsthand. Phiri residents who complained about problems after meters were installed were told they could not go back to the old system. Residents who resorted to “self-help” measures by attempting to disable or bypass the water-restriction devices were punished with total disconnection from water service.

Users thus did not get to choose the prepaid meter technology; they were subjected to it. Prepaid water meters were deployed in South Africa to serve the cost-saving and revenue-maximizing goals of the agency that had the power to impose the technology rather than the human needs of the persons subjected to it. The design was optimized to meet the needs of the organization that purchased and implemented the devices, but did not take into account the needs of the people who would be directly affected by the technology. Phiri residents were not in control of the technology and did not have input into its design or implementation. They were not consulted about its parameters or informed of its potential risks. And even after the harmful effects became clear, they did not have the freedom to reject it. Technology became yet another means by which poor, black, politically disempowered South Africans were abused.

II The Mazibuko Litigation

Because Phiri residents lacked the power or autonomy to shape decisions around the prepaid meter technology, they were ultimately forced to seek redress in the courts. Human rights lawyers from the Center for Applied Legal Studies at the University of Witwatersrand represented them on a pro bono basis. The case was first heard in the High Court of South Africa, Witwatersrand Division.Footnote 8 The City of Johannesburg initially argued that it had no obligation to provide any amount of free water to the poor, but only a statutory obligation to offer water services for a fee. Justice Tsoka dispensed with that argument swiftly, confirming a constitutional obligation “to ensure that every person has both physical and economic access to water.”Footnote 9 This interpretation was grounded upon the South African Constitution’s explicit recognition of the right to water, read in light of international human rights law.Footnote 10 The High Court upheld the amount of 25 kL per person per day as a reasonable minimum, but emphasized that the city was “obliged to provide more than the minimum if its residents’ needs so demand and they are able, within their available resources, to do so.”Footnote 11 In light of conditions in the Phiri neighborhood, where households are large, sanitation depends upon an adequate water supply, and the residents are “mainly poor, uneducated, elderly, sickly and ravaged by HIV/AIDS,” the court concluded that the 6 kL free water allowance was insufficient.Footnote 12

Judge Tsoka went further, however, characterizing the water restriction devices as inherently unconstitutional because of the automatic shutoff function. The opinion first reviewed judicial opinions regarding water disconnections in Brazil, Argentina, France, and the United Kingdom. The Brazilian and Argentinian precedents were characterized as holding that a water company may not interrupt the supply of water due to nonpayment, because this would be a violation of human rights.Footnote 13 In France, it was noted, water companies are required to make special arrangements to ensure access to water for poor households, and disconnection for failure to pay requires court authorization.Footnote 14 In the United Kingdom, prepayment meters had been declared illegal under national statutes because they offered no notice or opportunity for a hearing prior to the cutoff of water supply.Footnote 15 Similarly, Judge Tsoka held that the use of automatic shutoff devices violated the South African constitutional right to “lawful, reasonable and procedurally fair administrative action,” at least for poor households.Footnote 16 Judge Tsoka further condemned the lower procedural protections given to Phiri’s poor black residents as “unreasonable, unfair and inequitable … [and] discriminatory solely on the basis of colour.”Footnote 17 As a remedy, the High Court ordered that all Phiri residents should receive a free basic water supply of at least 50 liters per person per day and be able to opt out of prepaid meters.Footnote 18

The City of Johannesburg and Johannesburg Water appealed the decision. The Appellate Court also found in favor of the Phiri residents. Its opinion upheld the lower court’s determination that the restrictive meters were unauthorized by law, and set the standard for constitutionally adequate water provision only slightly lower, at 42 liters per person per day. At this point, the City of Johannesburg and Johannesburg Water accepted their loss and did not initiate a further appeal. But the applicants themselves decided to push forward. Despite having obtained most of what they sought, including recovery of attorney fees, they pushed forward in hopes that the Constitutional Court would reinstate the High Court’s 50 liter per person per day benchmark and establish an even stronger precedent.

What happened next was a stunningly disappointing result for the Mazibuko plaintiffs. To everyone’s surprise, the Constitutional Court reversed every aspect of the prior decisions. Instead, the Constitutional Court used the Mazibuko case as an opportunity advance a more conservative vision of “the role of courts in determining the content of social and economic rights.”Footnote 19 While recognizing the constitutional right to water, the opinion refused to assign any real content to that right. It firmly rejected the notion of setting any quantitative threshold for a constitutionally adequate water supply.Footnote 20 Contrary to the lower courts’ reasoning, the Constitutional Court sided with Johannesburg in insisting that the right to water “does not confer a right to claim ‘sufficient water’ from the state immediately.”Footnote 21 Rather, it “requires the state to take reasonable legislative and other measures progressively to realise the achievement of the right of access to sufficient water, within available resources.”Footnote 22 In judging the city’s water policies as lawful and reasonable, the court went out of its way to give the state the benefit of every doubt. The opinion repeatedly emphasized that judicial review in the area of social and economic rights should be very deferential to the democratically accountable branches of government.Footnote 23 Rather than strictly scrutinizing the state’s actions, as the High Court and appellate judges had done, the Constitutional Court looked only for a rational basis.

Indeed, the opinion strongly suggests that the sole function of courts with respect to social and economic rights should be to provide a venue where citizens can require government agencies to publicly explain the reasons behind their policies.Footnote 24 This spotlight effect can pressure the government to revise its policies, as happened in this case, with the water agency making several concessions as the case wound its way through the courts. The opinion concluded optimistically:

This case illustrates how litigation concerning social and economic rights can exact a detailed accounting from government and, in doing so, impact beneficially on the policy-making process… Having to explain why the Free Water Policy was reasonable shone a bright, cold light on the policy that undoubtedly revealed flaws. The continual revision of the policy in the ensuing years has improved the policy in a manner entirely consistent with progressive realization.Footnote 25

The opinion’s frequent explicit references to “social and economic rights” make clear that this deferential approach to judicial review is reserved specifically for socioeconomic rights. Thus the secret to gaining stronger judicial protection against the use of technology to the detriment of human rights – at least in South Africa, and likely elsewhere as well – is to position it within more familiar frames of traditional civil rights protections against government abuses. The right to science can point the way to such an approach.

III The Right to Science

When the Mazibuko case was being litigated in 2007–09, the conceptual foundation for the right to water had only recently been laid. At that time, “the right to science” was not yet even a term in human rights discourse. It was thus not possible for the Mazibuko lawyers to consider framing their case in terms of the right to science, in addition to the right to water. Since that time, however, the right to science has been the subject of significant normative development by scholars and within the United Nations system.Footnote 26

The right to science offers two ways of framing the problems posed by prepaid meters. One is to focus on the aspect of the right to science that calls for expanding access to technology, particularly to what the Special Rapporteur has described as “technologies essential for a life with dignity.”Footnote 27 Modern indoor plumbing, which permits washing, bathing, cooking, and sanitation, has a strong claim to be considered an essential technology. In this way, the right to science might provide a hook for constitutional litigation in the same way that the right to water did. This view, however, also lends itself to similar weaknesses. This aspect of the right to science is a positive rights claim, subject to the logic of progressive realization. Many courts are hesitant to impose minimum core standards for essential services. Yet without judicially enforced minimums, it often seems impossible to make out a clear violation.

There is a second and, in my view, more interesting way of approaching the right to science as it relates to prepaid meters: to focus on the aspect of the right to science that calls for states “to prevent and preclude the utilization of scientific and technological achievements to the detriment of human rights and fundamental freedoms and the dignity of the human person.”Footnote 28 This approach is based on the notion that technologies are not inherently beneficial or harmful. Problems arise only when technologies are deployed in ways that are detrimental to human rights. Certain categories of technology are more likely to be problematic, however, an idea I will return to later in this chapter.

The right to science offers a framework for anticipating and responding to potential problems through human rights safeguards. This way of framing the legal challenge to demand management devices will refocus attention away from the question of how much water is sufficient – with all the attendant complexity, difficulty, and resistance to defining a quantitative minimum core to be enforced by courts – and instead toward recognition of the coercive application of the restrictive technology as the fundamental harm to be prevented. This way of looking at the right to science presents a classic negative rights claim, a right to freedom from harmful state action. Viewed from this perspective, Phiri residents suffered from a violation of their right not to be subjected to technology in a way that was harmful to their human rights and human dignity.

One way to understand the rollout of prepaid water meters in Phiri is as a massive technological experiment, conducted upon thousands of vulnerable people. Indeed, officials at Johannesburg Water understood the Phiri effort as an experiment. The stated intent was to pilot an unproven technical solution, in order to decide whether to roll it out more broadly. The Phiri prepaid water experiment was problematic for a number of reasons. It involved an unproven technology designed to restrict a substance vital to human life. It was conducted on a very large group of people who were particularly vulnerable by reason of their extreme poverty, including children, pregnant women, elderly people, and people suffering from HIV/AIDS, tuberculosis, and malaria. Subjects were coerced into participating and had no freedom to withdraw from the experiment once it started – in violation of the human rights principle that groups nonconsensual scientific experimentation with torture.Footnote 29 Fewer than twenty-five years after the end of apartheid, only black South Africans were selected for participation. Had university researchers proposed to run such an experiment, they would never have received ethical approval.

IV Human Rights Safeguards

After World War II, Nazi scientists were tried for war crimes for failing to follow internationally accepted ethical standards. The Nuremberg Code, the first international attempt to articulate these standards, remains a foundational document in scientific ethics. The World Medical Association’s 1964 Declaration of Helsinki similarly articulates basic standards for human subjects research and is regularly updated. While both of these documents are specifically directed to medical research, the 1978 Belmont Report is framed more broadly.Footnote 30 Its intent was to elaborate “broader ethical principles [to] provide a basis on which specific rules may be formulated, criticized, and interpreted.”Footnote 31 The Belmont principles continue to serve as touchstones for research ethics internationally, most significantly in the Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights.Footnote 32 The high level of generality of these principles makes them particularly useful for thinking about human rights obligations related to the application of new technologies.

A The Threshold Question: When Is Human Rights Scrutiny Required?

This first step in the Belmont Report was to establish threshold criteria for when special ethical review is required. Similarly, companies, administrative agencies, and courts need criteria to determine when the implementation of a new technology should require special human rights scrutiny.

The Belmont Report distinguished, on the one hand, traditional medical or behavioral “interventions that are designed solely to enhance the well-being of an individual patient or client and that have a reasonable expectation of success.”Footnote 33 Similarly, a proven technology that is designed primarily to enhance the well-being of the end user should trigger no special human rights scrutiny. Examples include extending traditional water service to new homes, upgrading old or leaking pipes with newer ones, or providing users with a text-messaging hotline to report water problems.

In contrast, the Belmont Report cautions that “radically new procedures … should … be made the object of formal research at an early stage in order to determine whether they are safe and effective.”Footnote 34 Prepaid water meters offer an ideal example of a radically new technology that requires safety and efficacy study. The technology had not previously been used in South Africa and had very limited application anywhere in the world. The prepaid meters also operated in a radically new way. Globally, the standard approach to water delivery has always been to provide a secure and consistent source of water controlled by the end user. Traditional water meters measure usage for billing purposes, but do not interrupt the supply against the user’s wishes. The prepaid meters, in contrast, dispensed a limited water supply determined by someone other than the user, and required payment in advance for additional amounts, through a brand-new token system.

Moreover, the interruptive meter technology was not designed and selected “solely to enhance the well-being” of the user.Footnote 35 Instead, this technology was selected and designed to advance larger demand-management and cost-recovery goals of Johannesburg Water. This criterion is important, because it helps to determine whether a conflict of interest exists between the person recommending the intervention and the person who will bear the risks. Where such a conflict of interest or tension exists, external review and accountability are recognized as being particularly important. Here, a strong tension existed between the goals of the technology planners and the well-being of individuals who were subjected to the technology. This conflict of interest heightens the risk of harm and therefore the need for human rights safeguards.

A third consideration should be the degree of freedom that individuals have to opt out of using the technology. When people are free to adopt or reject a particular technology, the option to “exit” serves as an important safeguard. When a technology is revealed to be harmful, individuals can often protect themselves by discontinuing its use. If an experimental drug makes a person sick, he or she can stop taking it. If a restrictive water meter is cutting off the water needed to cook, an individual should be able to bypass it. The exit option incentivizes companies to offer well-designed technologies with adequate support, so that consumers do not abandon their products. In a context where individuals are not free to reject a technology, however, these important safeguards are destroyed. Where a government mandates a technology that individuals experience as harmful to their health, liberty, privacy, or other interests, the need for human rights safeguards is paramount.

Finally, technologies that are intentionally designed, in the normal situation of use, to limit human rights call for special scrutiny. Most technologies will not trigger this concern. Seatbelts, credit card security chips, vaccinations, and Internet protocols are all examples of technology that is designed to enhance the user’s welfare. Government mandates to use these technologies would not typically be concerning in the ordinary case. In contrast, technologies that are designed to limit privacy, freedom of expression, or access to basic services deserve greater scrutiny. Such technologies would include surveillance technology and water-restriction devices. Dual-use technologies, or technologies that are designed in ways that enable both rights-restricting and rights-enhancing activity, also warrant enhanced scrutiny. Similarly, technologies that automate processes previously subject to the due process of law also deserve special scrutiny.

Prepaid water meters raised all four of these red flags. They were radically new and designed for a purpose other than the user’s well-being. People had little to no freedom to opt out of using them. They restricted access to a substance essential for human life. They bypassed existing legal processes by interrupting water access without the required court order. Following the logic of the Belmont principles, these characteristics should have triggered formal research to evaluate their safety and effectiveness. Arguably, the pilot application of the prepaid meter technology in Phiri was this required research. The problem, therefore, was not the complete lack of research, but rather the haphazard and unethical way in which the pilot was designed and carried out.

This can be seen by proceeding to examine the three principles that the Belmont Report lays out to guide ethical research: respect for persons, beneficence, and justice. First, “respect for persons demands that subjects enter into the research voluntarily and with adequate information.”Footnote 36 Second, beneficence requires researchers to put the best interests of the research subjects front and center in order to do no harm, or at least to minimize possible harms while maximizing benefits.Footnote 37 Finally, justice requires that persons submitting to the risks of scientific research should benefit from the fruits of that research, and that vulnerable people should not be inappropriately targeted as experimental subjects.

In other words, the Belmont principles establish requirements related to “informed consent, risk/benefit assessment, and the selection of subjects for research.”Footnote 38 The Phiri pilot had significant flaws with respect to each of these criteria. Consent was neither informed nor free, appropriate efforts were not taken to minimize risks, and the selection of subjects was discriminatory.

B Respect for Persons: Ensuring Free and Informed Consent

The first essential human rights safeguard for experimental technologies is insistence upon free and informed consent. The Belmont Report states, for example, that “[r]espect for persons requires that subjects, to the degree that they are capable, be given the opportunity to choose what shall or shall not happen to them. This opportunity is provided when adequate standards for informed consent are satisfied.”Footnote 39 The Universal Declaration on Bioethics provides: “The autonomy of persons to make decisions, while taking responsibility for those decisions and respecting the autonomy of others, is to be respected. For persons who are not capable of exercising autonomy, special measures are to be taken to protect their rights and interests.”Footnote 40 According to the Belmont Report, informed consent requires that “the subjects should understand clearly the range of risk and the voluntary nature of participation.”Footnote 41 Individuals must be adequately informed of the risks presented by the technology before making a free choice whether to participate or not. “Consent may be withdrawn by the person concerned at any time and for any reason without any disadvantage or prejudice.”Footnote 42 Experimentation in a context where consent may be unduly influenced by power dynamics, such as research on prisoners, is highly suspect.Footnote 43 Financial compensation may be offered for research participation, but care must be taken that such incentives do not corrupt freedom of choice, particularly with poor populations.

The consent process followed by Johannesburg Water was egregiously deficient by these standards. Johannesburg Water sent facilitators through the Phiri neighborhood with instructions to obtain signed consent forms from every property owner. Most of the property owners lacked the education to read the consent form, creating the distinct risk that facilitators would mislead them about the nature of the intervention in order to obtain their signatures. Respect for autonomy was so low, water meters were installed even despite some residents’ explicit refusal. For example, the lead plaintiff in Mazibuko testified that the facilitator seeking her signature deceived her, stating that the repairs were necessary to replace old and rusty pipes and making no mention of a prepaid meter. Having heard about prepaid meter installations elsewhere, however, she cautiously refused to sign the paper and verbally refused a meter. Notwithstanding her refusal, Johannesburg Water installed a prepaid meter at her property the following day.Footnote 44

Indeed, the vast majority of persons subjected to the Phiri prepaid meter experiment were never even asked for consent. A property owner’s signature was deemed sufficient for all residents of the property, whether adults or children, and even for unrelated members of separate households renting backyard shacks. Compounding this problem, the property owner was offered a significant financial benefit in exchange for subjecting other residents to the study. Johannesburg Water promised to erase years of past water debts in exchange for formally consenting to the installation of a prepaid meter.

To the extent that consent was sought, it was obtained under duress. Residents were advised that if they did not consent to the installation, their water supply would be completely disconnected. This threat was actually carried out when property owners did not sign the consent form. The lead plaintiff testified that after Johannesburg Water installed a prepaid meter on her property against her wishes, it disconnected her water supply. For several months, she walked 12 kilometers per day to transport water in a wheelbarrow for her household. Eventually, she broke down and “consented” to use a prepaid meter.Footnote 45

An additional fundamental requirement of free and informed consent is that participants have the opportunity to exit at any time. This was not assured in Phiri. Property owners were asked to consent to the installation of an unfamiliar technology. Once they had the opportunity to become familiar with the technology and its limitations and risks, however, there was no procedure by which they could revoke consent and have the device removed.

Finally, no effort was made to inform residents of the risks entailed by water restriction devices, despite their significance. Water authorities knew that the system would force households to dramatically reduce their water consumption. They also knew that the free allowance would be inadequate for even the most basic needs of larger households. Yet this information was not shared with residents, who had no ability to predict how far the free water supply would go in their household or how much they might have to spend on tokens. Some households lost renters who were contributing desperately needed income because the water supply had been downgraded. Other households watched their gardens, which were supplying much-needed fresh foods, wither and die. Most households had to divert funds from other essential spending in order to meet new water expenses. Households that could not do this would be entirely without water for days or weeks, until the next month’s supply began.

In sum, the Phiri prepaid water experiment is a case study in how not to practice informed consent. Gestures were made toward the need for consent, but only to the limited extent that was convenient for Johannesburg Water. There was never any actual respect for the individual’s right to refuse. These deficiencies reflect the extremely lopsided power dynamic at play in this particular technological experiment. Johannesburg Water understood itself as entitled to install its technology whether the individuals who were subjected to it wished it or not. Residents’ preferences were quite literally deemed to be irrelevant by actors who presumed to make these decisions in their best interest. Judge Tsoka, who had grown up as a black man under apartheid, reacted strongly to the patronizing racism he perceived in this wholesale denial of options: “That patronization sustained apartheid: its foundational basis was discrimination based on colour and decisions taken on behalf of the majority of the people of the country as ‘big brother felt it was good for them’.”Footnote 46

C Beneficence: Maximizing Benefit and Minimizing Harm

The second principle outlined in the Belmont Report is beneficence. The ordinary meaning of this term is the quality of doing something for the benefit of others. In the context of research ethics, it means that designers of experiments should concern themselves with the welfare of research participants by taking steps to minimize the risks and maximize the benefits to them. The Hippocratic principle “do no harm” is cited as an ideal to be approached.Footnote 47 “In applying and advancing scientific knowledge, medical practice and associated technologies, direct and indirect benefits to patients, research participants and other affected individuals should be maximized and any possible harm to such individuals should be minimized.”Footnote 48

It is entirely possible that Johannesburg Water officials believed they were acting in the best interests of the Phiri residents. It is always easy for planners to overestimate the reliability and user-friendliness of a new and untried technology. It is also clear that Johannesburg Water officials believed that substantial water was being wasted due to residents’ failure to value what they did not pay for. From their comfortable middle-class perspective, it may have been difficult to imagine that Phiri residents could not afford to pay such tiny charges.

What is clear from the Belmont Report, however, is that good intentions are not enough. Careful and independent scrutiny adds needed accountability to the risk-benefit calculation. “[T]here should first be a determination of the validity of the presuppositions of the research; then the nature, probability and magnitude of risk should be distinguished with as much clarity as possible.”Footnote 49 A key goal of this process is not merely to prevent unethical experiments from occurring, but also to inform the design of the research in order to minimize the potential for harm and maximize the benefits for those involved.

In this case, a more gradual, careful rollout should have preceded a neighborhood-wide implementation. Water officials should have identified, at the outset, that the technology they sought to implement needed to be field-tested to ensure its safety in the context of acute poverty. They might have first tried the technology in their own offices or homes, to become familiar with its limitations and potential risks (such as device malfunction). The experimental design should also have been informed by research studying current water use patterns in the community. The trial should have started with a restriction at 30 kL and worked gradually downward toward the target of 6 kL, watching for problems along the way. Each home should have been provided with an emergency water supply in case of device failure. Study participants might have been given cell phones so that they could easily report any urgent problems they experienced. Early participants should have been provided with a supply of tokens, so they would not have to use scarce resources in order to participate in the study.

Another critical safeguard is the participants’ ability to end their participation in the experiment, which is relevant to both freedom of consent and minimization of harm. Johannesburg Water should have designed pipes to permit either prepaid or conventional service, at the option of the consumer. This would have secured the exit option and the ability to quickly respond to problems. Had this level of care been put into the Phiri experiment, well-meaning persons at Johannesburg Water and the City of Johannesburg would have been better able to anticipate and manage the risks created by prepaid meters.

D Justice: Selection of Experimental Subjects

The third and final Belmont principle is justice. “The principle of justice gives rise to moral requirements that there be fair procedures and outcomes in the selection of research subjects.”Footnote 50 The risks of experimentation should not be placed disproportionately upon stigmatized or disadvantaged persons, nor upon persons who already bear great burdens. Where an experiment is conducted on a population of vulnerable persons – such as children, racial or linguistic minorities, or the very poor – careful scrutiny is required to ensure that they are not involved solely because they are easier to manipulate.Footnote 51 The potential benefits to society cannot be used to justify the risks to individuals directly involved. “In applying and advancing scientific knowledge, medical practice and associated technologies, human vulnerability should be taken into account. Individuals and groups of special vulnerability should be protected and the personal integrity of such individuals respected.”Footnote 52

Phiri was a community of families already facing massive burdens of poverty, unemployment, and extremely poor health. They should not have been also asked to face the burden of piloting a new and risky technology. The principle of justice would have been advanced by initially testing the technology in middle-class neighborhoods with high levels of education and English fluency. Those users would have been in a better position to cope with and report problems. Eventually, the technology would also need to be tested for safety in the specific social context of poverty, where it was intended to be used. At this stage, the study should not have been designed to involve more people than was necessary. Families with pregnant women, young children, and significant health problems should not have been included in the first wave of experimentation with the devices.

More broadly, we should also ask whether the principle of justice was honored not just in how the technology was field-tested, but also in the plan for its normal use. In litigation, the City of Johannesburg emphasized the public necessity of water conservation. Was it just for the burden of water conservation to be placed upon the extremely poor? If coercive measures were truly necessary to limit water usage, surely they were all the more necessary in affluent homes with much higher water usage per capita. Perhaps policy-makers chose to place this burden upon the poor and socially marginalized residents of Phiri because they were less likely to effectively complain and resist. Or perhaps the need for water conservation was a pretense all along, and the real need was simply to increase monetary recovery. The principle of justice would urge this to be accomplished by charging higher rates in affluent neighborhoods rather than squeezing additional payments from the very poor.

V Conclusion

The Mazibuko water dispute highlights the harm that even innocent-seeming technologies can do in the context of a power disparity between designers and users. From beginning to end, this problematic technology was controlled by a powerful institution that designed and implemented it to serve its own purposes, with little regard for the wishes of the vulnerable people subjected to it. The result was a series of decisions about implementation that resulted in serious harm to human dignity, health, and life.

Despite the country’s having one of the most rights-protective constitutions in the world, South Africa’s Constitutional Court felt unable to remedy this harm within the framework of the right to water. Reframing the facts of this case through the lens of the right to science, however, puts things in a very different perspective. The state is no longer engaged in a difficult process of progressive realization of socioeconomic rights, which courts are arguably ill-suited to second-guess. Instead, the state is more clearly seen to be actively violating the human rights of its citizens through its own reckless actions.

The implementation of a new, unproven, and potentially harmful technology calls for special ethical and legal safeguards to prevent abuse and harm. Even in jurisdictions where the right to science is not explicitly recognized, the framework of human rights safeguards as protection against problematic technologies still works. South African lawyers, for instance, might assert the right to freedom and security of persons, which is constitutionally defined to include the right “not to be subjected to medical or scientific experiments without their informed consent.”Footnote 53 This could then be interpreted by South African courts with reference to international practice and norms related to science, such as the Belmont Report and the Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights.

Courts of law are well positioned to adjudicate human rights violations within this framework. This approach does not require courts to set minimum standards for technical performance or to reach the conclusion that a particular technology does or does not violate human rights. Instead, it asks courts to do something that is uniquely within their institutional competence: to evaluate the sufficiency of procedural safeguards. The Belmont principles offer a framework for defining the procedural rights that must be upheld when people are subjected to unproven and potentially harmful technologies, in order to prevent abuse and minimize harm. Where these procedural rights are not respected, a court might either order a technological experiment to be suspended or require specific new safeguards, such as improved consent procedures, special protections for vulnerable populations, or the freedom to opt out. A court might also order financial compensation, a formal apology, or other remedies to rectify past harm. Where the evidence demonstrates a propensity for repeated violations, a court could mandate human rights training or the creation of an ethical review board. These measures might also be stipulated by means of a settlement negotiated between the parties.

A central function of ethical scrutiny of human subjects research is to provide external oversight over potentially harmful action before it takes place. This can help to guard against conflicts of interest, where a particular researcher or agency may be insufficiently concerned with the impact on individuals involved because of their own interest in seeing the project through. Yet an equally important function of ethical review is to encourage researchers to be self-policing, in order to sensitize them to their professional duty to protect their subjects’ interests and encourage them to design research protocols to minimize the potential for harm. Had the Johannesburg authorities subjected their plans for the Phiri trial of prepaid meters to an ethical evaluation of this sort, they would likely have chosen to redesign the technology, policy, and procedures, avoiding significant harm in the process.

The introduction of unproven and potentially dangerous technologies, whether formally conceptualized as research or not, should be subjected to similar safeguards. Individuals subjected to such technologies without their consent should be able to seek redress in a court of law. That court should consider whether the technology’s introduction was undertaken with appropriate consideration for human rights, in the form of procedural protections such as informed consent, risk-benefit analysis, and concern for vulnerable populations. Legal accountability along these lines would focus the attention of public interest advocates, lawmakers, bureaucrats, and corporations on the adoption of appropriate safeguards to minimize risks arising from the introduction of unproven and potentially harmful technologies. The possibility of legal liability would incentivize desirable internal caution. The same principles provide the framework for exercising that self-scrutiny within corporations and administrative agencies, as part of policy and technological design.

3 Climate Change, Human Rights, and Technology Transfer Normative Challenges and Technical Opportunities

Dalindyebo Shabalala
I Introduction

This chapter will review the broad strategy to link human rights and climate change, focusing specifically on how well the strategy works to strengthen obligations on developed countries to transfer technology that can reduce or mitigate the effects of increased carbon emissions. Elements of this strategy include regulatory action such as exceptions to patent protection, performance and technology transfer requirements for investments, compulsory licensing, price controls, and other measuresFootnote 1 to make climate technologies available and affordable for the populations that need them most. The chapter posits that the state-centered “development” approach that has dominated both economic development and climate discourse to date has failed to provide a sufficient foundation for realistically addressing the issue of technology transfer.Footnote 2

This chapter argues that the human rights approach solves two key problems that the development framework does not. First, it enables differentiation to take place, not between states, but between more vulnerable and less vulnerable populations within countries. It thus enables a focus on the most vulnerable populations, and in doing so also provides a basis for limiting the scope and nature of the demand for technologies to address climate change. Second, by limiting the scope of needed technologies, a human rights approach makes it more likely that such technologies will be made available to populations in need. If they are not, and lower-resource governments must act to secure climate change mitigation technologies for their citizens, the human rights approach will limit the grounds upon which actors in developed countries can challenge these decisions.

The United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC), ratified in 1992, is the international treaty framework that governs global efforts to combat climate change. This treaty uses a state-centered development framework for its legal and political framework of duties and rights,Footnote 3 with the unit of analysis being the state for both climate mitigationFootnote 4 and adaptation. The 1997 Kyoto Protocol governs the UNFCCC States Parties’ legal obligation to limit greenhouse gas GHG emissions as measured at the economy level.Footnote 5 The UNFCCC also creates a state-to-state obligation to provide technological and financial support for climate change mitigation and adaptation.Footnote 6

The development approach embodied in the UNFCCC aggregates needs and achievements at the national level rather than focusing on various strata of society that often do not evenly embody the risks and benefits of technological, social, and environmental change. Cost-benefit calculations can end up obfuscating the losses suffered by some portion of the population by counting the benefits to other portions of the population against them. This is particularly problematic from a human rights perspective when the portion of the population that suffers the loss is already disadvantaged while the portion that benefits is already privileged.

A human rights approach ensures that the individual rather than the nation as a whole is the primary beneficiary of actions that include technology transfer. It strengthens the fairness claim from both sides: developing countries can make a strong claim that any action they take is in the interests of specific vulnerable populations, and that they are not engaging in pure protectionist mercantilism or industrial policy favoring well-connected industrial actors. Developed countries providing financial and technological support can insist that this support be targeted primarily at vulnerable populations, making it easier to justify the spending to their citizens.

The effectiveness of this fairness claim is directly linked to the instrumental effect of a human rights approach. The human rights approach shifts away from the question of state-to-state obligations and instead asks the more direct question about who within each country should be the recipient of technology transfer aimed at fulfilling rights. This has several effects. Most importantly, it removes the danger of cost-benefit calculations that try to aggregate gains and allow particular individuals or groups to be sacrificed for the sake of the general welfare. It also removes from the set of options those that would more negatively impact vulnerable populations. A classic example of this is hydroelectric dam construction that involves the forced resettlement and land dispossession of marginalized communities. While the electricity generated may be cleaner and result in lower emissions, thus meeting the country’s obligations in the UNFCCC, the displacement and dispossession inflicts irreversible harms on those affected by it.

The human rights approach solves another core problem in climate technology transfer: how to limit the scope of technologies for which action is needed and justified. At the aggregate level, the scope of technologies necessary to achieve climate mitigation and adaptation within the necessary time frames is enormous. There is no global or UNFCCC coordinating principle or mechanism for identifying and prioritizing technology needs in developing countries. This leaves decisions about which technologies to pursue at the discretion of demandeur developing countries, and the decision about whether to provide technology at the discretion of developed countries. This chapter argues that by focusing on impacts as felt by individuals on the ground, a human rights approach provides such a mechanism for prioritizing technologies needed to address climate impacts.Footnote 7

The next section of this chapter describes the limits of the development framework, tracing it from its roots in postcolonial demands for a New International Economic Order (NIEO) to the bargains embodied in multilateral environmental treaties. The subsequent section describes the two key problems posed by the approach within the UNFCCC: the fairness issue and the scope of technologies. The final section discusses the ways in which a human rights approach could solve some of the problems inherent in the development approach.

II The Limits of the Development Approach
A Modernization and Development

The increase in GHG emissions since the advent of the industrial revolution can largely be attributed to the economic activity of what we now call developed countries,Footnote 8 which are somewhat coextensive with political groupings such as the G7 and the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD).Footnote 9 The definition of this group of early industrializers significantly overlaps with the colonial powers that dominated Africa, Asia, and South America through the middle of the twentieth century.

This chapter makes significant claims around differential treatment of populations in developing countries. There is a long history of similarly categorizing nations, whatever the limitations of such schema may be. At the height of the Cold War, for instance, public discourse in journalism and political science divided states into the First, Second, and Third Worlds.Footnote 10 The Third World referred to those countries that remained colonized, or had recently been decolonized and remained on the periphery of world economic affairs, consisting of all of Africa, all of Asia (sometimes including Japan), and all of South America.Footnote 11 Second World referred to the specific group of Eastern European and Soviet-orbit countries, and First World referred primarily to the industrialized countries of the Western Hemisphere, encompassing Western Europe and the United States, but also Australia and New Zealand. In economics, the use of terms such as “industrialized,” “industrializing,” and “nonindustrialized” became more prevalent in the late 1970s and early 1980s, given the need for more objective descriptors of the economic status (as opposed to the geopolitical status) of different countries.Footnote 12

This chapter traces the trajectory of the shift toward differentiation within and between developing countries. The term “developing country” fully came to the fore in 1974 with the publication of the United Nations Declaration for a NIEO.Footnote 13 The Declaration did not define the term “developing country” except to frame it with regard to those countries that had received their freedom from colonialism.Footnote 14 The term “developing country” has now come to be used in conjunction with two other terms: “developed country” and “economy in transition.” Usually, within the category of developing economies there is also a subset of least-developed countries (LDCs). LDCs are the only set of countries for which there is a legal, international definition within the UN system, under the responsibility of the UN General Assembly Committee for Development Policy.Footnote 15 LDC status does not legally require states to provide special measures to support these countries either bilaterally or multilaterally, but the clear demarcation and process makes it possible to do so where countries and international organizations wish.Footnote 16

The broader category of “developing countries,” in contrast, has no legal basis as such, but nonetheless is commonly used in discourse about international political economy in the United Nations and other international organizations. The Bretton Woods institutions (the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund) recognize the existence of the category of developing countries, primarily through differentiated status for concessionary lending for what it defines as lower-income countries, blended lending for lower-middle-income countries, and nonconcessionary lending for upper-middle-income countries.Footnote 17 The World Trade Organization (WTO) also recognizes the distinction between developed and developing countries, categories into which countries self-select.Footnote 18

In the UN General Assembly, developing countries self-define as the Group of 77 plus China. The G77 was established at the first meeting of the UN Conference on Trade and Development in 1964 and originally consisted of seventy-seven developing countries, defined as such by a joint declaration.Footnote 19 The membership is now 133 self-selected countries, primarily former colonies.Footnote 20 Membership in the G77 provides no specific legal status in the United Nations or other organizations, but provides a mechanism for this group of countries to make demands on “developed” countries on the basis of justice, fairness, and other principles, and to use their common weight to try to influence outcomes in international negotiations and decision-making bodies.

The G77 negotiates as a group to represent common interests in several organizations, such as the UNFCCC,Footnote 21 but does not serve as the sole organizational mechanism for developing countries. Within the broader UN system, countries are also categorized using the Human Development Index (HDI), labeled as having a low, medium, high, or very high level of human development.Footnote 22 The various methods of categorizing countries have significant overlap. The nations that rank lowest on the HDI tend to be LDCs, while those that rank in the middle of the HDI tend to be the same ones that lie between the least and most economically developed. A high or very high human development score tends to be associated with a high level of economic development.Footnote 23

The existence of intermediate categories of developing countries, such as “emerging economies,” “economies in transition,” “middle-income countries,” and BRICS,Footnote 24 is more than just an attempt to do a better descriptive job. Rather, it poses a challenge to the very concept of a cohesive set of developing countries with common interests largely defined against the interests of developed countries. The differentiation plays out in unique ways in various international fora. In this chapter, when discussing a specific forum, I will specify the ways in which it makes the distinction, but will generally refer to the broad categories of developed and developing countries.

In the WTO regime, specific differential treatment for developing countries is generally called special and differential (S&D) treatment.Footnote 25 S&D policy usually provides developing countries (mostly former colonies) more time and financial assistance to comply with international economic obligations. S&D treatment is accorded to developing countries under several of the WTO-covered agreements.Footnote 26 The WTO officially recognizes LDCs as a group within it based on the UN Committee on Development Policy List,Footnote 27 and these countries are entitled to additional concessions.Footnote 28 The justification for S&D treatment is that these countries are saddled by the ongoing and pernicious aftereffects of colonialism, which continue to retard their development. This policy is based in part on fairness claims; i.e., that differently situated and less capable countries should not be subject to the same obligations in international arenas as developed countries. It is also based on justice; i.e., that developing countries are owed some form of restitution and aid because developed countries dominate the current economic landscape based on their past success exploiting the natural resources and populations of their colonial holdings.

The demand for policies giving special treatment to developing countries was most strongly expressed in the NIEO.Footnote 29 The NIEO drew on traditional modernization theory,Footnote 30 which viewed industrialization as a stepwise process by which countries moved up the value chain from primary commodity producers to value-added manufactured product producers, resulting in a “modern” industrialized society. A key to modernization was integrating technology into production processes and relinquishing traditional extractive modes of economic activity. At the same time, dependency theory also gained traction as a critique of the international economic system, arguing that developed countries had deliberately deindustrialized their former colonies in order to ensure access to raw materials and ready markets for their own finished industrial products.Footnote 31

These twin economic theories/ideologies framed the NIEO. On the one hand, modernization theory was an argument for access to similar opportunities to develop along the same paths and using the same policies historically available to developed economies, without having to adhere to newer rules and having limitations imposed. On the other hand, dependency theory was an argument for restitution for the deliberate damage caused by developed economies during their periods of colonial and postcolonial exploitation.

These twin strains can be seen in the text of the NIEO, which, among other things, demands sovereignty over all natural resources and the right to nationalize, free from external coercion by other states;Footnote 32 the right to restitution and compensation for colonialism;Footnote 33 fair and equitable pricing of raw minerals and resources in international markets;Footnote 34 special and differential, or preferential, treatment for developing countries in all international economic institutions; and, most importantly: “Giving to the developing countries access to the achievements of modern science and technology, and promoting the transfer of technology and the creation of indigenous technology for the benefit of the developing countries in forms and in accordance with procedures which are suited to their economies.”Footnote 35

This demand for transfer of technology as a means of achieving development was central to the vision of the NIEO, yet there is still no universally recognized or legally enforceable definition for what technology transfer is or what form it must take. In this chapter, the term “technology transfer” refers to the flow of technological goods and knowledge across borders.Footnote 36 Transfer happens when technology and associated know-how are first transported from one country to another and then adopted by public or private firms. The technology can either be built into the means of production (i.e., industrial or economic processes), or built into the products and services themselves. The clearest and most well-articulated provisions for technology transfer in the environmental arena can be found in Chapter 34 of Agenda 21 of the 1992 Rio Declaration on Environment and Development.Footnote 37 The language in Agenda 21 has been a guide for the kinds of actions expected of developed countries in multilateral environmental treaties, wherein developed countries agree to provide technology transfer in exchange for developing country participation in efforts to mitigate climate change. The NIEO vision lines up with the broader approach of Agenda 21, focusing on free or low-cost access to technology and relaxation of intellectual property restrictions.

The NIEO vision has been consistently resisted by developed countries as an imposition on the legitimate intellectual property rights of their corporations, especially in international fora such as the United Nations Conference on Trade and Development (UNCTAD)Footnote 38 and the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO). That resistance led to the failure to adopt the Draft Code of Conduct of International Transfer of TechnologyFootnote 39 in 1985, despite formal negotiations that had been ongoing since 1976.Footnote 40 That resistance also resulted in the failure of WIPO to adopt true S&D treatment provisions after the minimal achievements of the 1967 revisions of the Berne ConventionFootnote 41 and the Paris ConventionFootnote 42 in Stockholm.

By the time the 1971 revisions to the Berne and Paris Conventions were being considered, developing countries had become the majority of members in WIPO and could block any further adoption of stronger intellectual property protections that did not take their concerns into account. This majority of developing countriesFootnote 43 influenced internal processes in most UN-affiliated international institutions, which operated on a one-country, one-vote structure. Developing countries could block further decision-making, but they could not impose their will on developed countries, because those countries would simply not negotiate or refuse to join treaties on economic matters proposed by developing countries. This developing country veto blocked any further norm-setting in WIPO. It also meant that developed countries had few venues for further development of norms on intellectual property other than bilateral mechanisms.

Developed countries retained primary decision-making power in the Bretton Woods institutions (the World Bank and the IMF) and the General Agreement on Trade and Tariffs (GATT), however, where clout was determined by levels of financial contribution. As these institutions gained prominence in the 1980s, the desire for access to the low trade tariffs enjoyed by developed country GATT members was a key impetus for developing countries to participate in the Uruguay Round of negotiations that led to the creation of the World Trade OrganizationFootnote 44 and resulted in the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS).Footnote 45

S&D treatment was enshrined in TRIPS, which laid out minimum standards for intellectual property protections in all countries but was limited to additional transition time from old rules to new ones, primarily for the subgroup of LDCs.Footnote 46 TRIPS provided for longer transition periods, but only a five-year period was provided for most developing countries.Footnote 47 In order to extend patent protection to products in addition to processes, countries such as India had only a ten-year transition. Only the LDCs received a full transition period of ten years for the entire agreement; this period has since been extended twice.Footnote 48

TRIPS represents an almost complete transition in international economic policy from a system that provided some, albeit limited, recognition of fairness and justice claims by developing countries to one that now largely elides such differences in favor of harmonization. The dispute settlement mechanism at the WTO, which provides for financial sanctions for noncompliance, poses some of the strongest restrictions on policy discretion that developing countries have experienced since their independence. There remains some room for taking action around compulsory licensing, but the use of historically available measures to enable technology transfer – e.g., exclusions from patentability, local working requirements, exceptions to patent rights – was severely curtailed by TRIPS.Footnote 49

Nevertheless, the demand for and discourse around S&D treatment have permeated other regimes in international law and remain a potent force in the environmental arena. The next section discusses how this development framework has also led to an impasse in international environmental negotiations.

B Environment, Development, and Climate Change
1 Differentiation, Fairness, and Justice Claims in the UNFCCC Framework

Differential categorization of developing countries – whether they are “middle income,” “emerging,” or “in transition” – is the backdrop for current debates regarding which countries are obligated to immediately take the first steps to address climate change and which should be given a grace period to start this process and be entitled to financial assistance from developed countries to meet their obligations. In that debate, “middle income,” “emerging,” “industrializing,” or “newly industrialized” economies like India, China, Mexico, Argentina, Brazil, South Africa, Taiwan, and Singapore are now seen by many economically dominant countries as viable competitors in the international economy rather than worthy recipients of aid and support. While this erosion of concern is almost complete in international economic law and institutions, a similar situation in environmental law, and climate change law in particular, is still in its early stages.

The UNFCCC was built on the concept of common but differentiated responsibilities (CBDR), under which developed countries have had the burden to act first and most, as the acknowledged contributors to the problem, for all but the last two decades of the twentieth century.Footnote 50 That division is specifically established in the UNFCCC classification of countries between Annex I and non-Annex I countries. Annex I countries includes the OECD countries plus twelve economies in transition.Footnote 51

However, unlike the pure fairness and justice claims to differential treatment in the WTO setting that were based on colonial exploitation, CBDR also had another component – a transactional one. Threats to the international commons, such as climate change (or chlorofluorocarbon emissions damaging the ozone layer), require common action. The threats affect developed and developing economies alike, although with some greater impacts in developing countries due to lower resilience and adaptive capacity. There are, however, considerable opportunity costs associated with climate change mitigation. Differentiated treatment was needed to incentivize developing countries to do their part.

If a country avoids the use of a specific technology or product or reduces its GHG emissions, that imposes a cost on the country’s development by forcing it to develop or adopt different products, technologies, and economic behaviors. Developed countries that wished to address climate change had to convince developing countries to participate in a process under which they would commit to reduce their emissions even when it cost them in economic terms or slowed their rate of development. This required a carrot: financial assistance to deal with adjustment costs and technology, at low or zero cost, to enable them to reduce their own emissions and adapt to climate impacts. This bargain is reflected in Article 4, which establishes a series of commitments that distinguish between Annex I and non-Annex I countries as well as between developed and developing countries more generally.Footnote 52

On technology transfer in particular, Articles 4.1(c), 4.3, 4.5, and 4.7 establish S&D treatment for developing countries. Article 4.2 establishes commitments that only apply to “developed countries and others in Annex I.” The UNFCC also establishes a group of Annex II countries that have financial and technological support obligations on top of mitigation commitments under Article 4 generally. These countries are the traditional OECD group of early industrializers.Footnote 53

The CBDR framework, however, has proven to be unworkable within the current international political climate, with the emergence of a category of “intermediate” developing countries not identified in the original UNFCCC. In particular, while historically emissions have been largely due to developed countries, developing countries like China, India, Brazil, and Mexico have begun to catch up, and China has become the largest source of emissions at present.Footnote 54 These are also countries that have become significant trading competitors for developed countries.Footnote 55 Despite large domestic populations that remain in poverty, the aggregate economic strength of these countries is such that they are no longer viewed by developed countries as having any right to financial and technological support.Footnote 56 Their emissions also erode the argument that they should delay taking mitigation action, as they continue to increase their share of emissions. This was already the case at the time the Kyoto Protocol was signed in 1997. It is worth noting that the US Senate refused to ratify it precisely because countries like China were excluded from quantified emissions-reduction obligations as a developing country in the UNFCCC.Footnote 57

The transaction frame has not been successful, however, for a different reason: because developing countries believe that developed countries have not provided sufficient levels of finance and technology transfer.Footnote 58 This has created a chicken-or-egg problem for mitigation action by those intermediate developing countries that may be in a position to take on more obligations. These countries are driven by several concerns. The first is the perception that, until relatively recently, developed countries had failed to meet their obligations under the Kyoto Protocol to reduce their emissions.Footnote 59 The second is the perception that developed countries have failed to meet their obligations to provide financial and technological support to prepare them to take on obligations.Footnote 60 These perceived failures make intermediate developing countries less willing to take on obligations, while hardening other developing countries against any measures to weaken the differentiation between developed and developing countries in the UNFCCC framework. This conflict came to a head during the Bali Conference of the Parties in December 2007. It led developing countries to refuse to agree to negotiations for any new commitment period in the Kyoto Protocol or any new agreement that included developing country emissions-reduction commitments.Footnote 61

The issue of differentiation and the push to have developing countries take on measurable, reportable, and verifiable emissions-reduction obligations has been at the center of climate negotiations since the post-Kyoto discussions. The end result of that process was the 2015 Paris Agreement,Footnote 62 which significantly erodes the distinction between developed and developing countries compared to the UNFCCC and the Kyoto Protocol. Article 1 notes that all parties are required to provide voluntary nationally determined contributions (NDCs),Footnote 63 a major departure from past agreements. Each country determines for itself the extent of action it will take, instead of the obligation being tied to country classifications. This solution was viewed as necessary to bring countries such as the United States into the agreement by addressing the major complaints about the Kyoto Protocol: the exclusion of major developing country economies from emissions-reduction obligations and the imposition of stronger measurable, reportable, and verifiable emissions reductions on UNFCCC Annex I countries.

The agreement does recognize in several instances that developing countries may make slower progress toward emissions reductionsFootnote 64 and that some support will be needed to ensure their implementation of commitments,Footnote 65 but the broader obligation to commit to emissions reductions applies to all parties. Nevertheless, Article 4(4) notes that developed countries are to express their NDCs as quantified economy-wide emissions reductions, whereas developing countries are only required to provide enhanced action. Additionally, Article 4(5) reiterates that developing countries should be supported. In terms of financial and technological support, Articles 9 and 10 state that developed countries remain obligated to provide support to developing countries.Footnote 66

Nothing in the Paris Agreement necessarily redefines what constitutes a developing or developed country, but it does abandon the framework of Annex I, Annex II, and non-Annex I countries that previously framed obligations. It is difficult to escape the conclusion that this erosion of differentiation may force more capable developing countries to take on more concrete obligations even while they contain significant vulnerable populations. The majority of people in developing countries, even intermediate countries such as China and India, live in climate-vulnerable environments and ecosystems.Footnote 67 Coastal and island states risk sea-level rises leading to flooding, salinization of arable land, and increased vulnerability to extreme weather events.Footnote 68 For North African and West African states, the risks are associated with encroachment of the Sahara Desert and increased frequency and severity of drought events.Footnote 69 For central and eastern Africa, shifts in disease bands, as well as increased floods and droughts, may lead to more hunger and illness. For countries on the Asian subcontinent, such as India and Bangladesh, the melting of glaciers and the unpredictability of monsoons are likely to lead to increased coastal flooding and shortages of drinking water.Footnote 70

Climate vulnerabilities are complicated by a lack of resources needed to prepare for and adapt to changes in climate. For developing countries, the costs of paying for activities needed to address climate change are astronomical and likely to be crippling to their development.Footnote 71 The current development framework represented in the UNFCCC approach provides little or no means by which differentiation can be made between newly industrialized countries and other developing countries. This erosion of differentiation means that newly industrialized countries will be increasingly asked to make greater sacrifices despite their lack of financial capacity and large populations living at the bottom of the HDI. Absent a fundamental realignment of interests, the CBDR framework has left countries mired in this no-man’s land, where both the fairness and justice claims of developing countries to financial and technological support and the claims on them to take action equal to that of developed countries remain weak.

In the last section of this chapter, I discuss how a human rights approach may enable a way out by refocusing the justice and fairness claims within the countries rather than state-to-state. In the next section, however, I discuss the second major problem posed by the CBDR/development approach: that it is overly broad in the scope of technologies that are identified for technology transfer.

2 The CBDR/Development Approach and the Scope of Technologies

The Earth continues to experience record-breaking temperatures caused by increased atmospheric concentrations of carbon dioxide and other GHGs.Footnote 72 To keep warming well below 2 degrees, and to retain the possibility of stabilizing at the safe level of 1.5 degrees above preindustrial levels, it may be necessary for global emissions to peak by 2020.Footnote 73 Projections suggest that past emissions mean the Earth is already locked into a baseline increase in temperature that makes some impacts unavoidable by 2100.Footnote 74 None of the associated costs of climate change between now and 2050 are likely to be avoided because of this lock-in.Footnote 75

The timing of impacts is crucial to determine who, both between and within countries, is likely to be impacted first, as well as which technologies are going to be most effective at addressing the mitigation and adaptation needs of those populations. That calculus of which technologies to transfer and who they should benefit differs depending on whether harm is viewed at the aggregate level or is based on the needs of the most vulnerable.

A CBDR/development framework begins with the question of what the state, at the aggregate level, must do to meet its adaptation and mitigation needs. For mitigation, this is determined by when the country will need to begin to lower emissions (generally at some point between 2015 and 2020), implying a need for almost all currently available technologies aimed at reducing emissions most efficiently and quickly. A cursory glance at the details of the implied technologies shows a large, unwieldy list of specific technologies.Footnote 76

In energy, for example, the speed and scale of action required would seem to select for energy projects that are energy-efficient and easily and quickly deployable, and that target those countries currently consuming high rates of GHG-intensive energy sources. While these will not always be the largest-scale projects, this approach will tend to select for the kinds of projects that generate large amounts of energy per site, that can feed into the current grid, and that supply heavy industrial and urban users. This tendency can be seen in the discussion and projections of the International Energy Agency, which focuses on large-scale carbon capture and storage and nuclear generation.Footnote 77

In adaptation, the challenge is quite clear, from sea-level rise to changes in the hydrological cycle.Footnote 78 When focusing on the state level, as the UNFCCC does, adaptation requires actions like “strengthening institutional capacities and enabling environments for adaptation, including for climate-resilient development and vulnerability reduction”Footnote 79 or “[b]uilding resilience of socio-economic and ecological systems, including through economic diversification and sustainable management of natural resources.”Footnote 80

There are few, if any, references to differentiation of populations within individual countries, and little focus on those most vulnerable to climate change and thus most in need of adaptation. The UNFCCC provides funding at the level of the aggregate need of each country and does not require states to prioritize the needs of the most vulnerable in the disbursement of this money. Thus, in the Green Climate Fund, the primary financing entity within the UNFCCC, for example, funding is generally focused on high-impact, systemic-oriented programs and projects.Footnote 81 Vulnerability is primarily discussed at the level of the state.Footnote 82 In the illustrative indicators for the impact of its adaptation programs, there are only two criteria that look to the extent of impact on the most vulnerable populations, one defining reduced beneficiaries and the other defining it in terms of “enhancing adaptive capacity and resilience … focusing particularly on the most vulnerable populations or groups.”Footnote 83

While nothing requires countries to focus on the most vulnerable, the formulation of national adaptation plans may involve such prioritization or focus on the most vulnerable, as noted in the UNFCC’s Technical Guidelines for the National Adaptation Plan Process.Footnote 84

The Adaptation Fund, an independent financing entity of the UNFCCC established under the Kyoto Protocol, is a “direct access” fund, which means that few or no conditions are placed on countries’ priorities and none are required as long as these are carried out by an accredited national implementing entity.Footnote 85 Nothing in the Adaptation Fund policies requires a focus on the most vulnerable populations within countries in order to receive funding.Footnote 86 As such, no distinction is made between the hypothetical need to ensure that beach erosion does not destroy the second holiday homes of the wealthy (including a significant percentage of foreigners) in Cape Town, South Africa, versus the need to set up flood defenses for riverside villages in Kwazulu-Natal. The Paris Agreement refers only to “vulnerable parties.”Footnote 87

Adaptation presents a complex challenge that involves a network of existing capacity and vulnerability, with impacts and adaptations to impacts taking place within a network of cofactors such as poverty, population shifts, migration patterns, and changing land use.Footnote 88 The Stern Review, commissioned by the UK government in 2006 to examine the economics of climate change in order to inform the government’s policy positions within the EU and international negotiations,Footnote 89 suggested that the key mechanisms for addressing adaptation were the same as those for generating economic wealth more generally. The report argued for prioritizing infrastructure, technology, information, knowledge, and skills,Footnote 90 especially in domains like agriculture, which makes up the majority of economic activity in most developing countries (up to 64 percent participation in South Asia and sub-Saharan Africa) and is very sensitive to climate variability.Footnote 91 A stable and sustainably growing framework for agricultural production and distribution is necessary to reduce vulnerability and enable adaptive capacity in developing countries.Footnote 92 Health interventions to deal with chronic diseases (both communicable and noncommunicable) in developing countries are also necessary to reduce vulnerability and adaptive capacity.Footnote 93 This implicates general health infrastructure and health management systems, but also the opportunity costs associated with the prices of medical products, devices, and services.

The breadth of the development approach points to a crucial weakness: under a development framework, technology transfer for adaptation covers an extremely broad range of technologies, aimed at generating economic growth and increasing the fungible wealth that enables resilience and increases adaptive capacity. Viewed in this way, the adaptation need is indistinguishable from the development need framed under the NIEO; i.e., developing countries need technology in order to engage in modernization and industrialization. From this view, the adaptation challenge is essentially a development challengeFootnote 94 and covers all sectors of technology relevant to ensuring rapid, non–fossil-fuel-dependent economic development. This makes the demand for access to all these technologies equally broad and limitless, and, within the context of the CBDR framework, imposes such a cost burden on developed countries that it fails in the current international framework.

As a result, industrialized countries are increasingly reluctant to fund adaptation, because they fear they are simply adding to their overseas development assistance (ODA) obligation without really addressing climate change-related issues. Further, the lack of a clear dividing line between adaptation and development makes it difficult to hold industrialized countries accountable for their climate change obligations, since they can simply point to existing ODA as fulfilling their UNFCCC obligation to adapt.

III How Does a Human Rights Approach Solve the Problems Posed by the CBDR/Development Approach?

Having discussed the weakness of the common but differentiated responsibilities approach for fairness and justice claims and for delimiting the scope of technologies, this section discusses how taking a human rights approach can be used to address these weaknesses. As an initial step, I focus on a key element of the human rights approach: the requirement that states prioritize action on behalf of citizens whose rights are least fulfilled or most under threat.Footnote 95

Locating the right to development within the individual rather than the state has been central to a human rights-based approach to development.Footnote 96 The CBDR/development approach clearly does not focus on the fulfillment of individual human development, and primarily only acknowledges state interests in climate mitigation and adaptation.

This deficiency points us to the first step necessary for a human rights-based approach to climate change: the unit of climate impact analysis must be the individual and the community rather than the state. A rights-based approach is also helpful in the context of climate change, because it identifies both the developing country itself and other states in the international community as potential duty bearers with the obligation to provide for technology transfer.Footnote 97 In this chapter, I focus on those impacts that trigger a human rights claim against both the government of the developing country where the harmed individual resides and the developed country that fails to provide technological or financial support to prevent or address climate impacts.

A human rights approach also provides a basis for prioritizing policy choices that benefit vulnerable individuals even over other choices that might be more beneficial in the aggregate.Footnote 98 Aggregate data does not reveal how the benefits of development are distributed; a human rights approach, in contrast, attends to these distributional questions.Footnote 99 Finally, a human rights approach aims not just to identify rights that are threatened by climate change or to specify duty holders, but to further argue that the need to protect rights requires access to technologies to address the harm.

A human rights framework for responding to climate change begins with an analysis of the rights that are negatively impacted by climate change. Thus, the first limiting principle of a human rights approach is that it is defined by the very specific suite of internationally recognized, legally cognizable rights. These rights are enshrined in international human rights treaties, including the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) and the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), as they have been elaborated by human rights institutions, and, where appropriate, judicial and quasi-judicial mechanisms. In this, I take a conservative approach that does not rely on newer or derivative “rights,” such as the right to development or the right to energy. My concern here is to evaluate and elaborate on how a relatively uncontroversial reading of traditionalFootnote 100 human rights obligations can serve to: 1) strengthen fairness and justice claims to technology transfer; and 2) enable limitations on the scope and prioritization of technologies for technology transfer.

The human rights framework provides a very circumscribed justification for claims of access to mitigation technologies.Footnote 101 By focusing on impacts, we inevitably focus on adaptation. This, however, is a feature, not a “bug” of the approach. Without a focus on impacts, the causal link to states’ obligations is missing, or at least attenuated.

A Which Rights Are Impacted by Climate Change?

The extensive academic literature has linked climate impacts to the following key rights established in the Universal Declaration on Human Rights, the ICESCR, and the ICCPRFootnote 102: the right to life, the right to health (and to a healthy environment), the right to water, and the right to food.

Rights to health and food are economic rights that are governed by the framework of “progressive realization.” Although a state has an obligation to fulfill these rights, progressive realization recognizes the reality of limited resources. States are not required to fulfill these rights immediately, but rather must make progress toward realizing them.Footnote 103 The framework of progressive realization has two components: the establishment of baselines or thresholds below which rights may not fall, and a general movement toward fulfillment of rights. The first requires an immediate focus on the most vulnerable populations to ensure that no absolute harm occurs, and a focus on other groups as resources permit.

The right to life, on the other hand, requires states to actively refrain from action that would cause death and to prevent relatively foreseeable deaths from actions by others or by nature. This implies a measure of prevention to mitigate the effects of disasters (human or natural) and an obligation to take action when such disasters strike, in order to reduce or prevent deaths. In the context of climate change, the majority of disaster events are water-based and relate to coastal risks, although major rain events occur inland as well. Additionally, drought events are related to famine conditions that would trigger obligations related to the right to life.

Article 12 of the ICESCR affords the right to the “highest attainable standard of physical and mental health.” In its General Comment 14,Footnote 104 the Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (CESCR), the body charged with receiving reports from states on their compliance with the treaty, defines health broadly. The key link to climate change impacts, as well as climate change vulnerability and adaptive capacity, is the idea that health includes the right to a healthy environment. Thus there are two levels at which links can be made: at the level of direct health effects, such as disease burdens, but also at the level of the underlying determinants of health.

At the level of direct health impacts, climate change will result in changes in precipitation patterns, the length of rainy seasons, and the length of warm seasons.Footnote 105 The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), for example, points to significant uncertainty regarding the increased frequency and intensity of diseases, due in large part to a lack of long-term epidemiological data.Footnote 106 The IPCC notes that disease incidence may be due to social changes resulting from climate change, such as migration and subsequent changes in population density. Nevertheless, the IPCC points to four major categories of health impactsFootnote 107: direct effects of heat or cold, vector-borne diseases, food- and water-borne diseases, and pollen- and dust-related diseases.

The right to water is not explicitly mentioned in the ICESCR. However, the CESCR has concluded that the right to water is implied in Article 11 as an aspect of the right to an adequate standard of living.Footnote 108 Climate is linked to the right to water in two ways. The first is that extreme weather events associated with climate change are likely to result in temporary but severe disruptions of water supply that deprive portions of the population of access to water. During an extreme weather or sea event, water supply can be cut off due to the malfunction of desalination plants, damage to rainwater collectors, or contamination of wells. The second linkage is a reduction in available freshwater and increased incidence of drought, as temperatures increase and surface moisture evaporates more quickly. The reduction in access to water due to climate change can be traced to increased glacial melt and a general reduction in the amount of water held in ice each winter season.Footnote 109 Such ice systems provide freshwater for much of the Indian subcontinent, for example. We can also expect increased intensity of droughts as well as expansion of dry areas.Footnote 110 These are impacts that are already being felt and are likely to increase in intensity through to 2050.Footnote 111

The right to food is addressed in a number of international human rights documents.Footnote 112 Food production, both plant and animal, is the primary source of GHG emissions in many nonindustrialized developing countries. Thus agricultural practices that involve fertilizers, soil-tilling methods, and bovine farming contribute to GHG emissions through nitrous oxide and methane release.Footnote 113 Deforestation to create more agricultural land also removes carbon sinks. On the other hand, food production is also one of the areas affected by increased dry areas and drought, as well as flooding. The loss of productive land may result in lower food production. For coastal lands, increased sea-related extreme weather events such as storm surges can also lead to the loss of cultivable land due to salination of the soil. In addition, changing weather patterns are affecting the lengths of growing seasons as well as humidity levels, soil acidity, and other factors. This can render existing plant varieties less productive.Footnote 114 Finally, the IPCC report also points to increased vulnerability to extreme drought events in the near term.Footnote 115

B Instrumental Approaches: Limiting the Scope of Technologies

Simply by describing human rights impacts on the most vulnerable populations within a country, we see a manageable set of technologies that might be needed to mitigate the effects of climate change. While the development approach to addressing adaptation is focused primarily on economic growth as a means of ensuring adaptive capacity, a human rights approach focuses the set of choices, narrowed down by: 1) identifying a specific set of beneficiaries within each country; and 2) selecting for specific types and categories of technology.

1 The Beneficiaries of Action

With respect to the beneficiaries of action, a human rights approach requires a focus primarily on the needs of the most vulnerable rather than those already well-off or capable of adapting.Footnote 116 This means that while middle-class residents in each country are clearly targets of mitigation and adaptation action, from a human rights perspective they are not the top priority.

In addressing, for example, the right to food, who, then, are the “most vulnerable” that the CESCR is concerned about and how does focusing on them limit the scope of technologies? A development approach has no specific mechanism for distributional concerns. At the aggregate level, a general focus on increasing food production encompasses technologies within the entire agricultural production and distribution chain. A human rights approach focuses on vulnerable populations in both rural and urban areas and can focus on specific technologies within the agricultural value chain. Looking first at rural populations of small-holder and subsistence farmers most vulnerable to hunger, the action would focus primarily on ensuring that subsistence farming remains viable and productive where drought or flood events increase. This means prioritizing small-hold farming methods and practices over large-scale industrial agriculture, which is already supported by the powerful multinational agribusiness industry.

However, given the increased urbanization that is likely to occur due to the displacement of rural populations by increased land stress (i.e., reductions in quality and availability) as a result of climate change, it will also be necessary for small-holder farmers to generate sufficient surpluses to feed those urbanized populations. This means focusing on transportation, distribution, and food storage systems. To the extent that those urban populations would need food, some form of more intensive agriculture may be needed, but a human rights approach would allow that only to the extent that it did not involve dispossession and displacement of small-holder and subsistence farmers.

2 The Selection of Human Rights-Appropriate Technologies

A human rights approach also directs the selection of technologies. Although human rights would not necessarily require any particular kind of technology, it would create a bias toward those technologies that were inexpensive, easily deployable by the government or market providers, and easily maintained by the target beneficiaries. This is a result of the need to address near-term impacts on vulnerable populations without significant purchasing power or adaptive capacity of their own.

However, relevant technologies would not be limited to basic or low-cost ones, but could involve sophisticated micro-grid applications or big data programs for weather monitoring linked to mobile telephony and Internet access. The key is accessibility and sustainability of the technologies for the most vulnerable, as compared to something like energy management software for household appliances, which is low-hanging fruit as far as mitigation measures are concerned.Footnote 117 The type of technology could shift depending on the nature of the right and the needs of the population. It may make sense for the state to prioritize sensor and data technology to keep track of rainfall in water-stressed areas in order to deliver on its obligation to fulfill the right to water. It also makes sense for the state to enable access by individuals and communities to specific water-purification technologies, such as water-purification tablets, that are easily deployable and usable in a sustained manner. Adopting this approach does not necessarily mean that states should neglect national-level infrastructure, but it does mean at least a partial prioritization of technologies that address harms to the most vulnerable populations, or at least ensuring that these needs are addressed concurrently with broader investments in infrastructure.

IV Conclusion

By refocusing the discourse away from the obligations of states to one another and toward the obligations of all states to vulnerable populations, a human rights approach can bypass the continuing impasse at the UNFCC on how developed and developing countries should be categorized and assigned obligations. This chapter describes the means by which developing countries can frame their adaptation action (and, secondarily, their mitigation action) to make a stronger claim on developed countries to assist them in meeting their human rights obligations to their vulnerable populations. This kind of framing has the potential to transform the discourse from a “donor” framework, in which developed countries provide technology at their discretion, if at all, to a “demandeur” framework, in which vulnerable citizens of developing countries can make direct claims to technologies in ways that developed countries may find more difficult to challenge on legal, political, or economic grounds.

4 Judging Bioethics and Human Rights

Thérèse Murphy
I Introduction

Bioethics is, without doubt, the premier mode of governing the biomedical and human life sciences and their technologies: sciences that “have ethics”Footnote 1 are widely lauded as good sciences – the epitome of responsible research and innovation. But international human rights law and practice also has something to say about science and technology, and about bioethics. There is, for instance, a European Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine, which has a preamble invoking “the need for international cooperation so that all humanity may enjoy the benefits of biology and medicine,” as well as a range of protocols on matters such as biomedical research, human cloning, and genetic testing.Footnote 2 There is also a Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights,Footnote 3 which is part of a series of UNESCO initiatives on science, technology, and rights.Footnote 4 And recently, the UN Special Rapporteur on cultural rights expressed the view that it is “essential” for the ethics codes of professional scientific organizations to be “explicitly informed by human rights.”Footnote 5

For me, the coexistence of bioethics and international human rights law and practice in governing the biomedical and life sciences and their technologies gives rise to two questions. First, how do bioethics and bioethicists see human rights in general, and international human rights law in particular? Second, how do human rights, and international human rights lawyers in particular, see bioethics? These questions, to be clear, are not about turf war or about acclaiming interdisciplinarity. They are about starting over, about engaging in fresh conversation between fields that have a history of shared interests but little in the way of mutual understanding.

Fresh conversation is made easier by fresh content. In this chapter, I suggest international human rights case law as a source of such content. I see its appeal as twofold. First, human rights case law focuses us on what “is,” obliging us to look at how the legal and the ethical are figured in judicial practice. Second, it is less likely to alienate than either philosophy, on the one hand, or stronger forms of legalism, on the other.

To develop these claims, I focus on an institution that has been described as “the conscience of Europe,”Footnote 6 the European Court of Human Rights. This court hears allegations of violations of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR), the “jewel in the crown” of international human rights law.Footnote 7 Its decisions bind contracting states, and its views tend to be cited both by other international human rights courts and quasi-courts and by national courts within and beyond Europe. It operates with a doctrine of deference to state decision-making in certain circumstances, which can irritate some who are purist about human rights, but appeals to others as an appropriate way to recognize that universal values are instantiated in specific local contexts.

Taking my lead from bioethics’ longstanding interest in both the start of life and biotechnology, I examine the court’s case law on assisted reproductive technologies (ARTs)Footnote 8 – a total of six cases, four of which include a judgment from the Grand Chamber of the court. The cases range across the technologies of assisted insemination (AI), in vitro fertilization (IVF), and pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD),Footnote 9 and they focus primarily on limits and prohibitions on access to ARTs.

In Evans v. United Kingdom, the first of the cases, the applicant sought access to embryos that were her only chance of having a child to whom she would be genetically related.Footnote 10 The embryos had been created using her eggs and the sperm of her then-fiancé before she underwent treatment for ovarian cancer. When the couple separated, he withdrew permission for use or continued storage of the embryos, and under the law in the United Kingdom, this meant the embryos would have to be destroyed. The next case, Dickson v. United Kingdom, involved a married male prisoner serving a life term and his female partner, who challenged a refusal to allow them to access AI, which was their only option if they were to try for a genetically related child.Footnote 11 Next, in S.H. and Others v. Austria, two married heterosexual couples challenged a legislative ban on IVF with donor gametes.Footnote 12 In Costa and Pavan v. Italy, a married heterosexual couple who carried a serious inheritable genetic condition challenged a blanket ban on PGD.Footnote 13 In Knecht v. Romania, a woman complained inter alia of the refusal by medical authorities to allow her to transfer her embryos from the location where they were being stored to a clinic of her choice.Footnote 14 Finally, in the most recent case, Parrillo v. Italy, a woman who no longer wanted to use IVF embryos for reproductive purposes following the unexpected death of her male partner brought a challenge to a legislative ban on donating embryos to scientific research.Footnote 15

So what am I aiming to do by looking at these six cases? Overall, the chapter is more exploratory and exhortatory than normative, which makes it unusual as a piece of legal scholarship. I am stepping back from what the law “ought to be” in order to encourage the fresh conversation that I want to see take place between bioethics and international human rights law and practice. To be openly and actively normative could encourage hubris – a sense that international human rights law and practice “does it better” than bioethics. It would almost certainly encourage allegations of hubris – a sense that international human rights lawyers think they and their field are the best. As we shall see, the relationships between bioethicists and international human rights lawyers are complicated enough; to focus on what a human rights-based approach to ART “ought to be” would only add to the trouble and hinder conversation.

I use the ART cases to address two questions. First, does the European Court of Human Rights have a view on how bioethics relates to international human rights law? Second, do the cases offer food for thought, not just for human rights lawyers, but for bioethicists too? Above all, do they incite us to think about the place of international human rights law in the space of bioethics, and the place of bioethics in the space of international human rights law?Footnote 16 These latter questions can, of course, be addressed in other ways as well. For instance, as Lea Shaver demonstrates in Chapter 2, we could concentrate on the right to science, framing any problematic application of technology as an “experiment” and foregrounding ways in which particular bioethics principles could be incorporated into human rights law and practice, and technological design and implementation, in order to prevent or mitigate harm.

This chapter, by contrast, begins by offering a short account of interactions to date between bioethics and international human rights law and practice. It describes the lack of interest displayed by the latter, and the harsh, persistent complaints concerning human rights that come from the former. The next sections offer an introduction to the ART cases. They explore the court’s descriptions of the technologies involved and the issues to be addressed. They also examine the court’s account of good lawmaking in this field (including how it sees its own role). I also consider the extent to which the court has broached the relationship between the legal and the bioethical. The last section provides a conclusion.

II Entwining and Estranging: A Short History of the Relationship Between Bioethics and International Human Rights Law and Practice

In this section, I sketch how bioethics and international human rights law and practice view each other, and how they are viewed by critics. I want, in particular, to look at how the two domains have both entwined and estranged. To do this, I begin with bioethics, the word itself coming from two Greek words, bios (life) and ethos (values or morality), and used today in multiple registers. It is difficult to parse these registers, so my plan is to focus on the principal ones – namely, bioethics as an intellectual field and as a governance practice.Footnote 17

I know that immediately some will insist that bioethics is not a field, but a discipline or set of disciplines, an expert domain, or a topic. I am no expert, but I suspect that diverse national histories and diverse priorities for the future of bioethics make it important to accommodate a range of terms. However, because I need to move forward, my hope is that even if the idea of bioethics as a field is controversial, there will be common ground on the following: first, bioethics has an interdisciplinary character; second, philosophy, law, and medicine have been key contributors to that interdisciplinary character; third, bioethics has had a longstanding focus on patients and research participants; and fourth, more recently, it has been focusing on technology, in particular technologies of human reproduction and enhancement.Footnote 18

As to the second register, which I have labeled “bioethics as a governance practice,” here too it might be best to acknowledge that contemporary bioethics hosts a range of such practices,Footnote 19 including the ethics committees of hospitals and research institutions. But my particular interest is “public ethics,”Footnote 20 by which I mean the practices of political or advisory bodies on bioethics. These bodies may be appointed by one state acting alone or by a group of states; they can also be independent of the state. The United Kingdom’s Nuffield Council on Bioethics is one example of the sort of body I have in mind; the Council of Europe’s Committee on Bioethics is another. Other examples include the Deutscher Ethikrat (Germany’s National Ethics Council), the US Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues, the Comitato Nazionale per la Bioetica (Italy’s National Bioethics Committee), UNESCO’s International Bioethics Committee, and the European Commission’s European Group on Ethics in Science and New Technologies.Footnote 21

Interestingly, what I have just said about bioethics could also be said of international human rights law and practice. The latter, in other words, is both an intellectual field and a range of governance practices, with mechanisms and institutions ranging from courts and quasi-courts to the UN Special Procedures.Footnote 22 There are other parallels, too. There is, for instance, a range of resonant preoccupations, including “the vulnerable human subject,” dignity, autonomy, and relatedly the requirement for informed consent prior to treatment. There are also stories of shared origins. Typically, this includes the Doctors’ Trial in Nuremberg in the aftermath of World War II, but there are also country-specific accounts that emphasize particular braidings of bioethics and rights; in the United States, for instance, some commentators point to the significance of the civil rights era for both fields.Footnote 23

In a further parallel, both bioethics and international human rights law and practice seem rife with insider and outsider criticism. The critics of international human rights law and practice typically denounce it as both hegemonic and replete with out-of-date and inappropriate ideas and techniques. Meanwhile, the critics of bioethics accuse it of becoming “institutionalized ethics,” both too focused on conforming to standardized rules and regulations (and too keen to wrap diverse settings and states in a timeless, placeless, one-size-fits-all “global bioethics”) and too quick to endorse and promote technology’s promised utopias.Footnote 24

What’s more, bioethics and international human rights law and practice have faced some similar criticisms. In particular, each has been accused of neglecting lived experience and structural injustice, and of overemphasizing freedom, autonomy, and consent and, more broadly, principles-based reasoning.Footnote 25 Typically, the most trenchant critics of each field are blunt about what needs to happen: bioethics (and, equally, international human rights law and practice) should “get out of the way.” For some of these critics, “progress” is the preferred guide; for others, it is “justice.” To be fair, though, whether we are talking about bioethics or international human rights law and practice, a majority of critics argue for reform and reorientation rather than abandonment.

Parallels are, however, just part of the story; there is considerable contrast too. Thus, bioethicists have spent far more time criticizing and engaging with international human rights law and practice than vice versa.Footnote 26 And bioethicists, not surprisingly, are far more skeptical of law than their international human rights counterparts. There are plenty of bioethicists who are also highly skeptical of human rights. More broadly, as the American Association for the Advancement of Science has observed: “Human rights per se are often viewed as irrelevant to the practice of ethics.”Footnote 27 Why is that?

The lack of a convincing theory of human rights is the biggest stumbling block. It has become a particular irritant in the context of the international right to health, where bioethicists and philosophers line up to insist that neither law nor legal scholarship offers a way to make sense of this right in the context of limited resources.Footnote 28 Other stumbling blocks to bioethical engagement with rights include the advocacy and activist orientation of international human rights law and practice, and its substantial focus on the state. There are also some bioethicists who would take the “human” out of human rights, either because they prefer to focus on “persons,” or because they see human rights as an obstacle to enhancement technology’s promise of “post-humans.”Footnote 29 Others, focused on the doctor–patient relationship, believe that human rights law risks denuding medical ethics of its capacity to be the “soul of medicine.”Footnote 30

Thus, despite the fact that bioethics has engaged with rights-based approaches in the process of broadening its own interests from the doctor–patient relationship and questions concerning new technologies, there is an overall sense that bioethicists do not see human rights as a legitimate form of analysis and reasoning. There is a sense, too, that for those who play a formal part in public ethics, consensus might be hard to achieve if all parties were to come to the table claiming “their rights.”

Another clear contrast is that philosophy is central to bioethics, whereas it is less common and less valued in international human rights law and practice. Equally, by contrast with bioethics, international human rights law and practice has had low levels of interest in ART.Footnote 31 As far as technology is concerned, advocates of human rights have tended to engage with information and communication technology (including how it can be used to expose human rights violations), and with the uptake of technology in the criminal justice sphere. And as regards reproduction, the central foci of international human rights advocacy have been safe motherhood, forced sterilization, and the vast unmet need for access to modern contraception and associated information and services.Footnote 32

“Safe motherhood” requires engagement with abortion, but as the term itself indicates, the emphasis has been on unsafe abortion as a major public health concern, rather than competing rights claims. States have been encouraged to decriminalize abortion and to guarantee access to quality post-abortion care in order to reduce the high levels of maternal mortality and morbidity that stem from unsafe abortion. Rights arguments have been put aside in order to avoid conflict and dissent that could stall state action and leave pregnant women at risk of injury and death. Relatedly, when asked to adjudicate upon state practice with respect to abortion, international courts (including the European Court of Human Rights) have avoided definitive statements on the status of the fetus. Their principal focus has been whether states, where abortion is lawful in at least some circumstances, have taken steps to ensure that abortion on these grounds is available in practice.Footnote 33

III A Poor Perch? Introducing the ART Cases from the European Court of Human Rights

The aim of this section, and the two that follow, is to explore the extent to which the six ART cases from the European Court of Human Rights can open up conversation between bioethicists and international human rights lawyers. The conversation could simply be about the regulation of ART, or it could be about the broader question of the optimum relationship between the legal and the ethical in regulation of the life sciences and their technologies – in particular, the relationship between human rights-based approaches to science and sciences that “have ethics.”

On first reading, the cases lack promise in that none of them makes explicit reference to bioethics.Footnote 34 There is also little by way of general comment on ART and human rights, and the technological dimensions of assisted reproduction seem to be under the radar too. Thus, IVF is described as a “fast-moving” technology, “subject to particularly dynamic development in science.” And its use is said to raise “sensitive moral and ethical issues.”Footnote 35 Overall, however, the cases lack the level of engagement one finds in cases from other fields of technology, notably S and Marper v. United Kingdom, in which the court issued a warning that any uptake of technologies in the criminal justice sphere must not “unacceptably weaken” the right to respect for private life, family, home, and correspondence in Article 8 of the ECHR.Footnote 36

The judges also seem to be inconsistent in how they understand the technology involved, with some evidence that different labels align with different levels of scrutiny of state practice. In S.H., which involved an unsuccessful challenge to Austria’s ban on IVF using donor gametes, the joint dissenting opinion spoke exclusively of “medically assisted procreation,”Footnote 37 thereby framing ART as medical, not technological, and as an ordinary, understandable way of “assisting nature.” The majority, by contrast, used the phrase “artificial procreation,” taking its lead from the title of the law in the respondent state.

Overall, the cases display little depth or range. They indicate that the right to respect for private life encompasses the right to respect for the decision to become or not to become a parent, including in the genetic sense.Footnote 38 The right of a couple to conceive a child and to make use of medically assisted reproduction for that purpose is protected as an “expression of private and family life.”Footnote 39 But this barely scratches the surface of the issues that arise. Relatedly, there is no sense of engagement across “different worlds of lived experience” of ART – engagement of the sort that is standard in fields like anthropology and sociology.Footnote 40 The court, of course, does not review legislation or practice in the abstract; it focuses on examining the issues raised by the case before it.Footnote 41 Nonetheless, there is a sense of missing context and problematic assumptions.

In S.H., for instance, the majority spent a good part of its judgment looking at claims made by the respondent state as to the risks of permitting IVF with donor eggs. But then, with no discussion of whether the context was the same or not, it took its reasoning on this matter and applied it to donor sperm.

Similarly, in Evans, in which the applicant unsuccessfully sought access to six embryos that were her only chance of having a child to whom she would be genetically related, the court made no reference to the differing levels of sophistication of egg and sperm freezing – even though the opportunity to freeze eggs, rather than embryos created with her then-fiancé’s sperm, would have avoided the difficulties that followed when their relationship broke down and he withdrew his consent to the storage or use of the embryos. The Evans court also made no reference to the requirement in domestic law (since amended) that treatment providers take account of the child’s “need for a father,” a requirement that could well have blocked the applicant’s access to treatment if she had asked to use donor sperm to fertilize her eggs, rather than the sperm of her then-fiancé.

The more recent decisions are just as frustrating. In Costa and Pavan, the applicants, who were carriers of cystic fibrosis, succeeded in their challenge to Italy’s blanket ban on PGD. Crucial to the court’s decision was the fact that Italian law was inconsistent: the law banned PGD (which allows the identification of genetic abnormalities in embryos created via IVF), but allowed abortion on grounds of fetal malformation. Under Italian law, in other words, the applicants could commence a pregnancy, take a prenatal genetic test, and request an abortion if the test suggested a malformation, but they could not have their embryos screened prior to implantation. For the court, it was entirely wrong that the applicants were put in such a position.

It is, I think, easy to empathize with the court on this, but where I have less empathy is the court’s limited engagement with PGD. The court focused exclusively on the inconsistency of Italian law, making no real comment on PGD from a rights perspective. It did note that the applicants had not complained of a violation of a “right to have a healthy child.” The applicants were, it said, relying on a more “confined” right, namely, “the possibility of using ART and subsequently PGD for the purposes of conceiving a child unaffected by cystic fibrosis, a genetic disease of which they are healthy carriers.”Footnote 42 It also referred to the applicants’ “desire” to conceive a child unaffected by cystic fibrosis, and to use ART and PGD to this end, as a “choice” that was “a form of expression of their private and family life” and thus within the scope of Article 8 of the ECHR.Footnote 43

This leaves open many questions regarding both discrimination and choice. On different facts, would the court see PGD not as an ART but as a “selective reproductive technology”; i.e., a technology that is not only about overcoming infertility, but also “used to prevent or allow the birth of certain kinds of children”?Footnote 44 Evidence suggests that, in places, PGD is being used to select against sex and against disabilities, which compounds powerful prior practices of discrimination. The question that arises is: What would be a human rights-based approach to PGD?

PGD, and ART more broadly, also raise questions concerning choice and its companion, informed consent. How, for instance, would the European Court of Human Rights respond to ethnographic evidence that reproductive responsibility, rather than reproductive choice, can weigh heavily on would-be parents, leading some (who have given consent in the manner expected and promoted by international human rights law) to say they felt they had “no choice” but to use PGD?Footnote 45 These would-be parents seem to be reporting obligations, not options. Evidence also suggests that prenatal diagnostic tests are often undertaken without full knowledge of their implications and, above all, in the hope of reassurance, which leaves would-be parents ill-equipped for the “choices” that follow. Reading between the lines, it is clear that the court in Costa and Pavan saw the applicants as responsible would-be parents and Italian law as deeply irresponsible. That analysis, however, offers no guidance as to what would count as a human rights-based approach to technologies that encourage would-be parents to keep trying for a child and also offer increasing options for identifying, and eliminating, unwanted traits in any future children.

There are two other points. The first concerns what counts as an ART case; the second concerns the court’s position on the status of the human embryo. Those who follow the court’s case law may ask why my list of ART cases does not include decisions such as Mennesson v. France,Footnote 46 Foulon and Bouvet v. France,Footnote 47 and Paradiso and Campanelli v. Italy,Footnote 48 each of which involved a surrogate pregnancy facilitated by IVF. The question, in other words, is: Where does technology-enabled surrogacy fit in the court’s ART frame? My answer is that we need to wait and see, as the most recent decision, Paradiso and Campanelli, signals that several members of the court are deeply opposed to surrogacy and keen to limit the scope of Article 8 of the ECHR in this context.

The court’s focus in the surrogacy cases is narrow: it is looking only at the post-birth context, in particular at the steps that can legitimately be taken when a child has been born following an overseas surrogacy arrangement and the contracting state believes there has been a contravention of its domestic law.Footnote 49 But this did not constrain the four concurring judges in Paradiso and Campanelli, who expressed regret that the court had not taken a clear stance against surrogacy. Surrogacy, according to these judges, treats people “not as ends in themselves, but as means to satisfy the desires of other persons.” And, whether it is remunerated or not, “[it] is incompatible with human dignity. It constitutes degrading treatment, not only for the child but also for the surrogate mother.” It is, the judges conclude, incompatible with the values underlying the Convention.Footnote 50 This is a very strong stance. It does not, to be clear, represent the decision of the court. The decision does not rule on the compatibility of surrogacy with the Convention. It simply says that surrogacy raises “sensitive ethical questions” on which there is no consensus amongst contracting states.Footnote 51 Hence my claim that we need to wait and see.

As to the status of the human embryo, by and large the court has sought to stay away from this issue, emphasizing that it is the state, not the court, that is the key decision-maker. But several of the ART cases suggest that this might not hold going forward. More importantly, the court could find itself in a tangle as it tries to steer clear of the question of personhood and when the right to life, protected in Article 2 of the ECHR, begins (which it sees as a question for states),Footnote 52 while also protecting women’s rights under the Convention and developing Article 8’s qualified right to respect for private and family life. The developing idea of human dignity could play a part too, given that the court has said that “the potentiality of [the embryo/fetus] and its capacity to become a person … require protection in the name of human dignity, without making it a ‘person’ with the ‘right to life’ for the purposes of Article 2.”Footnote 53

In Evans, the court stated that “the embryos created by the applicant and [her ex-fiancé] [did] not have a right to life within the meaning of Article 2 of the Convention,”Footnote 54 a position described, in extreme terms, by a concurring judge in a later case as “the Evans anti-life principle.”Footnote 55 Then, in Costa and Pavan, the court said that “the concept of ‘child’ cannot be put in the same category as that of ‘embryo’,”Footnote 56 while also seeming to indicate that the status of the embryo falls within Article 8(2) of the ECHR, under which infringement of the right to respect for private and family life may be justified if necessary in a democratic society to protect the “rights and freedoms of others.”Footnote 57

Most recently, in Parrillo, the majority made a range of similarly difficult-to-reconcile statements. On the one hand, and perhaps in line with Costa and Pavan, they framed the applicant’s embryos as “others”; on the other hand, they went on to say that they were not determining whether “others” extends to embryos.Footnote 58 In another difficult-to-interpret position, the majority said that “the embryos contain the genetic material of [the applicant] and accordingly represent a constituent part of [her] genetic material and biological identity,” but also said that the applicant’s relationship with her embryos did “not concern a particularly important aspect of [her] existence and identity.”Footnote 59 It is hard to know why the majority made these clumsy statements. It seems the judges wanted to emphasize the importance of genetic material, while also ensuring that because the case was about the use of human embryos, the final decision would rest with the state, not the court.

Parrillo also featured a claim by the applicant to a property right over her embryos under Article 1 of the EHCR’s Protocol 1. This was dismissed with little consideration. The majority concluded on the point by noting that because Article 1 of Protocol 1 has an “economic and pecuniary scope,” human embryos cannot be reduced to “‘possessions’ within the meaning of that provision.”Footnote 60 The majority also noted that Article 2 was not at issue in the case, which meant that “the sensitive and controversial question of when human life begins”Footnote 61 did not have to be examined.

IV The Ethics of the Margin: How Has the Court Used the Doctrine of the Margin of Appreciation in Its ART Cases?

The court’s particular identity is part of the reason it holds back from definitive statements on the status of the embryo and fetus: it is a supranational human rights institution, not a domestic one. To reflect this, the court has crafted what is called the doctrine of the margin of appreciation. The doctrine allows the court to control the amount of discretion it is willing to give to the contracting state against which a complaint of a rights violation has been levelled. Where the court declares that the margin should be wide, it takes a step back – in essence, positioning itself as the “international judge,” less well-placed than national authorities to be the central decision-maker on the issue at stake.Footnote 62

For some, the granting of a wide margin of appreciation is a sign that the court is too keen to constrain itself and too quick to shelter the Convention from the dynamic or evolutive style of interpretation that could, they say, secure its status as a living instrument. Others take a different view: for them, the legitimacy problem stems from cases in which the court limited the margin accorded to the respondent state. These cases, they complain, are evidence of an international court acting like a constitutional court and involving itself in issues that are none of its business, issues that ought to be determined at the national level.Footnote 63

For my purposes, the obvious question is: What would bioethicists think of the doctrine and its use-in-practice by the court? I anticipate strong views, given the debate about relativism versus universalism in bioethics. Four of the ART cases, Evans, S.H. and Others, Knecht, and Parrillo, involved the granting of a wide margin of appreciation to the states concerned. It appears there were two principal reasons for this: first, what the court saw as the absence of consensus within the member states of the Council of Europe on the issues raised (“either as to the relative importance of the interest at stake or as to the best means of protecting it”Footnote 64), and second, and relatedly, the presence of “sensitive moral or ethical issues.”Footnote 65 In Evans, the court provided a third reason for greater deference: “There will usually be a wide margin of appreciation accorded if the State is required to strike a balance between competing private and public interests or Convention rights.”Footnote 66

Dickson, by contrast, is a reminder that the court will restrict the margin accorded to a state “where a particularly important facet of an individual’s existence or identity is at stake.”Footnote 67 In Dickson, in which a prisoner and his wife successfully challenged the process by which they were refused access to AI facilities, the court indicated that “the choice to become a genetic parent” is one such facet of an individual’s existence and identity.Footnote 68

In S.H. and Others, however, this was not enough to assist the applicants; their challenge to Austria’s ban on using donor gametes for IVF was rejected by the court. In rejecting their challenge, the court mentioned, inter alia, their option to seek assisted reproduction abroad and have parenthood recognized at home.Footnote 69 Relatedly, in Parrillo, having described the applicant’s cryopreserved embryos as a “constituent part of [her] identity,” a majority of the court later justified the granting of a wide margin of appreciation in part by drawing a distinction between the case before it and cases concerning “prospective parenthood.” The majority’s position was that although the right to donate embryos to scientific research was “important,” it was not “one of the core rights attracting the protection of Article 8 of the Convention as it does not concern a particularly important aspect of the applicant’s existence and identity.”Footnote 70

When the court grants a wide margin of appreciation, it does not abdicate all power and responsibility to the respondent state. As the court explained in Costa and Pavan, “the solutions reached by the legislature are not beyond the scrutiny of the Court.”Footnote 71 In conducting this scrutiny, the court tends to focus on the lawmaking process and whether the impugned law strikes a “fair balance” between all competing private and public interests.Footnote 72

But the judges do not always agree on what is required, and there have been strongly worded dissenting opinions that accuse the majority of using the margin of appreciation in a formal or mechanical way – i.e., granting deference but without the companion scrutiny that would weigh the state’s arguments, evidence, and expertise. In Evans, for instance, the joint dissenting opinion cautioned that the doctrine must not be used by the court “as a merely pragmatic substitute for a thought-out approach to the problem of proper scope of review.”Footnote 73 Furthermore, none of the ART cases provides an explanation of the category of “sensitive moral and ethical issues” that will trigger a wide margin of appreciation. This leaves a range of questions. How does the court see the relationship between “moral” issues and “ethical” ones – are the terms synonymous? What is the significance of the adjective “sensitive” (or “delicate,” another qualifier used by the court)? And in what circumstances is there “acute sensitivity” or “profound moral views” (both of which were used by the court to justify a wide margin of appreciation in A, B and C v. Ireland, which involved a challenge to a restrictive abortion law)?Footnote 74

Those interested in debates concerning universalism versus relativism will want to pay particular attention to the “European consensus,” another determining factor with respect to the degree of deference the court is willing to accord to contracting states. The “emerging European consensus” is more interesting still. It featured in S.H. and Others, in which the court made reference to “a clear trend in the legislation of the Contracting States towards allowing gamete donation for the purpose of in vitro fertilisation.”Footnote 75 Ultimately, the trend was not used by the court to limit the wide margin of appreciation granted to the respondent state; it was not based on “settled and long-standing principles established in the law of the member States,” but rather reflected “a stage of development within a particularly dynamic field of law.”Footnote 76 Nonetheless, the idea of the emerging consensus as a signaling tool – a shot across the (state) bow, a sign that the future could be different – is intriguing.

One final point about the emerging consensus and its counterpart, the European consensus: both concentrate the court’s attention on collectives. Notice that this also can be said of the court’s increasing reference to international instruments (which may not have been ratified by all contracting states) and to the evolution of societal thinking. So my question would be: How is this attention to collectives seen by those who criticize international human rights law and practice for being obsessed with the individual and the universal and with crude, decontextualized norms? Bioethicists feature heavily among those critics, so this would be one obvious opportunity for fresh content to stimulate fresh conversation.

V Law’s Capacities: Does the Court Have Faith in Law and Lawmaking on ART?

I turn finally to the question of whether the court has expressed a view on what counts as good law and good lawmaking in the field of ART. As I see it, any such views would contribute to my hoped-for conversation between bioethicists and international human rights lawyers.Footnote 77 For instance, does the court share bioethics’ enthusiasm for processes or procedures of decision-making? Equally, does it share the view of some bioethicists that law is a way of capping off bioethical consensus, a way of “putting [bioethics’] words and ideas into practice”?Footnote 78 Or does it, by contrast, prefer the negative view offered by others, that law generally gets in the way of both scientific progress and decent ethical argument?Footnote 79 Relatedly, does the court itself see law expansively, or is there a closing down of law’s forms and capacities – a sense that in the end, law talk is about bans, moratoria, and limits of other sorts? Finally, to what extent does the court endorse the popular view that while law might be “marching alongside” medicine, science, and technology, it is “always in the rear and limping a little”?Footnote 80

The ART cases do not provide much explicit detail on the court’s views about what counts as good law and good lawmaking in the field of ART. In part the reason for this is that the wide margin of appreciation granted in four of the cases extends, in principle, “both to the State’s decision whether or not to enact legislation governing the use of IVF treatment and, having intervened, to the detailed rules it lays down in order to achieve a balance between competing public and private interests.”Footnote 81 Still, there are some pointers. In Evans, the court encouraged contracting states to take steps to recognize that embryo-freezing produces “an essential difference between IVF and fertilisation through sexual intercourse”: “the possibility of allowing a lapse of time, which may be substantial, to intervene between the creation of the embryo and its implantation in the uterus.” In light of this, the court advised states to devise legal schemes that take the possibility of delay into account. Such schemes were, it said, “legitimate – and indeed desirable.”Footnote 82

Second, in both Evans and S.H. and Others, the court made clear that even when important private life interests are engaged, it is open to legislators to adopt “rules of an absolute nature” – “[rules] which serve to promote legal certainty.”Footnote 83 Put differently, legislators do not have to provide for “the weighing of competing interests in the circumstances of each individual case.”Footnote 84 But this is not a free pass for legislators. For instance, in S.H. and Others, having noted that “concerns based on moral considerations or on social acceptability must be taken seriously in a sensitive domain like artificial procreation,” the court went on to insist that such concerns “are not in themselves sufficient reasons for a complete ban on a specific artificial procreation technique such as ovum donation.”Footnote 85 The court then reminded contracting states that, even where a wide margin of appreciation is granted, the impugned domestic legal framework “must be shaped in a coherent manner which allows the different legitimate interests involved to be adequately taken into account.”Footnote 86

But what is not clear from S.H. and Others, or from the ART cases as a whole, is what these different legitimate interests are. There are, at best, some pointers. Thus, in Evans, in determining whether the competing private and public interests had been weighed in a way that achieved fair balance, the majority emphasized two particular public interests: first, that the impugned provisions of the UK’s ART law upheld the principle of the primacy of consent, and second, that their “bright-line,” no-exceptions approach promoted legal clarity and certainty.Footnote 87 On the private interests side, the majority focused on the right to be, or not to be, a parent, including in the genetic sense. In Parrillo, the majority noted that the drafting process of Italy’s ban on donating human embryos to scientific research had taken account of both “the State’s interest in protecting the embryo” and the private interest in exercising the right to individual self-determination “in the form of donating [one’s] embryos to research.”Footnote 88 In S.H. and Others, which upheld Austria’s ban on donor gametes in IVF, the majority referred to the need to take account of “human dignity, the well-being of children thus conceived and the prevention of negative repercussions or potential misuse.”Footnote 89 They also noted that there was “no prohibition under [the law] on going abroad to seek treatment of infertility”Footnote 90 and having the resulting maternity and paternity recognized upon returning to Austria.

Frustratingly, the majority made no attempt to engage with the particular challenges of cross-border reproduction. The joint dissenting opinion did engage to a degree,Footnote 91 and some of the potential challenges were raised by one of the interveners. The latter saw what it described as “procreative tourism” as a “negative side-effect of the ban” – one that left “couples seeking infertility treatment abroad … exposed to the risk of low quality standards and of suffering from considerable financial and emotional stress.”Footnote 92 No one, however, mentioned the impact on donors in the state visited by the couple (including the risk of exploitation), or the potential costs to the health service in the home state. Equally, no one mentioned how would-be parents viewed treatment abroad, or whether they cared about recognition of legal parentage.Footnote 93 And no one mentioned the difficulties that might be faced by a donor-conceived child seeking information about his or her genetic origin.

More positively, the ART cases as a whole are clear about the court’s enthusiasm for process. The court encourages states to be proactive: In upholding Austria’s ban on IVF with donor gametes in S.H. and Others, the court emphasized that “this area, in which the law appears to be continuously evolving and which is subject to a particularly dynamic development in science and law, needs to be kept under review by the Contracting States.”Footnote 94 But the court also observed that it was “understandable that the States find it necessary to act with particular caution in the field of artificial procreation”Footnote 95 and applauded Austria for an approach that was “careful and cautious.”Footnote 96 Similarly, in Evans, the United Kingdom’s ART law was described as “the culmination of an exceptionally detailed examination of the social, ethical and legal implications of developments in the field of human fertilisation and embryology, and the fruit of much reflection, consultation and debate.”Footnote 97 Most recently, in Parrillo, the court highlighted the drafting process behind Italy’s ban on donating to scientific research human embryos that had been created for the purpose of medically assisted reproduction.Footnote 98

This procedural lens is not without difficulties. In Parrillo, the court turned to the drafting process of the impugned law, having said it was about to examine whether a fair balance had been struck between the competing public and private interests at stake. In what followed, however, it focused exclusively on the formalities of the legislative process; there was, in other words, no engagement with the substantive arguments that had emerged during that process. Parrillo also raises questions about why, precisely, the court is relying on legislative process. Is it to determine the breadth of the margin of appreciation? Is it an element of a broader proportionality analysis, or is it simply a poor substitute for that analysis?Footnote 99 The dissenting opinion of Judge Sajó in Parrillo takes a much more probing stance on both the legislative process and the impugned law itself, which suggests that the court’s judges do not have an agreed stance on my questions.

There is a sense from some of the ART cases that, unlike some bioethicists and much of the media, the court has faith in law’s capacity to handle the challenges of a rapidly evolving set of technologies like ART. We should, of course, expect a court to have faith in law, so what is interesting is the detail. In S.H. and Others, the court seemed to suggest that law could handle what Austria described as the risks of “harm to women” arising from egg donation (in particular, the risk of exploitation of donors). In this regard, it drew attention to the success of adoption law, though it accepted that “the splitting of motherhood between a genetic mother and the one carrying the child differs significantly from adoptive parent-child relations and has added a new aspect to this issue.”Footnote 100

There have also been indications of what irks the court in the context of law, law-making, and application of law – of what it sees as falling short of democratic legitimacy. In Knecht v. Romania, although the court dismissed the complaint, it took the time to describe the Romanian regulator’s attitude as “obstructive and oscillatory.”Footnote 101 In Costa and Pavan, it was the incoherence of Italian law that irked the court. The applicants, a married couple carrying cystic fibrosis, had been barred from using IVF and PGD to screen their embryos so that only healthy ones could be implanted. Were they to conceive, however, the law permitted them to terminate the pregnancy on the grounds of fetal genetic condition. This, the court said, “caused a state of anguish for the applicants,”Footnote 102 and, as noted earlier, it went on to hold that Italy’s ban on IVF with PGD constituted a disproportionate interference with the applicants’ right to respect for private and family life.

VI Conclusion

In drawing to a close, two points stand out from my review of the court’s ART cases. First, the court invokes “the ethical” but largely leaves us guessing about what would constitute a human rights-based approach to the relationship between “the legal” and “the bioethical.” Second, and relatedly, the court leaves us guessing as to what would constitute a human rights-based approach to ART.

These gaps are problematic. Rights holders and duty bearers would benefit from clarity on what is a legal responsibility and what is a moral or an ethical one. But I suggest we see the gaps as productive, too. They allow us to think about the scope and content of rights and responsibilities in the ART field, without stalling on what is legal and what is ethical. More broadly, they demonstrate that international human rights case law is a starting point for discussion, not a full stop – that it is much more contested than the stereotypes of freedoms, entitlements, and duties suggest, much more provisional than the word “law” indicates, and much more interwoven with the domestic than the word “international” implies.Footnote 103

I am not saying that there is no need to grasp what is, or could be, unique to human rights law, just that it would be useful to approach that question in new ways. With that in mind, and focusing on the contribution that international human rights law and practice could make to “good science,” this chapter has explored whether the ART case law of the European Court of Human Rights could generate fresh conversation between human rights lawyers and bioethicists. My conclusion is that it could.

The ART cases, as we have seen, do not set down what “ought to be.” They flag the centrality of the right to respect for private life, which covers the decision to become or not to become a parent, including in the genetic sense, and to use medically assisted procreation to that end. In a less-developed manner, the cases flag the relevance of other Convention rights (notably the rights to life and to respect for family life), the Convention’s guarantee of nondiscrimination,Footnote 104 and the state’s interest in protecting “the rights and freedoms of others.” Considerable ebb and flow should be expected as the court and states continue to grapple with the balance between these rights and interests.

The court’s particular identity as a supranational human rights court is flagged by the cases, too. ART is presented as a field that raises “sensitive moral and ethical issues,” which is one of the triggers for a wide margin of appreciation. But a wide margin is not a free pass, nor is it guaranteed. It can be limited by a European consensus (and potentially by an emerging one as wellFootnote 105). It can also be limited where a particularly important aspect of an individual’s existence or identity is at stake, which includes the right to respect for the decision to be or not to be a parent in the genetic sense. And even where a wide margin is seen as apt, the court has the power to scrutinize the democratic legitimacy of the impugned domestic measure. Each of these elements offers scope for study and, of course, for different views.

There are other potentially interesting elements that I have not addressed, such as: Did the gender of the judge count in any of the court’s ART cases?Footnote 106 In S.H. and Others, four women judges authored the biting dissent,Footnote 107 which suggests this question merits further study. Equally, how many of the court’s ART cases have featured third-party interventions, and is there a pattern in terms of who is intervening, in what types of cases, and with what sorts of claims?

Case selection is relevant too. For instance, would this chapter have read differently if I had framed the court’s ART cases as part of medical jurisprudence,Footnote 108 reproductive rights jurisprudence,Footnote 109 the jurisprudence of pregnancy,Footnote 110 or even a jurisprudence of kinship? And what would have emerged if I had looked at all of the court’s bioethical cases, which address issues including consent to medical examination and treatment, abortion, and assisted suicide? Equally, what would have emerged if either a particular concept (say, dignity or autonomyFootnote 111) or a particular practice (say, cross-border care or informed consent) had been the focal point? And, changing tack again, what would we have seen if we had looked at all of the court’s technology cases? In particular, do we expect the question of ethics to feature in the court’s cases on other technologies, and if not, why not?

These, I suggest, are just some of the questions that arise. Moreover, if the aim is to delineate the relationship between the legal and the bioethical, and relatedly to capture what is distinctive about the authority of international human rights law, it will be important to locate the European Court of Human Rights within a broader frame. That frame should include not just other human rights actors, both domestic and international, but also other “palaces of hope”Footnote 112 from the field of international law that play a part in the regulation of the life sciences and their technologies. And finally, because human rights practice is not exclusive to legal actors, we should also be exploring how national bioethics bodies (such as those mentioned earlier in this chapter) and professional scientific organizations view the bioethics–human rights relationship. These explorations are not standard fare. They could, however, engage bioethicists and international human rights lawyers in ways that are important and overdue. And over time, they could contribute to “good science” as well.

5 Drones, Automated Weapons, and Private Military Contractors Challenges to Domestic and International Legal Regimes Governing Armed Conflict

Laura A. Dickinson Footnote *
I Introduction

The development of unmanned aerial vehicles and increasingly autonomous weapons systems is radically reshaping the nature of modern warfare. The US military now depends on unmanned aerial systems, often referred to as drones, to provide intelligence and surveillance, while armed drones that can drop bombs on terrorists form a core part of the US arsenal in the war on terror. From the longstanding Phalanx system, deployed by the US Navy to automatically detect and neutralize missiles that breach a warship’s protective envelope, to the Counter Rocket, Artillery, and Mortar (C-RAM) system, the US Army’s comparable land-based defense, to the X-47B drone that can fly by itself during takeoff and landing, the United States has relied increasingly on weapons systems that are unmanned or have at least some autonomous capability. Other countries have developed such systems as well, from Israel’s Harpies, which autonomously ferret out enemy radar and then dive-bomb to destroy them, to South Korea’s robotic sentries protecting the border.Footnote 1

In addition to altering the nature of warfare on the ground and in the air, the use of these new weapons systems has shaken up existing legal frameworks, both domestic and international, regulating the use of force abroad. Scholars and policy-makers have frequently grappled with the legal implications of deploying unmanned vehicles and increasingly autonomous weapons systems.Footnote 2 For example, some have discussed the legality of US efforts to target individual terrorists for assassination, often through drone strikes.Footnote 3 Others have focused specifically on the question of whether such targeted killings can be justified anywhere outside the battlefields of Afghanistan and Iraq.Footnote 4 Still others debate whether drones are worse (or better) than conventional weapons at limiting civilian casualties.Footnote 5

Drones and automated weapons also raise broader questions about the asymmetry inherent in this sort of warfare, where one side has few if any casualties and the other is subject to multiple strikes without an effective way to respond. Such asymmetry, some argue, violates fundamental principles of humanity undergirding the entire body of International Humanitarian Law (IHL).Footnote 6 Finally, debates under US domestic law focus largely on whether the Constitution can be invoked extraterritorially to protect the rights of citizens (or even noncitizens) targeted in such strikes, given that so far individuals have only been targeted while outside the territorial borders of the United States.Footnote 7

Concurrent with this trend toward the use of weapons that are more autonomous, the United States and many other countries have also privatized a broad array of military and security functions, using private contractors to an arguably unprecedented degree.Footnote 8 For example, at the high point of the conflict in Iraq and Afghanistan, the US government employed more than 260,000 contractors, which at times exceeded the total number of US military personnel deployed in those two countries.Footnote 9 Such contractors have performed a myriad of roles, from constructing military bases and refugee camps to cutting soldiers’ hair, serving meals in mess halls, maintaining weapons on the battlefield, interrogating detainees, and guarding diplomats and military facilities.Footnote 10 Scholars and policy-makers have confronted the legal implications of this shift, and many have called for increasing oversight.Footnote 11

Yet few, if any, studies have addressed the potentially incendiary mix of legal challenges arising from the combined use of drones and automated weapons, on the one hand, and private contractors, on the other. These trends have occurred side-by-side and even reinforce each other, because drones and automated weapons themselves often depend on contractors to function. Each twenty-four-hour combat air patrol of the US armed Predator and Reaper drones, for example, requires at least 350 people, many of whom are contractors. Contractors often invent and produce autonomous systems, and contractors may also be responsible for maintaining and operating these systems on the battlefield.

This chapter charts the rapid and intertwined growth of unmanned and increasingly autonomous weapons, on the one hand, and private military and security contractors, on the other. And it grapples with the particular challenges this combination of forces creates under both domestic and international law. The first part describes the increased use of drones and more fully autonomous weapons as well as the growing role of contractors in developing and operating these systems. The next part discusses the destabilizing impact that this trend is having on one of the foundations of the US constitutional framework itself: the allocation of power between the president and Congress in deciding whether or not to use force overseas. By reducing the political cost of war, the rise of these weapons systems and the growing use of contractors have together emboldened the president to deploy force unilaterally. At the same time, these twin trends have made possible legal arguments that the use of force is itself not significant enough to warrant congressional involvement. Such arguments are premised upon the idea that if there are few US military casualties there is less likely to be a war for constitutional purposes, or hostilities within the meaning of the War Powers Resolution. This reality is made possible in part because the use of autonomous weapons and contractors radically reduces the official casualty count.

The final part charts the similarly disruptive impact these trends have had on accountability and oversight under IHL. Together, the use of autonomous weapons and privatization have fragmented decision-making over the use of force, rendering accountability for violations of IHL principles much more difficult to achieve. Accordingly, from the perspective of both domestic and international law, the rise of autonomous weaponry combined with the increased use of contractors raises significant challenges to the rule of law during armed conflict and the protection of human rights in noncombat contexts.

II The Rise of Drones and Autonomous Weapons, and the Increasing Role of Military Contractors
A Drones

Unmanned aerial vehicles (UAVs), popularly referred to as “drones,” are now a seemingly permanent and pervasive fixture of the United States’ strategy to combat terrorism. These remote-controlled flight technologies are probably best known for their ability to drop bombs on terrorism suspects without putting US troops in harm’s way. Less discussed is their even bigger role in conducting surveillance. Such remote surveillance has radically reshaped and augmented military capabilities, both because UAVs can provide so-called enhanced situational awareness without endangering US troops on the ground and because they gather an enormous store of information that can then be used for multiple strategic purposes.Footnote 12 Given these important benefits, it is not surprising that drone use has surged dramatically in recent years.Footnote 13 The 2016 fiscal budget included $2.9 billion (US billion) for known costs in drone research, development, and procurement, and the Pentagon has at least 7,000 drones under its control.Footnote 14 Drone technology has become “fundamental” to military operations, and demand for the technology far outstrips the actual supply.Footnote 15

While the US overseas drone program has garnered significant public scrutiny, the integral role of contractors in developing and operating drones has attracted much less attention. It should be no surprise that leading defense firms develop and manufacture the broad range of drones that the United States uses, including the enormous high-flying RQ-4 Global Hawk (Northrup Grumman), with its powerful intelligence, surveillance, and reconnaissance capabilities; the deadly MQ-9 Reaper and MQ1 Predator (General Atomics), tactical strike and imaging drones that form the core of the US fleet unleashing bombs on terrorists; and tiny, handheld, battery-powered drones like the Dragon Eye (AeroVironment) and FQM Pointer (AeroVironment), which soldiers release from their backpacks to gather information.

But contractors also play a central role in the operation of drones, which for the larger models requires enormous teams of people. For example, each twenty-four-hour surveillance mission of the Global Hawk requires roughly 300–500 people. Each twenty-four-hour combat air patrol of the slightly smaller Predator and Reaper could require up to 350 people. Even the tiny handheld Dragon Eye and FQM Pointer depend on background teams of maintenance staff and intelligence analysts.

Contractors participate in almost every step of the complex array of tasks that make up a drone mission. Once the government purchases a drone, the manufacturer often provides continuing maintenance and logistical support services.Footnote 16 For example, in addition to assembling drones and providing maintenance for them, contractors have also reportedly fueled them and loaded ammunition onto them at military bases overseas.Footnote 17 Contractors also help operate drones, including, at times, steering them.Footnote 18 The Air Force has stated that while contractors do not “pilot” drones during the targeting portion of their missions, contractors do assist with other aspects of flight, such as takeoff and landing. In addition, the ever-present demand for drone missions, particularly as the conflict against ISIS escalated in Iraq and Syria, has led to pilot shortages and a growing need for contractors.

Finally, contractors also collect and analyze the data that drones gather.Footnote 19 In many cases, they review the live footage captured by drones.Footnote 20 Indeed, contractors frequently become the subject matter experts and can more easily distinguish patterns on the ground than their military counterparts.Footnote 21 Thus, while the Air Force has said that contractors do not make targeting decisions, contractor analysis of data can often shade into decision-making. For example, a 2013 Washington Post report suggested that a contractor who reviewed live footage from a drone essentially directed a Navy Seal to a particular target.Footnote 22 A more recent report by the Bureau of Investigative Journalism indicates that contractors working for the Department of Defense not only analyze the data from drones, but also provide evaluative judgments that may affect targeting decisions.Footnote 23

B Autonomous Weapons

The development of increasingly autonomous weapons systems is also reshaping modern warfare. Although there are multiple potential definitions of “autonomous,” the International Committee for the Red Cross defines an autonomous weapon as one “that is able to function in a self-contained and independent manner although its employment may initially be deployed or directed by a human operator” and that can “independently verify or detect a particular type of target object and then fire or detonate.”Footnote 24 An autonomous weapon system can also “learn or adapt its functioning in response to changing circumstances in the environment in which it is deployed.”Footnote 25 Most drones would not qualify as autonomous weapons, because human operators control them remotely. Yet many weapons systems, including a few types of drones, can now function autonomously to some degree. While fully autonomous weapons may still be decades away, current systems deployed on land, at sea, and in the air can now operate with an extraordinary degree of independence from individualized human decision-making.

In practice, militaries have deployed these systems primarily for defensive purposes, and they have retained a degree of human involvement even when the systems could operate without human participation. More than thirty countries are using such systems to defend military vehicles and bases.Footnote 26 They typically protect predetermined areas by detecting incoming munitions, such as mortars, rockets, or other projectiles, and then automatically responding by neutralizing these objects. Governments tend to deploy them in fixed, rather than mobile, positions in unpopulated and relatively simple and predictable environments, such as at sea or in remote areas, and they typically target weapons and objects rather than persons. In most cases, the reaction time required for engagement is so short that human interaction with the machines is minimal. Often, the human being is only given a brief opportunity to accept or reject the system’s choice of action before it deploys, or to override a course of action that the machine will otherwise take automatically.Footnote 27

A semi-autonomous offensive system, which mostly consists of projectiles, tends to require a human operator to launch,Footnote 28 but then autonomously guides the weapon to a preselected target, either by relying on passive sensors that respond to signals from the environment or by using active sensors that send out signals and look for a signal in return.Footnote 29 Known as guided munitions, these projectiles can be divided into two categories: “go-onto-target” projectiles, designed to hit a particular target, and “go-onto-location” projectiles, designed to hit a particular geographic location.Footnote 30 In some cases, humans can “control, abort, or retarget” such weapons in flight, but other times the projectiles cannot be adjusted once launched.Footnote 31

As with drones, private military contractors have been major players in inventing and producing these autonomous systems.Footnote 32 But perhaps even more significant is the potential role contractors play in testing, maintaining, and operating them. The military typically hires private contractors to test autonomous weapons systems in order to determine whether they will be effective and whether any changes need to be made before deployment. Sometimes contactors actually test their products in the field. For example, integrated teams of Northrop Grumman contractors and Navy personnel have tested the unmanned X-47B to prove that it is capable of operating in tandem with manned aircraft.Footnote 33 Based on such tests, private companies often receive contracts to upgrade autonomous weapons systems.Footnote 34 Finally, in some cases private contractors provide maintenance on autonomous weapons being used in the field in active deployment situations. For example, the US Army contracted with Northrop Grumman to install and maintain the C-RAM interceptor system at forward operating bases during Operation Enduring Freedom and the ongoing US mission in Iraq.Footnote 35 And Raytheon is currently contracted to provide ongoing technical and support services to the US Army on this system.Footnote 36

Contractors have even been hired to provide support to the autonomous systems being used in the field. Lockheed Martin has served as the AEGIS combat system engineering agent for the US Navy for the last forty years.Footnote 37 Currently, Northrop Grumman is fulfilling a $122 million contract with the US Army to “provide systems engineering, production, deployment and logistics support services for the C-RAM systems.”Footnote 38 Similarly, the foreign firm Rheinmetall Air Defence has received a contract for €20 million to provide documentation and training services for the Mantis, a short-range air defense protection system developed to protect the German Army in Afghanistan.Footnote 39

III The United States Separation of Powers Framework

This distinctive mix of autonomous devices and contractors upends traditional frameworks, both domestic and international, for regulating the conduct of war. This part examines how the rise of unmanned systems affects the implementation of the US constitutional and statutory regime governing the decision to use force abroad. The next part turns to the impact on the international humanitarian law regime.

The US Constitution explicitly and purposefully divides responsibility over the use of force abroad between the Congress and the president. Under the Constitution, Congress declares warFootnote 40 and holds the purse strings,Footnote 41 while the president is commander-in-chief of the armed forces.Footnote 42 Debates about the scope of the president’s power in relation to Congress date back centuriesFootnote 43 and have grown more fraught in the last fifty years as formal declarations of war have largely become a historical relic.Footnote 44 Some scholars and government lawyers have asserted broad theories of the president’s inherent power to use force unilaterally,Footnote 45 while others have taken a more restrained approach, articulating a view that shared responsibility between the president and Congress should continue.Footnote 46 After the Vietnam War, Congress tried to protect its position by enacting the War Powers Resolution, which requires the president to halt “hostilities” if Congress has not approved them within sixty days.Footnote 47 Since then, while Congress has, at times, spoken loudly to authorize the use of force – as it did in 2001 to allow a muscular response to Al Qaeda and the TalibanFootnote 48 and in 2003 to authorize the war in IraqFootnote 49 – at other times, Congress’s voice has been muted at best. Years into the US operations against the Islamic State in Iraq and Syria (ISIS), no new authorization of force was forthcoming from Congress.

In the face of congressional silence, the rise of unmanned systems, combined with the growing use of contractors, has enabled the president to claim greater scope for unilateral action. New technology has not merely emboldened the president politically, but has actually made possible new legal arguments to justify an expanded conception of the president’s role in relation to Congress. In order to see the development of these new legal arguments, this part focuses on three examples where the president used force overseas without receiving specific congressional approval: Kosovo in 1999, Libya in 2011, and the campaign against ISIS in Iraq and Syria beginning in 2014. In each case, we can see that the growing role of unmanned systems and contractors has opened space for legal arguments expanding the power of the executive branch.

A Kosovo

To understand the power shift that new technologies and the use of contractors have produced, and the impact of these trends on legal arguments about the use of force, it is useful to go back to 1999, when US President Bill Clinton sought to halt the ethnic cleansing campaign of the Yugoslav dictator Slobodan Milosevic in Kosovo. With the humiliating deaths of US troops in Mogadishu, Somalia, in 1993 still fresh in Americans’ minds, President Clinton aimed to intervene in a way that would minimize the risk of US casualties by relying primarily on an air campaign carried out jointly with the North Atlantic Treaty Organization (NATO).Footnote 50 This strategy endeavored to stop the killing without spilling American blood.

The military campaign was swift. President Clinton ordered US air strikes to begin in the province of Serbia on March 24, 1999, without explicit congressional approval.Footnote 51 The effort, conducted along with other NATO countries, lasted seventy-eight days and consisted entirely of an air campaign.Footnote 52 Of 37,000 sorties, the United States flew 23,208 (62 percent).Footnote 53 When President Milosevic agreed to withdraw Yugoslav forces from the region and allow the presence of a United Nations peacekeeping force on June 10, 1999, NATO suspended the bombing.Footnote 54 There were no combat casualties, a point the president highlighted at the end of the campaign.Footnote 55 Civilian casualties among the Yugoslav population, however, were in the range of 480–530.Footnote 56

Drones were also a part of the story. The US military had harnessed unmanned aircraft for surveillance as far back as the Vietnam War, when “Lightning Bugs” gathered information on the North Vietnamese. By 1999, drones had evolved sufficiently to give the military improved situational awareness and enable better targeting. During Operation Allied Force in Kosovo, the unmanned vehicles operated as “remote-controlled intelligence and surveillance platforms.”Footnote 57 The US military employed three tactical systems: the Air Force Predator, the Army Hunter, and the Navy Pioneer.Footnote 58 The Defense Department after-action report to Congress highlighted the significance of the new technology, emphasizing that the drones were used at “unprecedented levels” and “played an important role in our overall success.”Footnote 59 Specifically, the report noted, drones “enabled commanders to see the situation on the ground without putting aircrews at risk and provided continuous coverage of important areas.”Footnote 60 Their ability to convey live video feeds for “real-time targeting” was key. At this point, the drones did not conduct strikes, but they could fly lower than military aircraft, scout out targets, and transmit information in real time to minimize civilian casualties and make the air strategy more effective.

Contractors also formed a crucial element of the military strategy. During the air campaign, contractors provided intelligence support, served as linguists, transported fuel from barges on the Adriatic to locations inland, and built three refugee camps for displaced Kosovars.Footnote 61 After the primary air campaign ended, military contractors poured into the region, augmenting the US contingent of peacekeepers. The contractors performed an unprecedented variety of roles, including logistics, construction, training, and policing.Footnote 62 Significantly, their presence allowed the US military to contribute a much smaller number of troops (7,000) than might otherwise have been needed.Footnote 63 Overall, in the Balkans, the number of contractors far exceeded the number of troops, at a ratio of approximately 1.5–1.Footnote 64 It would be fair to say that the combined power of drones and contractors delivered a one-two punch that enabled the US military to reduce its footprint and the risk of military casualties.

This strategy of waging war from a safe distance, made possible in part by new technologies and contractors, gave the president more political leeway to act without clear approval from Congress. With regard to Kosovo, Congress debated the conflict extensively but neither explicitly supported nor opposed it, because those in favor of military action never mustered enough votes to pass a resolution permitting the use of force. The US House of Representatives narrowly defeated a concurrent resolution that would have authorized the air strikes (213–213)Footnote 65 and voted down a declaration of war by an overwhelming majority (427–2).Footnote 66 At the same time, those who opposed the intervention also could not garner enough support to pass resolutions condemning the strikes. Indeed, a concurrent resolution introduced in the House by Rep. Tom Campbell (R-California) directing the president to remove armed forces from Serbia within thirty days lost by a large majority.Footnote 67 The House did vote (249–180) to block funding for ground troops,Footnote 68 but Congress subsequently passed an emergency supplemental appropriations bill allocating $12.9 billion (US billion) for the campaign.Footnote 69

While Congress remained split, the aerial military strategy emboldened Clinton administration lawyers to justify the unilateral use of force as a legal matter. The Department of Justice Office of Legal Counsel (OLC) did not explicitly explain the constitutional basis of the president’s authority to conduct the Kosovo campaign in the absence of Congress’s authorization. Instead, an OLC memo articulated in general terms the purpose of the military action: “to demonstrate the seriousness of NATO’s purpose so that the Serbian leaders understand the imperative of reversing course; to deter an even bloodier offensive against innocent civilians in Kosovo; and, if necessary, to seriously damage the Serbian military’s capacity to harm the people of Kosovo.”Footnote 70 However, the memo did contend that the president had not run afoul of the sixty-day clock imposed by Section 5(b) of the War Powers Resolution. Although that provision stops the president from using force in “hostilities” without congressional approval, OLC argued that Congress had in fact authorized the use of force by funding the campaign, even though Section 8(a) of the War Powers Resolution purports to disallow such an approach.

Despite the ambiguity at the time, when OLC lawyers sought to explain the legal basis of President Barack Obama’s use of force in Libya in 2011 a decade and a half later, they drew a comparison to Kosovo. Specifically, they suggested that the low risk of US casualties in the Kosovo campaign justified, in part, exempting the president from needing to seek congressional approval either as a constitutional matter or within the framework of the War Powers Resolution. The memo reasoned that the Kosovo campaign “avoided the difficulties of withdrawal and risks of escalation that may attend commitment of ground forces – two factors that this Office has identified as ‘arguably’ indicating ‘a greater need for approval [from Congress] at the outset’.”Footnote 71 The memo also emphasized that, “as in prior operations conducted without a declaration of war or other specific authorizing legislation, the anticipated operations here served a ‘limited mission’.” Thus, OLC implied that Clinton never needed to get Congress’s blessing, in part because of the minimal risk of casualties. Of course, the casualty count was so low largely because harm to drones and contractors is not tallied in the official casualty figures.

B Libya

A decade after the Kosovo intervention, another US president ordered a military campaign to halt the atrocities of another dictator without first seeking congressional approval. When Libyan President Muammar Qadhafi attacked civilians protesting his iron-fisted rule, and continued to do so in flagrant defiance of UN Security Council condemnation,Footnote 72 President Obama joined a coalition of nations to initiate an air campaign to prevent further atrocities. In contrast to Kosovo, the Security Council had approved the multilateral intervention in Libya, imposing a no-fly zone and authorizing the use of force to protect civilians.Footnote 73 As Qadhafi’s forces were preparing to retake the city of Benghazi, the dictator pledged that his troops would show “no mercy and no pity” against protesters and that “[w]e will come house by house, room by room.”Footnote 74 Qadhafi, President Obama later noted, “compared [his people] to rats, and threatened to go door to door to inflict punishment… We knew that if we … waited one more day, Benghazi, a city nearly the size of Charlotte, could suffer a massacre that would have reverberated across the region and stained the conscience of the world.”Footnote 75

The US military intervention, dubbed Operation Odyssey Dawn, commenced on March 19, 2011.Footnote 76 The same day, France and the United Kingdom, which had played leading roles in advocating for military action and had cosponsored the Security Council resolutions, commenced Operation Harmattan and Operation Ellamy, respectively, in coordination with the United States.Footnote 77 US and coalition forces quickly established command of the air over Libya’s major cities, destroying portions of the Libyan air defense network and attacking pro-Qadhafi forces deemed to pose a threat to civilian populations.Footnote 78

At the time, President Obama emphasized that US military involvement in the operation would be limited. In his report to Congress on March 21, 2011, he explained that the use of military force in Libya served important US interests by preventing instability in the Middle East and preserving the credibility and effectiveness of the United Nations Security Council.Footnote 79 He also stated that the goal of US operations was to “set the stage” for further action by coalition partners.Footnote 80 The president pledged that no US ground forces would be deployed, except possibly for search-and-rescue missions, and he asserted that the risk of substantial casualties for US forces would be low.Footnote 81

Establishment of the no-fly zone over Libya proceeded relatively smoothly. One US aircraft was lost due to mechanical malfunction, but the crew was rescued. Estimates of the cost of the initial operation ranged between $400 million and $1 billion. NATO assumed control of military operations on March 30, 2011,Footnote 82 and international military operations concluded later that year, on October 31, after the death of Qadhafi, when the Security Council ended the mandate for military action.Footnote 83

Drones assumed an even larger role in Libya than they had during the Kosovo campaign. The technology of unmanned systems had evolved considerably. Drones now enhanced the Air Force’s capability to better gather information for targeting because of their greater ability to fly low for extended periods, hover in densely populated areas, and transmit high-quality information in real time.Footnote 84 This capacity increased the precision of conventional air power and helped reduce civilian casualties. Even more significantly, in addition to providing intelligence, drones could now themselves also drop bombs. The United States announced that it was sending its first armed Predator drones to the region in April 2011.Footnote 85 During the roughly seven-month air campaign, US unmanned systems launched 145 of the strikes on Libya, almost half of the overall total of US strikes, while also doing most of the spotting that enabled the manned strikes.Footnote 86 Moreover, even after NATO announced that the conflict was over in October 2011, the drones did not go home, but rather continued to fly combat air patrols, primarily for surveillance.Footnote 87

As in Kosovo, contractors also played a key role after the international air campaign ended. Because the new Libyan government expressed concerns about an extensive contractor presence, however, the contractor footprint was smaller and quieter.Footnote 88 The US State Department did not contract with well-known security firms such as Blackwater, a company that had guarded US diplomats in Iraq but earned a poor reputation after multiple abuse-of-force incidents, such as the notorious September 2007 killing of civilians in Baghdad’s Nisoor Square. Nevertheless, the US Embassy in Libya did employ contractors from lesser-known firms, some of which hired local nationals as employees.Footnote 89 The CIA also used contractors in Libya.Footnote 90 Indeed, in a brutal attack on September 11, 2012, militants killed not only the US ambassador, but also two American CIA contractors, Tyrone Woods and Glen Doherty.Footnote 91 Thus, while the contractor role in Libya may have been more muted, the combination of drones and contractors again enabled the military to shrink its visible image, just as it had in Kosovo.

This seemingly smaller footprint both emboldened the president politically to take action without congressional approval and lent credence to legal arguments that he was neither constitutionally nor statutorily required to obtain such approval. As in the Kosovo context, Congress did not authorize the military action, although debate within the legislature resulted in a mix of actions on several resolutions pointing in multiple directions. In the House of Representatives, two resolutions came to the floor on June 3. The first, introduced by Rep. Dennis Kucinich (D-Ohio) with Republican cosponsors, directed the removal of US armed forces from Libya within fifteen days, but it failed 148–265. The second, introduced by House Speaker John Boehner (R-Ohio), succeeded by a vote of 268–145. It noted that President Obama had “failed to provide Congress with a compelling rationale” for military activities in Libya and directed him to describe in detail within fourteen days US interests and objectives in Libya, as well as the reason why he did not seek authorization from Congress to use military force. Although not legally bound by the resolution, the president did submit a report within the requested time frame. On June 24, the House voted down (123–295) a resolution that would have authorized the military action, and rejected by a smaller margin (180–230) a measure that would have provided limited funding for the war. A Senate resolution put forward by Senator John Kerry (D-Massachusetts) and Senator John McCain (R-Arizona) on June 24 would have authorized the use of force (while prohibiting boots on the ground) and agreed with the president that the military intervention did not require congressional authorization under the Constitution or the War Powers Resolution.Footnote 92 That resolution was withdrawn without a vote.Footnote 93

Meanwhile, the president proceeded with the operation, while his lawyers made the case that, as a legal matter, “under these circumstances, the President had constitutional authority, as Commander-in-Chief and Chief Executive and pursuant to his foreign affairs powers, to direct such limited military operations abroad, even without prior specific congressional approval.”Footnote 94 More specifically, the OLC memo justified the use of force by arguing that the multilateral nature of the oprations and the reduced risk of casualties – made possible by drones and contractors – exempted the operation from any constitutional requirement that Congress declare war or explicitly authorize the use of force. The memo reasoned that a particular use of force is a war “for constitutional purposes” only if there are “prolonged and substantial military engagements, typically involving exposure of U.S. military personnel to significant risk over a substantial period.” In contrast, the military action in Libya, the memo argued, was “limited in scope and duration.” Again, the so-called limited scope was made possible by the expanded role of drones and contractors substituting for military personnel.

In addition to the constitutional arguments in the OLC memo, other administration lawyers (over OLC’s objections) also contended that the Libya campaign did not even fall within the War Powers Resolution’s sixty-day limit on engaging in “hostilities” absent congressional authorization. Crucial to their reasoning was the fact that manned planes had moved quickly into a mere supporting role, even though “unmanned forces” continued to carry out strikes up to the very day Qaddafi was killed. In other words, so the argument went, because US blood would not be at risk, it didn’t count as warfare.Footnote 95

C ISIS

The military engagements in the Balkans and Libya set the stage for the campaign against ISIS in Iraq and Syria. ISIS is a transnational Sunni Islamist insurgent and terrorist group that expanded its control over areas of northwestern Iraq and northeastern Syria beginning in 2013, threatening the security of both countries and drawing increased attention from the international community.Footnote 96 The group emerged against the backdrop of the brutal Syrian regime of President Bashir al-Assad, the disintegration of the country into civil war, and the sectarian strife within Iraq, where many segments of the Sunni population felt that they had not received adequate representation within the predominantly Shiite government.Footnote 97

In the face of ISIS military gains in Iraq and Syria, the United States launched an air campaign against the group beginning in August 2014. Drone strikes in this campaign have been significant. During the ten-month period from August 2014 to June 2015, for example, US and coalition forces used combat aircraft, armed unmanned aerial vehicles, and sea-launched cruise missiles to conduct more than 3,700 strikes in Iraq and Syria.Footnote 98 Further strikes have continued since that time.

The stated objective of these US strikes has evolved somewhat as circumstances have changed. Initially, the goal was to halt the advance of ISIS forces and reduce threats to American personnel and religious minorities in northern Iraq; subsequently, the objective included support for Iraqi military and Kurdish forces, with the aim of weakening the ability of ISIS to support its Iraq operation from within Syria. Other US strikes have targeted individuals belonging to the “Khorasan Group,” an Al Qaeda affiliate whose leadership is based in Pakistan.Footnote 99

Drones have played an even more significant part in the campaign against ISIS than they did in Libya. US Central Command has reported that drone strikes constituted about 15 percent of the overall number of strikes,Footnote 100 and drone surveillance capabilities enabled so-called eyes on the ground, particularly in denser urban areas. Indeed, demand for drones was so high and drone pilots became so overworked that in 2015 the US Air Force announced a crisis of drone “pilot fatigue.”Footnote 101

Contractor involvement has also been significant. While the number of military and security contractors has not swelled to levels witnessed during the previous phase of the conflicts in Iraq and Afghanistan,Footnote 102 US Central Command reported in July 2015 that the Department of Defense was employing 41,900 military contractors in the area within Central Command’s responsibility.Footnote 103 And this figure did not even include the State Department contractors who were providing services such as security to US diplomats, as the State Department does not release data on contractor numbers.Footnote 104

Contractors continue to provide extensive support to the drone operations themselves – performing maintenance on unmanned vehicles, loading bombs into them, analyzing the intelligence feeds they provide, piloting unarmed drones, and in some cases steering the takeoff and landing of armed drones.Footnote 105 And although contractors have not officially selected targets, some of their activities, such as intelligence analysis, have, at times, contributed to target selection. Certainly contractors were (and are) performing virtually the entire array of tasks associated with the operation of unmanned vehicles.

As in the Kosovo and Libya conflicts, the combined force of drones and contractors enabled the Obama administration to maintain the appearance of a small military footprint with minimal risk of harm to US troops. Indeed, President Obama repeatedly stressed that he would not deploy ground combat units to fight ISIS, maintaining that US troops could not fix the underlying political problems that ultimately caused the crisis.Footnote 106 While the president left the door open for the possibility of small special forces rescue missions and operations to target the ISIS leadership, he ruled out “enduring offensive ground combat operations.”Footnote 107

The Obama administration’s legal justification under domestic law for the military intervention rested on the preexisting Authorization to Use Force against Al Qaeda (and the Taliban) from 2001,Footnote 108 as well as the Authorization to Use Force in Iraq.Footnote 109 This legal theory, however, required the administration to draw a tenuous link between ISIS and Al Qaeda, two terrorist organizations that were literally fighting each other on the ground in Syria.Footnote 110 The administration sought a new authorization to use force, but action on that authorization stalled. Instead, members of Congress seemed content to acquiesce in this legal pretzel logic in order to avoid another vote.

However, even without new authorization from Congress, the precedent now exists for executive branch lawyers to contend that operations against ISIS (or similar operations elsewhere) might not require congressional authorization. To be sure, the Obama administration lawyers who supplied the legal reasoning for the Libya intervention would, in all likelihood, not have carried their arguments that far. Nonetheless, the legal groundwork now exists for the claim that a low risk of troop casualties, made possible by the involvement of contractors and autonomous weapons, could form the basis of military involvement of such “limited nature, scope, and duration” that it would not be big enough to trigger the need for congressional authorization.

The implications of this argument are profoundly unsettling for the historical constitutional tradition of “mutual participation” between the president and Congress in waging war.Footnote 111 To be sure, Congress’s abdication of its role and the corresponding swelling scope of presidential authority is a continuing storyline from the Korean War to the present.Footnote 112 Yet the force of new, increasingly automated military technologies, combined with growing military contracting, has arguably catapulted the phenomenon to another level. Not only have these new technologies and methods of warfare strengthened the executive’s political hand to use force unilaterally while keeping US military casualties low, but the twin trends of autonomous weapons and privatization have opened the door to legal claims that the use of force is so limited that congressional assent is neither constitutionally nor statutorily necessary. In so doing, these twin trends have profoundly upset the very architecture of US governance.

IV The International Humanitarian Law Criminal Accountability Framework

The combined impact of unmanned weaponry and military privatization not only destabilizes the constitutional and statutory separation of powers arrangements enshrined in US law, but also unsettles the framework of international humanitarian law, also known as the law of armed conflict. In particular, increasingly autonomous weaponry and growing privatization tend to spread responsibility for decision-making across a larger number of actors who do not fit neatly within either a military command structure or an ordered bureaucracy. Thus, as multiple actors work together to gather intelligence, make targeting decisions, and deploy weapons, the authority and responsibility for decisions involving violence are diffused and fragmented. Accordingly, if it turns out that the use of a weapon violates IHL, it is far more difficult even to determine who is responsible. In this new world of fragmented authority, our existing legal and bureaucratic processes are inadequate to provide sufficient mechanisms of accountability. As a result, we face potential difficulties in trying to ensure compliance with IHL norms.

Scholars and policy-makers have debated extensively whether the use of unmanned and autonomous weapons threatens fundamental IHL principles. For example, some have argued that the asymmetric harm such weapons can inflict flouts core principles of humanity that undergird IHL, or that the promise of precision that such weapons offer may be overstated.Footnote 113 In contrast, others have contended that such weapons are potentially more precise than human beings who pull triggers and might therefore provide an opportunity for more humane warfare, stripped of the irrationality, hot-blooded decision-making, and emotional toll of the battlefield.Footnote 114 Such weapons, according to this argument, might paradoxically lead to better effectuation of the IHL principles that lie at the heart of that body of law, such as distinction and proportionality.Footnote 115

Still others have emphasized that, regardless of whether or not unmanned and autonomous weapons might better implement substantive IHL principles, autonomy itself can pose serious problems for accountability.Footnote 116 Perhaps most significantly, these systems threaten the framework of individual criminal responsibility that undergirds all of IHL. From the Nuremberg trials of Nazi war criminals to proceedings before the International Criminal Court, a fundamental aspect of international humanitarian law is that perpetrators will be held individually responsible for egregious violations of the law of war that constitute war crimes. While such prosecutions are rare, they serve as core sanctions that ensure compliance with this body of law.

But whether it is individual criminal punishment or some other form of accountability, unmanned autonomous weapons pose problems for this framework. As a number of scholars have pointed out, in the case of truly autonomous systems, who will be responsible for the decision to strike?Footnote 117 In 2012, partly due to accountability concerns, the United States issued a temporary ban on fully autonomous systems.Footnote 118 Subsequently, policy-makers and scholars gathered at the United Nations in 2015 to discuss these issues.Footnote 119

Meanwhile, a rich debate has also emerged over the impact of military and security privatization on international humanitarian law and policy.Footnote 120 For example, some have called for an outright ban on the practice.Footnote 121 Others, including myself, have advocated for new means of regulation, such as the use of contracts and public-private accreditation regimes, that attempt to bring the public values embedded in IHL into this newly privatized realm.Footnote 122 Without such reforms, existing systems of accountability and oversight will be weak and ineffectual.

Yet few, if any, scholars have addressed the combined force of increasingly autonomous weaponry and privatization. Paired together, these trends significantly enhance the accountability and oversight problems each poses separately. Thus, my goal in this section is to break new ground by scrutinizing how these two phenomena intersect and to assess how that intersection could impact the potential for imposing accountability under IHL when serious violations occur.

Although much could be said about multiple forms of accountability, my focus here will be on individual criminal responsibility. In particular, my contention is that both privatization and the use of increasingly autonomous weapons fragment decision-making and bring it outside the ordinary bureaucratic chain of command. This fragmentation makes accountability harder to impose, because it becomes very difficult to hold individuals responsible for serious harms that occur. Thus, the use of these weapons by a military that has also outsourced multiple functions to private contractors presents distinct problems that add up to more than the combined impact of each of the two trends. In other words, the whole of the problem very likely is worse than the sum of its parts.

A Autonomous Weaponry and Individual Criminal Accountability

A growing body of scholarship highlights the difficulties in holding individuals criminally responsible for uses of unmanned and autonomous weapons that lead to significant violations of IHL. For example, Markus Wagner has observed that, if these weapons can effectively make decisions such as engaging in target selection, it will be very difficult to determine which individuals to hold responsible for those decisions, let alone fit the humans’ decisions into existing doctrinal frameworks.Footnote 123 If a soldier is monitoring the operation of a weapon that goes on a rampage and the soldier fails to stop it, should he or she be held responsible? Or does responsibility lie with the programmer who made it possible for the weapon to act in this way? Or the manufacturer? Or possibly even the military commander who approved the use of the weapon in the first place?

In a seminal article, Rebecca Crootof explained that a significant aspect of the problem flows from the doctrine of international criminal law itself, in particular the intent requirement for most war crimes.Footnote 124 War crimes usually must be committed “willfully,” which means that the accused must have either acted with the intent to commit a violation or acted recklessly. Thus, if autonomous weapons were used to commit war crimes, a prosecutor might demonstrate the requisite intent by proving that a software engineer had deliberately programmed the weapon to target civilians, or a commander had ordered them to be used in such a manner. But Crootof emphasizes that these are the “easy cases” and instead focuses on the hard case of “whether anyone might be accountable in the more complicated situation where no individual acts intentionally or recklessly, but an autonomous weapon system nonetheless takes action that constitutes a serious violation of international law.”Footnote 125 Assuming that “no one intended the violation or acted recklessly, no one can be held directly liable.”Footnote 126 Because of these difficulties, Crootof does not support criminalizing negligence, arguing that civil responsibility in tort is a more appropriate mechanism of accountability in such cases than criminal responsibility.

International criminal law does contain multiple doctrines that provide criminal accountability for participants in war crimes who do not actually pull the trigger. For example, the doctrine of command responsibility permits the imposition of liability on persons with authority over the acts of subordinates in some circumstances. The doctrine of aiding and abetting reaches those who may assist in the commission of a war crime. And the doctrines of complicity and joint criminal enterprise sweep broadly to cover all of those who agree to commit war crimes. These doctrines do not necessarily require all participants to have intended to commit war crimes.

Yet, as Heather Roff points out, these doctrines are premised on the notion that there is at least one individual who did possess the requisite intent, an observation that Crootof makes as well.Footnote 127 Thus, under the doctrine of command responsibility, a superior can be punished for the war crime of a subordinate if that superior has actual or constructive knowledge of the crime and effectively controls the subordinate. In other words, he or she need not have intended for the crime to be committed, but at least the subordinate must have possessed the requisite intent. In the case of a superior in charge of an autonomous weapon, it cannot be fairly said that the autonomous weapon possesses the requisite intent. Thus, merely negligent supervision could not clearly justify criminal punishment under a theory of command responsibility.Footnote 128

The problem depends in part on how one defines “autonomous,” which is the source of significant debate among scholars and policy-makers. The challenge of criminal accountability is particularly acute for fully autonomous weapons that can engage in independent decision-making. No such weapons are in operation, and the technology to implement this kind of autonomy in weapons systems may still be many years away. Nonetheless, the problem could still arise for a semi-autonomous system, as we will see below.

B Privatization and Individual Criminal Accountability

Privatization also undermines criminal accountability for war crimes, but in a slightly different way. When governments turn over military and security functions to armed contractors and authorize them to use force, there is, of course, a risk that those contractors could abuse the responsibility and commit criminal acts. To be sure, under well-established doctrines of international criminal law dating back to the Nuremberg trials of Nazis in the aftermath of World War II, non-state actors can be prosecuted for serious violations of the law of war during an armed conflict. As I have written elsewhere,Footnote 129 the mere fact that these contractors are private actors does not insulate them from war crimes prosecution.

Yet the fragmentation of decision-making within bureaucracies has long presented hurdles for such prosecutions. Notions of due process and fundamental justice in criminal proceedings tend to rest on principles of individual criminal responsibility and the opportunity to individually defend oneself in a fair proceeding. Guilt by association or group membership is antithetical to these principles. Yet, while individuals commit war crimes, in modern society they often do so within a much broader organizational context: as members of militaries, civilian governmental departments, private corporate contractors, terrorist organizations, or other groups. Thus, the person who pulls the trigger is often not the decision-maker. Subordinates may sometimes go rogue and act on their own, but at other times, they may be doing the dirty work for an organization’s leaders. At the same time, those leaders may not know of the subordinates’ specific actions, making it difficult to impose command responsibility. And, in between group leaders and trigger-pullers, other members of an organization may take small steps that facilitate or contribute to the commission of criminal acts; for example, a secretary may sign an order requisitioning the weapons used to target civilians, a budgeting official may allocate funds to purchase such weapons, and so on.

As noted above, international criminal law contains multiple doctrines that allow courts to convict individuals for war crimes and other atrocities even when they contribute to the commission of those crimes due to their role in larger organizations. Nevertheless, applying these doctrines remains fraught with difficulty. Perhaps the least controversial of the doctrines is the theory of command responsibility, whereby a superior with authority can be held responsible for the acts of a subordinate. Because of the intent requirement for both the subordinate and the superior, command responsibility fits most cleanly into traditional liberal conceptions of individual criminal responsibility. International courts and tribunals have deployed the doctrine to hold both military and civilian leaders responsible, and they have determined that formal legal authority is not necessary if the individual superior in question exerts de facto control over a subordinate.

Yet, privatization makes it far more difficult to impose even this less controversial version of criminal responsibility on the government actors who supervise contractors. This is because contractors often fall outside the military or bureaucratic chain of command, making it far more difficult to demonstrate that government actors exercised the requisite degree of authority and control to be criminally responsible themselves. For example, the fact that government actors may have generally supervised the large government contracts under which contractors operate would probably not be sufficient to impose command responsibility.

More broadly, the doctrine of command responsibility has never been able to comfortably encompass cases of fragmented responsibility, in which multiple actors together commit a wrong even if no one individual in the group intends the harm. Probably the most controversial and notable effort to address the problem of group-based contributions to war crimes took place during the prosecution of major Nazi war criminals before the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (IMT). There, prosecutors tackled the problem head-on by seeking to designate Nazi groups such as the Gestapo and the SS as criminal organizations.Footnote 130 Prosecutors had hoped to avoid the difficulty of proving the criminal responsibility of each individual within these organizations by persuading the IMT to deem these organizations criminal. Such a designation would have allowed subsequent proceedings to convict individuals for mere membership in these organizations. Relying on charter provisions that opened the door to organizational accountability,Footnote 131 the prosecution essentially argued that the entire Nazi state was a criminal operation: “We shall … trace for you the intricate web of organizations which these men formed and utilized to accomplish these ends. We will show how the entire structure of the offices and officials was dedicated to the criminal purposes and committed to the use of criminal methods planned by these defendants and their co-conspirators.”Footnote 132

The IMT rejected the prosecution’s broad theories, however, and took a much more limited approach to the question of the organizations’ criminality. Although the court did not throw out the conception of organizational criminality altogether, it defined quite narrowly the groups that could be deemed criminal, and concluded that only three of the six organizations qualified.Footnote 133 Moreover, the IMT struggled with the implications of a process that might lead to guilt by association and emphasized that “innocent persons” should not be punished.Footnote 134 Thus, the IMT concluded that a group could be deemed criminal only in the limited circumstances when it could be proved that group members were “bound together and organized for a common purpose” and the group was “formed or used in connection with the commission of crimes denounced by the Charter.”Footnote 135 The IMT further restricted the circumstances in which individuals could be convicted for membership in such associations, essentially crafting a requirement for an individualized finding of mens rea for each person accused of membership in a criminal organization.Footnote 136 Thus, while the tribunal recognized that group-based liability might be useful because of the challenges of bringing charges against each individual within a large organization,Footnote 137 the court was nevertheless reluctant to accept a broad theory of organizational responsibility because of the risks to fundamental due process in criminal prosecutions.

The Nuremberg Tribunal’s foray into organizational accountability has largely been viewed as a failure, certainly in comparison to its highly influential development of the substantive principle of individual criminal responsibility for war crimes and crimes against humanity. Indeed, the tribunal’s efforts to wrestle with the problem of organizational accountability highlights what David Luban has described as a core challenge of modern life: “the problem of moral responsibility in bureaucratic settings.”Footnote 138

Drawing on the work of Robert Conot and Hannah Arendt, Luban notes that part of the horror of Nazi atrocities stemmed from the organizational setting in which they took place. These were not the acts solely of evil masterminds or bloodthirsty gangsters. Rather, “through the fragmentation of authority and tasks, it was possible to fashion a murder machine.”Footnote 139 Luban cites Conot as observing that “[t]housands of people were involved, but each considered himself nothing but a cog in the machine and reasoned that it was the machine, not he, that was responsible.”Footnote 140 In Luban’s view, this “bureaucratic irresponsibility” is the “moral plague of modern life,” and he refers to Hannah Arendt’s insight that bureaucracy is “the latest and perhaps most formidable form of … dominion” because it is “the rule of an intricate system of bureaus in which no men, neither one nor the best, neither the few nor the many, can be held responsible, and which could be properly called rule by Nobody.”Footnote 141

Luban believes that the bureaucratic Nazi machine does not ultimately represent the most difficult version of this problem, however, because many of the participants could be said, at a minimum, to be “willfully” blind to their role. That is, they fit within relatively traditional conceptions of moral culpability and recognized criminal law concepts. To the extent that individual Nazi bureaucrats did not know about the final solution, for example, it was because they deliberately shielded themselves from that knowledge and therefore possessed some degree of intent. As Luban puts it,

the top Nazis may not have known what the inside of a death camp looked like, but they knew what the code name “Final Solution” meant. Lower level flunkies such as Ivan the Terrible, the notorious executioner at Treblinka, may not have known why they were gassing Jews, but they could not help but know that mass killing was mass murder. Whatever blindness such people allege is willful blindness.Footnote 142

The more difficult situation in which to assign moral culpability and impose criminal legal responsibility, however, is one in which each of the cogs in a bureaucratic machine is truly ignorant of the commission of atrocities. Such a situation may well be presented by the combination of automation and contracting. Individual contractors, operating outside of military hierarchies, are each responsible for one aspect of a drone’s construction, maintenance, and operation. Unlike the “willful blindness” described by Luban, these individuals may well be entirely ignorant of the larger purpose for which the drones are employed. Thus, automation and contracting together immensely complicate the search for moral and legal accountability within bureaucratic settings.

Subsequent proceedings before international criminal tribunals demonstrate the tensions inherent in the effort to impose criminal responsibility based on group membership, along with the challenges posed by war crimes committed within a bureaucratic setting more broadly. Arguing before these tribunals, prosecutors have used a variety of doctrines, including command responsibility, aiding and abetting, and joint criminal enterprise, to impose criminal responsibilities on individuals implicated in the commission of war crimes and other mass atrocities due to their roles in large, complex organizations. Yet most of these doctrines, as in the proceedings before the Nuremberg Tribunal, have retained a relatively traditional conception of individual criminal responsibility that is based on individual mens rea and individual culpability.

Thus, to the extent that such doctrines are predicated on individuals intentionally agreeing to and supporting criminal acts, they reflect a more traditional conception of individual responsibility. And when these doctrines have been applied more broadly and have attempted to sweep in a broader array of actors who may not have intended to commit or may not have truly participated in the underlying crime, critics have charged that these doctrines are antithetical to fundamental principles of individual criminal responsibility. For example, Allison Danner and Jenny Martinez have argued that these doctrines, “if not limited appropriately, have the potential to lapse into forms of guilt by association, thereby undermining the legitimacy and the ultimate effectiveness of international criminal law.”Footnote 143 With respect to joint criminal enterprise in particular, Danner and Martinez argue that international judges “should require that prosecutors demonstrate that each individual charged under a joint criminal enterprise theory made a substantial contribution to the fulfillment of the common objective of the enterprise” and that any form of the doctrine that tolerates a “reduced mens rea should not be used for specific intent crimes.”Footnote 144 With respect to command responsibility, they argue that “something more than ordinary negligence should remain the touchstone for criminal responsibility.”Footnote 145

Although these arguments make perfect sense from the traditional criminal law framework perspective, they may render many acts undertaken within bureaucratic institutions unaccountable, even when those acts represent tiny cogs in a bureaucratic machine that is committing grave atrocities. Moreover, in a world of increasingly automated weaponry and increasing military privatization, assigning traditional individual criminal responsibility may only become more difficult over time.

C The Combination of Autonomous Weaponry and Privatization

When an autonomous machine is injected into a bureaucratic system and then private contractors are hired to help operate it, individual criminal responsibility becomes even more challenging and problematic. Lethal force at the robotic hands of the autonomous weapon presents an even grimmer vision of Arendt’s “rule by no one,” probably far beyond even Arendt’s already dystopian imagination. Indeed, when information necessary for targeting decisions is sifted by private contractors, then the fragmentation of decision-making no longer even occurs inside the government, but now falls outside the bureaucracy itself. And when those contractors feed information into an autonomous system that is engaging in the targeting, the problem magnifies exponentially.

The threat is perhaps easiest to perceive when considering fully autonomous weapons systems that move, detect threats, and engage targets based on predetermined criteria. But because no fully autonomous weapons systems are currently operational (and some commentators question whether such technology is imminent) and because many governments have, for now, said they will not use them, I will focus instead on partially autonomous systems. These systems are preprogrammed to detect and strike certain categories of targets, but usually a human being remotely oversees the operation and can override the automated system.

One such example is the Israeli Harpy, which, when launched by a human operator, can detect an enemy radar system and autonomously dive-bomb and strike that target. If the Harpy killed a large number of civilians in a manner that could be said to violate the principle of proportionality, who could or should be held responsible? The human being with the responsibility to override the weapons system? The commander of the territory where the weapons system was deployed? The individuals who set policy for using the technology? The individuals who drafted the targeting criteria? The engineers who designed the weapons system to apply the targeting criteria? Anyone who supplied intelligence that fed into the weapons system and formed the basis for target selection? In the case of even partially autonomous systems, it is difficult to locate a responsible human agent.Footnote 146

Only human beings can be held criminally responsible for actions. But in this case, there is no clear human actor who bears full responsibility. Some of the people in the chain listed above might plausibly be tried, and the governments of the United States and the United Kingdom have said that the last human to make a decision regarding the operation of the weapon should be held responsible. Yet arguably this is inadequate, because no one person truly can be said to make that decision. As discussed above, the doctrine of command responsibility allows for superiors in the chain of command to be tried, but that theory is premised on the notion that the human being who actually pulled the trigger could also be tried for the same crime. Yet here there is no human being who can accurately be said to have pulled a trigger.

At its root, the problem is not the mere lack of a human agent. It is that autonomy – even partial autonomy – fragments the decision-making process, spreading the decision across a large number of individuals, thereby making it much harder to hold any one person responsible. And, of course, adding contractors to the mix further diffuses and breaks up the decision-making process. For example, as previously discussed, with many remotely operated weapons systems, such as drones, contractors are involved in supplying intelligence that leads to target selection as well as occasionally calling in targets from the ground. Is the intelligence-gathering that determines the targeting decision itself a targeting decision that implicates criminal responsibility? And does it matter that the contractor is not a state actor? In short, the existing legal doctrine is not equipped to cope with criminal responsibility in the case of automated and outsourced weapons systems.

V Conclusion

The purpose of this chapter has been to highlight the profoundly destabilizing impact of unmanned and autonomous weapons systems and privatization on both domestic and international law regulating the use of force abroad. These trends have emerged concurrently, and together they disrupt existing legal frameworks more than each would do separately. On the domestic front, unmanned and autonomous weaponry and privatization potentially alter the balance of power between the president and Congress by buttressing legal arguments that the use of force can be limited in ways that do not require congressional approval. Meanwhile, these trends also work together to put pressure on international humanitarian law, because they fragment and diffuse decision-making, thereby complicating efforts to impose individual accountability. Accordingly, it will be a core challenge for law and governance in the twenty-first century to evolve new legal regimes and new mechanisms of oversight and accountability to respond to the radically changing face of armed conflict.

Footnotes

2 Safeguarding Human Rights from Problematic Technologies

* The author assisted the South African legal team representing the Mazibuko applicants during 2006 and 2007 while a Fulbright Scholar at the Centre for Applied Legal Studies at the University of Witwatersrand, Johannesburg.

1 Founding Affidavit, Mazibuko and Others v. City of Johannesburg and Others (06/13865) [2008] ¶¶ 68–73.

2 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, art. 27(1) (“Everyone has the right to have access to … sufficient food and water.”).

3 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217A, December 10, 1948, art. 27(1) (“Everyone has the right … to share in scientific advancement and its benefits.”); International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A (XXI) December 16, 1966, art. 15(1)(b) (“the right of everyone … to enjoy the benefits of scientific progress and its applications”).

4 P. Bond and J. Dugard, “The Case of Johannesburg Water: What Really Happened at the Prepayment ‘Parish Pump’” (2008) 12 Law, Democracy, and Development 128; J. Dugard, “Choice from No Choice; Rights for the Left? The State, Law and the Struggle against Prepayment Water Meters in South Africa,” in S. Molta and A. G. Nilsen (eds.), Social Movements in the Global South: Dispossession, Development and Resistance (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011), p. 59.

5 A. Cronin et al., “A Review of Water and Sanitation Provision in Refugee Camps in Association with Selected Health and Nutrition Indicators – The Need for Integrated Service Provision” (2008) 6(1) Journal of Water and Health 118 at 2.

6 US Environmental Protection Agency, “Statistics and Facts,” www.epa.gov/watersense/statistics-and-facts.

7 Bond and Dugard, “The Case of Johannesburg Water” 1–28.

8 Mazibuko and Others v. City of Johannesburg and Others (06/13865) [2008] ZAGPHC 491, April 30, 2008 (High Court).

9 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 41. Here, Judge Tsoka referred to the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights’ guarantees of the right to an adequate standard of living and the right to health; General Comment No. 15 on the Right to Water, issued in 2002 by the UN Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights; the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child; the African Convention on the Rights of the Child; and the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights. For further background, see I. Winkler, The Human Right to Water: Significance, Legal Status, and Implications for Water Allocation (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2012).

10 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, art. 27(1).

11 Mazibuko (High Court), ¶ 126.

12 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 169–79.

13 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 86–87.

14 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 88–89.

15 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 90.

16 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 91–93.

17 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 94.

18 The order left ambiguous whether this was to be multiplied by the actual number of residents in a household, the average number of sixteen residents, or some other multiplier.

19 Mazibuko and Others v. City of Johannesburg and Others [CCT 39–09 2009] ZACC 28, October 8, 2009, ¶¶ 45–46 (Constitutional Court).

20 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 56–57.

21 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 57.

23 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 59–168.

24 Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 160–65.

25 Constitutional Court, Mazibuko, ¶ 153.

26 In July 2009, experts convened by UNESCO produced the Venice Statement on the Right to Enjoy the Benefits of Scientific Progress and Its Applications. In 2012, the UN Special Rapporteur in the field of cultural rights, Farida Shaheed, issued a report to the Human Rights Council that endorsed the view of recent scholarship conceiving of “the right to science” as a commitment to treating knowledge and technology as global public goods that must be made widely available. Report of the Special Rapporteur in the Field of Cultural Rights, Farida Shaheed, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/20/26 (May 14, 2012) (“Shaheed Report”) (citing L. Shaver, “The Right to Science and Culture” (2010) Wisconsin Law Review 121–85). In 2013, the UN Office of the High Commissioner on Human Rights hosted a highly generative academic seminar on this subject, convened at the UN headquarters in Geneva. Report on the Seminar on the Right to Enjoy the Benefits of Scientific Progress and Its Applications, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/26/19 (April 1, 2014). Another seminar was organized by Prof. Samantha Besson at the University of Freibourg, resulting in a special edition of the European Journal of Human Rights ([2015] European Journal of Human Rights, Special Issue, 403–580). The UN Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights has also taken early steps to develop a General Comment on the right to science.

27 Shaheed Report, ¶¶ 29, 74.

28 See, e.g., The Declaration on the Use of Scientific and Technological Progress in the Interests of Peace and for the Benefit of Mankind, G.A. Res. 3384 (XXX) (November 10, 1975) (“All States shall take appropriate measures to prevent the use of scientific and technological developments … to limit or interfere with the enjoyment of human rights and fundamental freedoms… All States shall take effective measures, including legislative measures, to prevent and preclude the utilization of scientific and technological achievements to the detriment of human rights and fundamental freedoms and the dignity of the human person.”). That Declaration also mentioned, while giving lesser emphasis to, positive aspects of the right to science, e.g., “all states shall take measures to ensure that scientific and technological achievements satisfy the material and spiritual needs for all sectors of the population”; “[a]ll States shall co-operate in the establishment, strengthening and development of the scientific and technological capacity of developing countries”; and “the state shall take measures to extend the benefits of science and technology to all strata of the population.” Footnote Ibid., ¶¶ 3, 5, 6.

29 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, G.A. Res. 2200A (XXI), Mar. 23, 1976, art. 7 (“No one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment. In particular, no one shall be subjected without his free consent to medical or scientific experimentation.”)

30 National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research (Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office, 1978).

31 Footnote Ibid., p. 1.

32 UNESCO, Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights, October 19, 2005; see also M. Kruger et al., Research Ethics in Africa: A Resource for Research Ethics Committees (Stellenbosch: Sun Press, 2014) (discussing the Belmont principles as “foundational” and citing the Belmont Report repeatedly).

33 National Commission, The Belmont Report, p. 2.

34 Footnote Ibid., p. 3.

35 Footnote Ibid., p. 2.

36 Footnote Ibid., p. 6.

38 Footnote Ibid., p. 10.

40 Universal Declaration on Bioethics, art. 5.

41 National Commission, Belmont Report, p. 11; see also Universal Declaration on Bioethics, art. 6.

42 Universal Declaration on Bioethics, art. 6.

43 National Commission, The Belmont Report, p. 6.

44 Founding Affidavit, Mazibuko, ¶¶ 79–92.

45 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 94.

46 Mazibuko (High Court), ¶ 153. The white author of the Constitutional Court opinion likely reminded Judge Tsoka of precisely this patronization in concluding that the policy was not “unfairly discriminatory” because the discriminatory impact upon black households could not be judged as harmful, given that Phiri’s indigent consumers were, if anything, better off avoiding the “worrying measures” of debt accumulation and collection. Mazibuko (Constitutional Court), ¶¶ 148–57.

47 National Commission, Belmont Report, p. 7.

48 Universal Declaration on Bioethics, art. 4.

49 National Commission, Belmont Report, p. 17.

50 Footnote Ibid., p. 18.

52 Universal Declaration on Bioethics, art. 8.

53 Constitution of South Africa, art. 12(2)(c).

3 Climate Change, Human Rights, and Technology Transfer Normative Challenges and Technical Opportunities

1 This includes such tools that were historically used by countries to promote their development and move up the technology value chain: patent working requirements, patent revocations, antitrust measures, reduction of patent terms, and joint venture requirements for foreign direct investment. For a full listing and discussion of these measures, see D. Shabalala, Climate Change, Technology Transfer and Intellectual Property: Options for Action at the UNFCCC (Maastricht: Maastricht University, 2014), pp. 263–97.

2 Transfer happens when technology is first transferred from one country to another and is then adopted by public or private firms, being built into either their means of producing products and services or into the products and services themselves. It involves transfer of goods, craft knowledge, and scientific and technical information.

3 See United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (“UNFCCC”), New York, May 9, 1992, in force March 21, 1994, 1771 UNTS 107, arts. 4.1(c), 4.3, 4.5, and 4.7.

4 Climate mitigation refers to efforts to reduce or prevent emissions of greenhouse gases through development, deployment, and use of technologies or changes in economic behavior. United Nations Environment Programme, “Climate Change Mitigation,” www.unep.org/climatechange/mitigation/.

5 Kyoto Protocol to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (“Kyoto Protocol”), Kyoto, Japan, December 10, 1997, in force February 16, 2005, 2303 UNTS 148.

6 See UNFCCC, art. 4.1(c).

7 There is, of course, a direct link between mitigation and adaptation. The faster and more extensively greenhouse gas mitigation action takes place, the lower the likely cost of action to address adaptation will be. As I note below, some impacts will be unavoidable no matter how much mitigation takes place.

8 The historical responsibility of developed countries amounts to almost 79 percent of all greenhouse gas emissions in the period from 1850 to 2011. See Centre for Global Development, “Developed Countries Are Responsible for 79 Percent of Historical Carbon Emissions,” August 8, 2015, www.cgdev.org/media/who-caused-climate-change-historically (citing CO2 emissions excluding LUCF [CAIT v2.0]).

9 The OECD consists of thirty-five industrialized countries, primarily in Europe and North America, but also encompassing Australia, Israel, Japan, Korea, Mexico, New Zealand, and Turkey. See OECD, “Members,” www.oecd.org/about/membersandpartners/. The group is largely self-selected, not simply as an outcome of the discourse of the postcolonial international political order but also as a creation of membership requirements. The members are defined as “developed economies,” with three members defined as “emerging economies”: Chile, Mexico, and Turkey.

10 See, e.g., L. Wolf-Phillips, “Why Third World?: Origin, Definition and Usage” (1987) 9(4) Third World Quarterly 1311–27 at 1313.

11 C. S. Clapham, Third World Politics: An Introduction (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1985), p. 1.

12 See, e.g., E. Ferrill, “Clearing the Swamp for Intellectual Property Harmonization: Understanding and Appreciating the Barriers to Full TRIPS Compliance for Industrializing and Non-Industrialized Countries” (2006) 15 University of Baltimore Intellectual Property Law Journal 137–70 at 141.

13 UN General Assembly Resolution 3201 (S-VI), Declaration on the Establishment of a New International Economic Order, U.N. Doc. A/RES/S-6/3201 (May 1, 1974) (“NIEO”). For a fuller discussion, see also M. Bedjaoui, Towards a New International Economic Order (New York: Holmes and Meier, 1979).

14 “The greatest and most significant achievement during the last decades has been the independence from colonial and alien domination of a large number of peoples and nations which has enabled them to become members of the community of free peoples. Technological progress has also been made in all spheres of economic activities in the last three decades, thus providing a solid potential for improving the well-being of all peoples. However, the remaining vestiges of alien and colonial domination, foreign occupation, racial discrimination, apartheid, and neo-colonialism in all its forms continue to be among the greatest obstacles to the full emancipation and progress of the developing countries and all the peoples involved.” NIEO, art. 1.

15 See UN Development Policy and Analysis Division, “LDC Identification Criteria & Indicators,” www.un.org/development/desa/dpad/least-developed-country-category/ldc-criteria.html.

16 See Committee for Development Policy and the UN DESA, Handbook on the Least Developed Country Category: Inclusion, Graduation and Special Support Measures, 2nd ed. (Geneva: United Nations, 2015), pp. 1112.

17 See World Bank, “Country and Lending Groups,” https://datahelpdesk.worldbank.org/knowledgebase/articles/906519.

18 World Trade Organization, “Who are the developing countries in the WTO?” www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/devel_e/d1who_e.htm.

19 Joint Declaration of the Seventy-Seven Developing Countries Made at the Conclusion of the United Nations Conference on Trade and Development, U.N. Doc. E/CONF. 46/138 (1965).

20 See The Group of 77 at the United Nations, www.g77.org/doc/members.html.

21 “Party Groupings,” United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change, http://unfccc.int/parties_and_observers/parties/negotiating_groups/items/2714.php.

22 See United Nations Development Program, “Internal Human Development Indicators,” http://hdr.undp.org/en/countries.

23 For example, looking at BRICS, India and South Africa have a medium HDI, whereas Brazil and China have a high HDI. Russia has a very high HDI.

24 BRICS is a group of countries – Brazil, Russia, India, China, and, more recently, South Africa – identified by Jim O’Neill of Goldman Sachs as having significant economic growth rates and increasing influence in the global economy. J. O’Neill, “Building Better Global Economic BRICS,” Goldman Sachs Economic Research Group Global Economics Paper no. 66 (London: Goldman Sachs Economic Research Group, 2001), p. 4.

25 See, e.g., World Trade Organization, “Special and differential treatment provisions,” www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/devel_e/dev_special_differential_provisions_e.htm.

27 See Committee for Development Policy and the UN DESA, Handbook on the Least Developed Country Category.

28 World Trade Organization, “Least-Developed Countries,” www.wto.org/english/thewto_e/whatis_e/tif_e/org7_e.htm.

29 NIEO.

30 See, e.g., D. C. Tipps, “Modernization theory and the comparative study of national societies: A critical perspective” (1973) 15(2) Comparative Studies in Society and History 199226 at 208–10.

31 See, e.g., T. Smith, “The Underdevelopment of Development Literature: The Case of Dependency Theory” (1979) 31(2) World Politics 247–88 at 249.

32 NIEO, art. 4(e).

33 Footnote Ibid. art. 4(f).

34 Footnote Ibid. art. 4(j).

35 Footnote Ibid. art. 4(p).

36 This discussion on definitions is drawn from D. Shabalala et al., “Climate Change, Technology Transfer and Human Rights,” Working Paper, CIEL/ICHRP (2010), www.ichrp.org/files/papers/181/138_technology_transfer_UNFCCC.pdf.

37 United Nations Division of Sustainable Development, Agenda 21: The Rio Declaration on Environment and Development, Adopted at United Nations Conference on Environment and Development (UNCED), Rio de Janeiro, June 3–14, 1992 (Geneva: United Nations 1992), http://sustainabledevelopment.un.org/index.php?page=view&nr=23&type=400&menu=35.

38 For more on this history, see P. G. Sampath and P. Roffe, “Unpacking the International Technology Transfer Debate: Fifty Years and Beyond,” Working Paper (International Centre for Trade and Sustainable Development, 2012).

39 UNCTAD, “Compendium of International Arrangements on Transfer of Technology: Selected Instruments – Relevant Provisions in Selected International Arrangements Pertaining to Transfer of Technology,” UNCTAD/ITE/IPC/Misc.5 (Geneva: UNCTAD, 2001), www.unctad.org/en/docs//psiteipcm5.en.pdf.

40 See Sampath and Roffe, “Unpacking the International Technology Transfer Debate” at 26.

41 Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works, Berne, Switzerland, September 9, 1886; revised at Berlin, November 13, 1908; completed at Berne, March 20, 1914; revised at Rome, June 2, 1928; at Brussels, June 26, 1948; at Stockholm, July 14, 1967; at Paris, July 24, 1971; and amended September 28, 1979, 1161 UNTS 3.

42 Paris Convention for the Protection of Industrial Property, Paris, March 20, 1883; as revised at Brussels, December 14, 1900; at Washington, DC, June 2, 1911; at The Hague, November 6, 1925; at London, June 2, 1934; at Lisbon, October 31, 1958; and at Stockholm, July 14, 1967; and as amended September 28, 1979, 828 UNTS 107.

43 As was established at the 1964 UNCTAD Conference. See Joint Declaration of the Seventy-Seven Developing Countries, U.N. Doc. E/CONF. 46/138 (1965).

44 Marrakesh Agreement establishing the World Trade Organization, Marrakesh, April 15, 1994, in force January 1, 1995, 1867 UNTS 4 (“WTO Agreement”).

45 Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property (“TRIPS”), Annex 1C to the Marrakesh Agreement establishing the World Trade Organization (“WTO Agreement”), Marrakesh, April 15, 1994, in force January 1, 1995, 1867 UNTS 4.

46 Identification as a developing country is a matter of self-selection. See World Trade Organization, “Least Developed Countries,” www.wto.org/english/thewto_e/whatis_e/tif_e/org7_e.htm.

47 TRIPS, art. 65.

48 “Extension of the Transition Period under Article 66.1 of the TRIPS Agreement for Least Developed Country members for Certain Obligations with respect to Pharmaceutical Products: Decision of the Council for TRIPS of November 6, 2015,” WTO, IP/C/73 (November 6, 2015).

49 See Shabalala, Climate Change, Technology Transfer and Intellectual Property, p. 363.

50 There is a basic philosophical and political objection to this concept that is an issue of attributability and knowledge-intent that I believe elides the broader international law presumption that successor states take on the obligations of previous states in terms of financial obligation. This was the basis on which developing countries took on international intellectual property obligations that have prevented them from accessing technology and knowledge held in developed economies. A concise and clear discourse on this can be found in D. Bell, “Global Climate Justice, Historic Emissions, and Excusable Ignorance” (2011) 94(3) The Monist 391411.

51 UNFCCC, Annex I.

53 UNFCCC, Annex II. The countries are: Australia, Austria, Belgium, Canada, Denmark, European Economic Community, Finland, France, Germany, Greece, Iceland, Ireland, Italy, Japan, Luxembourg, Netherlands, New Zealand, Norway, Portugal, Spain, Sweden, Switzerland, Turkey, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland, and United States of America.

54 M. Ge, J. Friedrich, and T. Damassa, “6 Graphs Explain the World’s Top 10 Emitters,” World Resources Institute, November 25, 2014, https://wri.org/blog/2014/11/6-graphs-explain-world%E2%80%99s-top-10-emitters.

55 See, e.g., European Commission, The EU’s New Generalised System of Preferences (GSP) (Brussels: European Commission, 2012), http://trade.ec.europa.eu/doclib/docs/2012/december/tradoc_150164.pdf.

56 Footnote Ibid., p. 3. The EU GSP excludes upper-middle-income countries from its coverage.

57 See C. R. Sunstein, “Of Montreal and Kyoto: A Tale of Two Protocols” (2007) 31 Harvard Environmental Law Review 165 at 2–3. The Kyoto Protocol only applied to implementation of Annex I country obligations to quantified economy-wide emissions reductions.

58 Expert Group on Technology Transfer, Report on the review and assessment of the effectiveness of the implementation of Article 4, paragraphs 1(c) and 5, of the Convention, FCCC/SBI/2010/INF.4, May 10, 2010.

59 M. Le Page, “Was Kyoto climate deal a success? Figures reveal mixed results,” New Scientist: Daily News, June 14, 2016, www.newscientist.com/article/2093579-was-kyoto-climate-deal-a-success-figures-reveal-mixed-results/. While the study examined notes that all Kyoto parties (excluding signatories US and Canada) had met their commitments, the article points out that much of that was attributable to already existing reduction in the economies in transition, the financial crisis, and purchase of carbon credits on trading markets in developing countries. Nevertheless, it does seem clear that while the overall aim of the Kyoto Protocol was met, there had long been arguments that the countries had failed.

60 See M. Khor, Climate Change, Technology and Intellectual Property: Context and Recent Negotiations (Geneva: South Centre, 2012), p. 1.

61 Summary of the Thirteenth Conference of Parties to the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change and Third Meeting of Parties to the Kyoto Protocol, December 3–15, 2007, Earth Negotiations Bulletin 12(354), December 18, 2007, p. 15, www.iisd.ca/climate/cop13/.

62 The Paris Agreement was signed in December 2015 as an agreement to succeed the Kyoto Protocol and the Copenhagen Accord, under which countries agreed to reduce their greenhouse gas emissions. The Paris Agreement was adopted as a decision of the UNFCCC parties rather than a protocol or a treaty, so as to avoid the domestic ratification obligations of some countries regarding formal international agreements. See Report of the Conference of the Parties on Its Twenty-First session, Held in Paris from November 30 to December 13, 2015: Decision 1/CP.21, U.N. Docs. FCCC (FCCC/CP/2015/10/Add.1) (January 29, 2016), http://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2015/cop21/eng/10a01.pdf.

63 Nationally determined contributions are the voluntary pledges made by countries on the extent to which they will reduce their emissions.

64 Paris Agreement, art. 4.

65 Footnote Ibid., art. 3.

66 Footnote Ibid., art. 9(1). (“Developed country Parties shall provide financial resources to assist developing country Parties with respect to both mitigation and adaptation in continuation of their existing obligations under the Convention.”)

67 See UNEP, Towards a Green Economy: Pathways to Sustainable Development and Poverty Eradication (Nairobi: UNEP, 2011), p. 19.

68 G. McGranahan et al., “The Rising Tide: Assessing the Risks of Climate Change and Human Settlements in Low Elevation Coastal Zones” (2007) 19(1) Environment and Urbanization 1737 at 18.

69 Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Climate Change 2014: Synthesis Report. Contribution of Working Groups I, II and III to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Geneva: IPCC, 2014), p. 50.

71 For example, looking just at mitigation scenarios, the IEA projected that from 2010–2020, more than $2.3 trillion (US trillion) annually would need to be invested, the majority of that private flows. The share of developing countries was $1.3 trillion annually, of which China represented $500 billion. In contrast to the scale of projected need, total investment flows in 2010 and 2011 were $247 billion and $260 billion, respectively. See IEA, Table 4.3, Energy Technology Perspectives 2012 (Paris: OECD/IEA, 2012), p. 139.

72 IPCC, Climate Change, p. 40.

73 Footnote Ibid., p. 82.

74 Footnote Ibid., pp. 78–79.

76 For a full list, see the tables in Shabalala, Climate Change, Technology Transfer and Intellectual Property, p. 59.

77 IEA, Energy Technology Perspectives 2012, p. 11.

78 Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, Climate Change, p. 51.

79 The Cancun Agreements: Outcome of the work of the Ad Hoc Working Group on Long-Term Cooperative Action under the Convention, Decision 1/CP.16, FCCC/CP/2010/7/Add.1 (2010), ¶ 14(c), http://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2010/cop16/eng/07a01.pdf#page=4.

80 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 14(d).

81 See Green Climate Fund, Investment Framework, GCF/B.07/06 (May 9, 2014), p. 9. www.greenclimate.fund/documents/20182/24943/GCF_B.07_06_-_Investment_Framework.pdf/dfc2ffe0-abd2-43e0-ac34-74f3b69764c0.

82 Footnote Ibid., p. 9.

83 Green Climate Fund, Decisions of the Board – Ninth Meeting of the Board, 24–26 March 2015. Annex III: Initial Investment Framework: Activity-Specific Sub-Criteria and Indicative Assessment Factors, GCF/B.09/23 (April 16, 2015), www.greenclimate.fund/documents/20182/239759/Investment_Criteria.pdf/771ca88e-6cf2-469d-98e8-78be2b980940.

84 See Least Developed Countries Expert Group, National Adaptation Plans: Technical Guidelines for the National Adaptation Plan Process (Bonn: UNFCCC, 2012) pp. 43, 94, www.unfccc.int/files/adaptation/cancun_adaptation_framework/application/pdf/naptechguidelines_eng_high__res.pdf

85 Adaptation Fund, Climate Adaptation Finance: Direct Access (November 2016), www.adaptation-fund.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/11/Direct-Access-English-Nov2016-WEB.pdf.

86 See Adaptation Fund, Guidance on Accreditation Standards, www.adaptation-fund.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/10/Guidance-on-Accreditation-Standards.pdf.

87 Paris Agreement, arts. 7.6, 7.9(c), 11.1.

88 Shardul Agrawala (ed.), Bridge Over Troubled Waters: Linking Climate Change and Development (Paris: OECD Environment Directorate, 2005), pp. 1617.

89 The Stern Review (sometimes called the Stern Report) was led by Sir Nicholas Stern, former chief economist at the World Bank. It proved highly influential in generating consensus around the idea that taking action on climate would not have a negative impact on economic growth. N. Stern et al., The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).

90 Footnote Ibid., p. 94.

91 UNEP, Towards a Green Economy, p. 38; see also Stern, The Stern Review, p. 95.

92 Stern, The Stern Review, pp. 38–40.

93 Footnote Ibid., pp. 208–09.

94 Footnote Ibid., p. 430.

95 United Nations Development Program, Human Development Report 2000 (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), p. 2, http://hdr.undp.org/sites/default/files/reports/261/hdr_2000_en.pdf; see also B. Hamm, “A Human Rights Approach to Development” (2001) 23(4) Human Rights Quarterly 1005–31 at 1011; A. Cornwall and C. Nyamu-Musembi, “Putting the ‘Rights-Based Approach’ to Development into Perspective” (2004) 25(8) Third World Quarterly 1415–37 at 1417.

96 See, e.g., Human Development Report 2000, p. 2; Hamm, “A Human Rights Approach to Development” at 1016.

97 Footnote Ibid., pp. 22–23.

98 Footnote Ibid., p. 23.

99 Footnote Ibid., pp. 178, 186.

100 I recognize that even this categorization of traditional and newer rights is not uncontested, but it is the fact of contestation that I am focused on; i.e., those rights about which there exists a minimal amount of contestation as to their existence and for which the scope has been elaborated by treaty bodies and other relevant institutions. As such, I do not address the right to development or the right to energy, for example, both of which would provide much stronger purchase for justifying unilateral action to access mitigation technologies.

101 Some arguments for mitigation arise from a claim that there is a broad “right to energy” that requires direct access to the means of generating it. In that sense, energy-generating technologies that do not create GHG emissions then become a necessity for fulfilling the right, a direct claim on renewable technologies. As noted above, this is a less developed right within traditional human rights discourse and remains contested, which is why I exclude it from the analysis in this chapter. See International Council on Human Rights Policy (“ICHRP”), Beyond Technology Transfer: Protecting Human Rights in a Climate-Constrained World (Geneva: International Council on Human Rights Policy, 2011), p. 25, www.ichrp.org/files/reports/65/138_ichrp_climate_tech_transfer_report.pdf.

102 See M. Limon, “Human Rights and Climate Change: Constructing a Case for Political Action” (2009) 33 Harvard Environmental Law Review 439–76 at 444; see also ICHRP, Beyond Technology Transfer; E. Caesans et al., Climate Change and the Right to Food: A Comprehensive Study (Berlin: Heinrich Boll Stiftung, 2009); M. Darrow et al., Human Rights and Climate Change: A Review of the International Legal Dimensions (Washington, DC: World Bank, 2011); J. H. Knox, “Climate Change and Human Rights Law” (2009) 50(1) Virginia Journal of International Law 163218; J. H. Knox, “Linking Human Rights and Climate Change at the United Nations” (2009) 33 Harvard Environmental Law Review 477–98; S. Humphreys (ed.), Human Rights and Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009).

103 Frequently Asked Questions on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, OHCHR Fact Sheet 33 (Geneva: Office of the United National High Commissioner for Human Rights, 2008), www.ohchr.org/Documents/Publications/FactSheet33en.pdf.

104 Economic and Social Council, United Nations Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (22nd Session, Geneva, April 25, 2000), The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health, U.N. Doc. E/C, December 4, 2000 (“General Comment 14”).

105 IPCC, Climate Change, p. 69.

108 Economic and Social Council, Committee on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (29th session, Geneva, November 11–29, 2002), Substantive Issues Arising in the Implementation of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights; General Comment No. 15 (2002), The Right to Water (arts. 11 and 12 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights), U.N. Doc. E/C.12/2002/11.

109 IPCC, Climate Change, p. 51.

112 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, December 10, 1948, U.N. G.A. Res. 217 A (III), art. 25 (right to adequate standard of living, including food); International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, December 16, 1966, 993 UNTS 3 (1976), arts. 11.1 and 11.2; Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women, December 18, 1979, 1249 UNTS 13 (1981), art. 12 (adequate nutrition during pregnancy and lactation).

113 K. A. Baumert et al., Navigating the Numbers: Greenhouse Gas Data and International Climate Policy (Washington, DC: World Resources Institute, 2005) p. 85, www.wri.org/publication/navigating-numbers.

114 IPCC, Climate Change, p. 51.

116 See Hamm, “A Human Rights Approach to Development” at 1011; Cornwall and Nyamu-Musembi, “Putting the ‘Rights-Based Approach’ to Development into Perspective” at 1417.

117 Appliances make up a significant portion of global electricity end use. Increased efficiency and use of best available technologies have large GHG emissions-reduction potential and are considered low-hanging fruit. See UNEP, Towards a Green Economy, p. 343.

4 Judging Bioethics and Human Rights

1 C. Thompson, Good Science: The Ethical Choreography of Stem Cell Research (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2013), p. 25.

2 Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine (Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine, as amended) (Oviedo Convention), opened for signature April 4, 1997, entered in force January 12, 1999, ETS 164, Art. 28.

3 UNESCO Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights (adopted by acclamation on October 19, 2005, by the General Conference). For commentary, see, e.g., H. A. M. J. ten Have and M. S. Jean (eds.), The UNESCO Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights (Paris: UNESCO, 2009).

4 See, e.g., UNESCO International Declaration on Human Genetic Data (adopted by acclamation on October 16, 2003, by the General Conference); Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights (adopted by acclamation on November 11, 1997, by the General Conference, and endorsed by the UN General Assembly in 1998).

5 Report of the Special Rapporteur in the Field of Cultural Rights, Farida Shaheed, ¶ 53, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/20/26 (May 14, 2012).

6 Council of Europe, The Conscience of Europe: 50 Years of the European Court of Human Rights (London: Third Millennium Publishing, 2010).

7 Convention for Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (European Convention on Human Rights, as amended), adopted November 4, 1950, entered into force September 3, 1953, ETS 5.

8 For a science and technology studies reading of several of these cases, see T. Murphy and G. Ó Cuinn, “Taking Technology Seriously: STS as a Human Rights Method,” in M. Flear et al. (eds.), European Law and New Health Technologies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), pp. 285308.

9 AI is the process whereby sperm from a partner or a donor is placed inside a woman’s uterus; IVF is the process of fertilizing an egg, or eggs, outside the human body; PGD is a process used alongside IVF, whereby diagnostic testing is performed on an embryo to determine if it has inherited a serious genetic condition.

10 Evans v. United Kingdom, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 6339/05 (Grand Chamber, April 10, 2007).

11 Dickson v. United Kingdom, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 44362/04 (Grand Chamber, December 4, 2007).

12 S.H. and Others v. Austria, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 57813/00 (Grand Chamber, November 3, 2011).

13 Costa and Pavan v. Italy, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 54270/10 (August 28, 2012).

14 Knecht v. Romania, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 10048/10 (October 2, 2012).

15 Parrillo v. Italy, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 464470/11 (Grand Chamber, August 27, 2015).

16 Adapted from S. S. Silbey and P. Ewick, “The Architecture of Authority: The Place of Law in the Space of Science,” in A. Sarat, L. Douglas, and M. Umphrey (eds.), The Place of Law (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2003), pp. 75108.

17 See the incisive account in J. Montgomery, “Bioethics as a Governance Practice” (2016) 24 Health Care Analysis 323.

18 For a sense of the field, see, e.g., H. Kuhse and P. Singer (eds.), Bioethics: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999); B. Steinbock (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Bioethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). Both public and global health have become prominent in recent years, and climate change is the focus of at least one recent book: C. C. Macpherson (ed.), Bioethical Insights into Values and Policy: Climate Change and Health (Basel: Springer, 2016).

19 See Montgomery, “Bioethics as a Governance Practice.”

20 See J. Montgomery, “Reflections on the Nature of Public Ethics” (2013) 22 Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 921 (contrasting ethical deliberation in the academy with its counterpart in the public domain).

21 For a more complete list, it would be important to add the ad hoc groupings that tend to be convened in the wake of scandal or of growing public concern about a specific aspect of medicine, science, or technology.

22 See generally A. Nolan, R. Freedman, and T. Murphy (eds.), The UN Special Procedures System (Antwerp: Brill, 2017).

23 See, e.g., D. J. Rothman, “The Origins and Consequences of Patient Autonomy: A 25 Year Retrospective” (2001) 9 Health Care Analysis 255–64.

24 See, e.g., C. A. Heimer and J. Petty, “Bureaucratic Ethics: IRBs and the Legal Regulation of Human Subjects Research” (2010) 6 Annual Review of Law and Social Science 601–26.

25 See, e.g., P. Farmer and N. G. Campos, “New Malaise: Bioethics and Human Rights in the Global Era” (2004) 32 Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 243–51.

26 For a concise, engaging account of responses to the UNESCO Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights, see R. Ashcroft, “The Troubled Relationship between Bioethics and Human Rights,” in M. D. A. Freeman (ed.), Law and Bioethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), pp. 3151.

27 American Association for the Advancement of Science, Science and Human Rights Coalition, Intersections of Science, Ethics and Human Rights: The Question of Human Subjects Protection: Report of the Science Ethics and Human Rights Working Group (February 2012) p. 2.

28 See, e.g., J. P. Ruger, Health and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010).

29 See, e.g., J. Harris, “Taking the Human out of Human Rights” (2011) 20 Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 920.

30 See, e.g., J. Montgomery, “Law and the Demoralisation of Medicine” (2006) 26 Legal Studies 185210.

31 If we take case law as a measure of interest, apart from the six ECHR cases, there is just one further case: Artavia Murillo et al. (“In Vitro Fertilization”) v. Costa Rica, Judgement, Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 257 (November 28, 2012), a decision of the Inter-American Court in which Costa Rica’s complete ban on IVF was held to be contrary to the American Convention on Human Rights.

32 A shift may be under way. See UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, General Comment no. 22 on the Right to Sexual and Reproductive Health (art. 12), U.N. Doc. E/C.12/GC/22, ¶ 21 (May 2, 2016) (“The failure or refusal to incorporate technological advances and innovations in the provision of sexual and reproductive health services, such as medication for abortion, assisted reproductive technologies and advances in the treatment of HIV and AIDS, jeopardizes the quality of care.”).

33 See, e.g., Karen Noelia Llantoy Huamán v. Peru, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/85/D/1153/2003 (Nov. 22, 2005); Tysiąc v. Poland, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 5410/03 (March 20, 2007); R.R. v. Poland, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 27617/04 (May 26, 2011).

34 Interestingly, the court’s research division produced a report that collects and classifies what it describes as the court’s bioethics cases. See Research Division, “Bioethics and the case-law of the Court” (2009, updated 2012), www.coe.int/t/dg3/healthbioethic/texts_and_documents/Bioethics_and_caselaw_Court_EN.pdf.

35 See, e.g., Evans, ¶ 81; Parrillo, ¶¶ 169, 174.

36 S and Marper v. United Kingdom, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. Nos. 30562/04 and 30566/04 (Grand Chamber, December 4, 2008) ¶ 112; see also T. Murphy and G. Ó Cuinn, “Works in Progress: New Technologies and the European Court of Human Rights” (2010) 10 Human Rights Law Review 601–38.

37 S.H. and Others, joint dissenting opinion of Judges Tulkens, Hirvelä, Lazarova Trajkovska, and Tsotsoria.

38 See, e.g., Evans, ¶ 71.

39 S.H. and Others, ¶ 82; Dickson, ¶ 66.

40 See, e.g., C. Thompson, Making Parents: The Ontological Choreography of Reproductive Technologies (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005); S. Franklin and C. Roberts, Born and Made: An Ethnography of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2006); S. Franklin and M. C. Inhorn (eds.), “Symposium: IVF – Global Histories” (2016) 2 Reproductive Biomedicine & Society Online 1136. From a legal perspective, see K. Lõhmus, Caring Autonomy: European Human Rights Law and the Challenge of Individualism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015).

41 See, e.g., S.H. and Others, ¶ 92; Knecht, ¶ 59.

42 Costa and Pavan, ¶ 53–54 (emphasis added).

43 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 57 (emphasis added).

44 T. M. Gammeltoft and A. Wahlberg, “Selective Reproductive Technologies” (2014) 43 Annual Review of Anthropology 201–16 at 201.

45 Franklin and Roberts, Born and Made; see generally I. Karpin and K. Savell, Perfecting Pregnancy: Law, Disability, and the Future of Reproduction (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2012); R. Mykitiuk and I. Karpin, “Fit or Fitting In: Deciding against Normal When Reproducing the Future” (2017) 31 Continuum 341–51.

46 Mennesson v. France, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 65192/11 (June 26, 2014); see also Labassee v. France, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 65941/11 (June 26, 2014).

47 Foulon and Bouvet v. France, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. Nos. 9063/14 and 10410/14 (July 21, 2016).

48 Paradiso and Campanelli v. Italy, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 25358/12 (Grand Chamber, January 24, 2017).

49 For a broader international human rights perspective on surrogacy, see J. Tobin, “To Prohibit or Permit: What Is the (Human) Rights Response to the Practice of International Commercial Surrogacy?” (2014) 63 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 317–52.

50 Paradiso and Campanelli, concurring opinion of Judges De Gaetano, Pinto de Albuquerque, Wojtyczek, and Dedov, ¶ 7; see also the separate concurring opinion of Judge Dedov.

51 Paradiso and Campanelli, ¶ 203.

52 See, e.g., Vo v. France, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 53924/00 (Grand Chamber, July 8, 2004) at ¶¶ 82, 85. Art. 2 provides, inter alia, that “Everyone’s right to life shall be protected by law.” In X v. United Kingdom, No. 8416/79, Commission decision of May 13, 1980, Decisions and Reports (DR) 19, p. 244, the former Commission ruled out recognition of an absolute right to life of the fetus under art. 2 (at p. 252, ¶ 19).

53 Vo v. France, ¶ 84. Immediately prior to this, the court noted that although there is no European consensus on the status of the embryo and/or fetus, “they are beginning to receive some protection in the light of scientific progress and the potential consequences of research into genetic engineering, medically assisted procreation or embryo experimentation.”

54 Evans, ¶ 56.

55 Parrillo, concurring opinion of Judge Pinto de Albuquerque, ¶ 31.

56 Costa and Pavan, ¶ 62.

57 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 59 (emphasis added).

58 Parrillo, ¶ 167; see also Costa and Pavan, ¶ 59.

59 Parrillo, ¶¶ 158 and 174, respectively.

60 Footnote Ibid. See also the concurring opinion of Judge Pinto de Albuquerque at n. 32, describing the applicant’s property claim as inconsistent with her right-to-private-life claim.

61 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 215.

62 See, e.g., Evans, ¶ 78 (recalling the words of Lord Bingham in the UK case Quintavalle: “Where … there is no consensus within the member States of the Council of Europe either as to the relative importance of the interest at stake or as to how best to protect it, the margin will be wider. This is particularly so where the case raises complex issues and choices of social strategy: the authorities’ direct knowledge of their society and its needs means that they are in principle better placed than the international judge to appreciate what is in the public interest.”); see also Knecht, ¶ 59.

63 For discussion, see M. K. Land, “Justice as Legitimacy in the European Court of Human Rights,” in H. Cohen et al. (eds.), Legitimacy and International Courts (New York: Cambridge University Press, forthcoming); A. Legg, The Margin of Appreciation in International Human Rights Law: Deference and Proportionality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012); G. Letsas, “The ECHR as a Living Instrument: Its Meaning and Legitimacy,” in A. Føllesdal, B. Peters, and G. Ulfstein (eds.), Constituting Europe: The European Court of Human Rights in a National, European and Global Context (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), pp. 106–41.

64 Parrillo, ¶ 169.

65 Evans, ¶ 81 (noting also that these issues arise “against a background of fast moving medical and scientific developments”); see also S.H. and Others, ¶ 94; Knecht, ¶ 59; Parrillo, ¶¶ 169, 174.

66 Evans, ¶ 77.

68 Dickson, ¶ 78.

69 See below text at Footnote nn. 90Footnote 93.

70 Parrillo, ¶ 174; see also the concurring opinion of Judge Pinto de Albuquerque, ¶ 34.

71 Costa and Pavan, ¶ 68; see also S.H. and Others, ¶ 97.

72 See, e.g., S.H. and Others, ¶ 100.

73 Evans, joint dissenting opinion, ¶ 12; see also Paradiso and Campanelli, concurring opinion of Judge Dedov: “For the first time when ruling in favour of the respondent State the Court has placed greater emphasis on values than on the formal margin of appreciation.”

74 A, B and C v. Ireland, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 25579/05 (Grand Chamber, December 16, 2010).

75 S.H. and Others, ¶ 96.

77 See also Vo, concurring opinion of Judge Costa, joined by Judge Traja.

78 C. E. Schneider, “Bioethics in the Language of Law” (1994) 24 The Hastings Center Report 1622 at 16–17.

79 For discussion in the context of the cloning report produced by President George W. Bush’s Council on Bioethics, see J. Lezaun, “Self-Contained Bioethics and the Politics of Legal Prohibition” (2008) 4 Law, Culture and Humanities 323–38.

80 Mount Isa Mines Ltd v. Pusey (1970) 125 CLR 383, at 395.

81 See, e.g., Evans, ¶ 82; S.H. and Others, ¶ 100.

82 Evans, ¶ 84.

83 Footnote Ibid. ¶ 89; S.H. and Others, ¶ 110.

84 S.H. and Others, ¶ 110.

85 Footnote Ibid ¶ 100.

86 Footnote Ibid. See also Dickson, in which the court determined that the applicants’ interest in becoming genetic parents had not been given due weight; the relevant policy on prisoner access to assisted insemination imposed an undue “exceptionality” burden on the applicants; there was no evidence that the minister responsible weighed different legitimate interests, or assessed proportionality in fixing the policy; and because the policy was not part of primary legislation, the legislature also had not engaged in weighting or assessment.

87 Evans, ¶ 89.

88 Parrillo, ¶ 188.

89 S.H. and Others, ¶ 113.

90 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 114.

91 S.H. and Others, joint dissenting opinion of Judges Tulkens, Hirvelä, Lazarova Trajkovska, and Tsotsoria, ¶ 13.

92 S.H. and Others, ¶ 74.

93 For discussion, see E. Jackson et al., “Learning from Cross-Border Reproduction” (2017) 25 Medical Law Review 2346.

94 S.H. and Others, ¶ 118.

95 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 103.

96 Footnote Ibid., ¶ 114. For a bioethical view on the case, see, e.g., W. V. Hoof and G. Pennings, “The Consequences of S.H. and Others v. Austria for Legislation on Gamete Donation in Europe: An Ethical Analysis of the European Court of Human Rights Judgments” (2012) 25 Reproductive BioMedicine Online 665–69.

97 Evans, ¶ 86.

98 Parrillo, ¶¶ 184–88.

99 See generally M. Saul, “The European Court of Human Rights’ Margin of Appreciation and Processes of National Parliaments” (2015) 15 Human Rights Law Review 745–74.

100 S.H. and Others, ¶ 105.

101 Knecht, ¶ 60.

102 Costa and Pavan, ¶ 66.

103 See C. McCrudden, “The Pluralism of Human Rights Adjudication,” in L. Lazarus, C. McCrudden, and N. Bowles (eds.), Reasoning Rights: Comparative Judicial Engagement (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2014), pp. 327.

104 Article 14’s nondiscrimination guarantee is “parasitic,” i.e., it only prohibits discrimination in the enjoyment of other Convention rights. Recently, however, the European Court of Human Rights has been developing this right by reference to views on substantive equality from other courts and in scholarship; see S. Fredman, “Emerging from the Shadows: Substantive Equality and Article 14 of the European Convention on Human Rights” (2016) 16 Human Rights Law Review 273301.

105 See Goodwin v. United Kingdom, Eur. Ct. H.R., App. No. 28957/95 (Grand Chamber, July 11, 2002).

106 See S. H. Vauchez, “More Women – But Which Women? The Rule and the Politics of Gender Balance at the European Court of Human Rights” (2015) 26 European Journal of International Law 195221.

107 S.H. and Others, joint dissenting opinion of Judges Tulkens, Hirvelä, Lazarova Trajkovska, and Tsotsoria. Women judges were part of the majority opinion, but the dissent was authored exclusively by women.

108 See J. Harrington, Towards a Rhetoric of Medical Law (London: Routledge, 2016).

109 See L. Oja and A. E. Yamin, “‘Woman’ in the European Human Rights System: How Is the Reproductive Rights Jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights Constructing Narratives of Women’s Citizenship?” (2016) 32 Columbia Journal of Gender and Law 6295.

110 See, e.g., M. Ford, “Evans v. United Kingdom: What Implications for the Jurisprudence of Pregnancy?” (2008) 8 Human Rights Law Review 171–84.

111 See, e.g., Lõhmus, Caring Autonomy; J.-P. Costa, “European Dignity and the European Court of Human Rights,” in C. McCrudden (ed.), Understanding Human Dignity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), pp. 393402; C. McCrudden, “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation” (2008) 19 European Journal of International Law 655724.

112 R. Niezen and M. Sapignoli (eds.), Palaces of Hope: The Anthropology of Global Organizations (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2017).

5 Drones, Automated Weapons, and Private Military Contractors Challenges to Domestic and International Legal Regimes Governing Armed Conflict

* Thanks to Bryan Cenko and Jiyoon Moon for useful research assistance.

1 For a discussion of these systems, see text and notes below.

2 J. Elsea, Legal Issues Related to the Lethal Targeting of U.S. Citizens Suspected of Terrorist Activities (CRS Legal Memorandum) (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2012), https://perma.cc/M26G-PR2W.

3 See, e.g., J. Daskal, “The Geography of the Battlefield: A Framework for Detention and Targeting Outside the Hot Conflict Zone” (2013) 161(5) University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1165–234 (surveying approaches of legal scholars); A. Hudson, “Beyond the Drone Debate: Should US Military and CIA Be Judge, Jury, and Executioner?” Truthout, June 2, 2015, https://perma.cc/8EE4-4FEK (discussing reactions by the legal world, noting that Philip Alston, Christof Heyns, and Naz Modirzadeh have condemned drone strikes as outside the norms of international humanitarian law).

4 See, e.g., M. O’Connell, “Unlawful Killing with Combat Drones: A Case Study of Pakistan 2004–2009,” in S. Bonitt (ed.), Shooting to Kill: The Law Governing Lethal Force in Context (London: Hart Publishing, 2012) (arguing that drone strikes are not a lawful use of force, that there is no armed conflict in Pakistan, and that drones are ineffective at killing only the intended target); see also Daskal, “The Geography of the Battlefield.”

5 For example, some suggest that tallies undercount civilian casualties and that civilians are being unnecessarily sacrificed in failed attempts to reach terrorists. See, e.g., C. Friedersdorf, “Flawed Analysis of Drone Strike Data Is Misleading Americans,” The Atlantic (July 18, 2012), https://perma.cc/PEY3-DTLB; “You Never Die Twice: Multiple Kills in the US Drone Program,” Reprieve, https://perma.cc/KVY6-8UZ8. Others argue that the numbers of civilian casualties have dropped as targeting technologies have improved. See P. Bergen and J. Rowland, “Civilian casualties plummet in drone strikes,” CNN, July 14, 2012, https://perma.cc/ZT4X-8M6G. Overall, the New America Foundation has calculated that Pakistani casualties ranged between 2,003 and 3,321 from 2004 to April 2013. See P. Bergen, Drone Wars: The Constitutional and Counterterrorism Implications of Targeted Killing: Testimony presented before the U.S. Senate Committee on the Judiciary, Subcommittee on the Constitution, Civil Rights and Human Rights, 113th Cong. (2013) (testimony of Peter Bergen, director of the National Security Studies Program, New America Foundation), https://perma.cc/64HV-B9AE. In Yemen, where the number of drone strikes has increased, estimates of civilian casualties in 2013 range from 467 to 674, the vast majority of which occurred under the Obama administration. See Bergen, Drone Wars. In late 2013, a drone strike mistakenly attacked a wedding party in Yemen, killing numerous unarmed civilians. See J. Serle, “American drone suspected in wedding-day massacre,” Salon, December 16, 2013, https://perma.cc/FWF6-87FJ. And in April 2015, the United States government was forced to admit that two civilians had been killed as a result of a mistaken drone strike. See J. Diamond, “U.S. drone strike accidentally killed 2 hostages,” CNN, April 23, 2015, https://perma.cc/S6KF-2E73.

6 See generally R. Sparrow, “War Without Virtue?” in B. Strawser (ed.), Killing by Remote Control (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013) (questioning the effects drone warfare will have on the military); B. Strawser, “Moral Predators: The Duty to Employ Uninhabited Aerial Vehicles” (2010) 9(4) Journal of Military Ethics 342–68 (arguing that drones are justified because they allow for greater protection of the military, providing that the drones do not interfere with the military’s ability to make just judgment calls); J. McMahan, “The Ethics of Killing in War” (2004) 114(4) Ethics 693733 (arguing that combatants fighting with an unjust cause require no reciprocity morally, so the drone program violates no ethics); J. McMahan, “On the Moral Equality of Combatants” (2006) 14(4) Journal of Political Philosophy 377496 (same).

7 Memorandum for the Attorney General re: Applicability of Federal Criminal Laws and the Constitution to Contemplated Lethal Operations Against Shaykh Anwar al-Aulaqi (Washington, DC: Office of Legal Counsel, 2010), https://perma.cc/AKQ5-GBVQ; see also Daskal, “The Geography of the Battlefield.”

8 See, e.g., D. Avant, The Market for Force: The Consequences of Privatizing Security (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005); L. Dickinson, Outsourcing War and Peace: Preserving Public Values in a World of Privatized Foreign Affairs (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2011); S. McFate, The Modern Mercenary: The Rise of the Privatized Military Industry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014); P. Singer, Corporate Warriors: The Rise of the Privatized Military Industry (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2007).

9 Transforming Wartime Contracting: Controlling Costs, Reducing RiskFinal Report to Congress (Arlington, VA: Commission on Wartime Contracting, 2011).

11 Dickinson, Outsourcing War and Peace; see also discussion below.

12 See J. Levs, “CNN Explains: U.S. Drones,” CNN, February 8, 2013, https://perma.cc/QUK5-UH6M; J. Gertler, U.S. Unmanned Aerial Systems (CRS Report No. R42136) (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2012), https://perma.cc/HS6H-UU9A.

13 U.S. Unmanned Systems Integrated Roadmap (fiscal years 2009–2034) (Washington, DC: US Department of Defense, 2009), p. 2, https://perma.cc/T88M-BYMA; Statement of Commander Gerald Lloyd J. Austin III before the House Armed Services Committee, 114th Cong. (2015), p. 41, https://perma.cc/M856-L7VL; see also Bergen, Drone Wars, p. 12 (chart outlining the differences between the number of air strikes and drone strikes comparing 2002 through 2013).

14 “Understanding Drones,” Friends Committee on National Legislation, https://perma.cc/9AV8-VWTP (drawing numbers from the 2016 budget and military reports).

15 Statement of Commander Gerald Lloyd J. Austin III; C. Whitlock, “How crashing US drones are exposing secrets about US war operations,” The Washington Post, March 25, 2015, https://perma.cc/SP5F-S88P.

16 D. Cloud, “Civilian contractors playing key roles in U.S. drone operations,” Los Angeles Times, December 29, 2011, https://perma.cc/6VSZ-P3M3.

17 A. Sundby, “CIA Hired Blackwater to Arm Afghan Drones,” CBS News, August 21, 2009, https://perma.cc/6PSU-GGQL; J. Risen and M. Mazzetti, “C.I.A. Said to Use Outsiders to Put Bombs on Drones,” The New York Times, August 20, 2009, www.nytimes.com/2009/08/21/us/21intel.html; Cloud, “Civilian Contractors.”

18 K. D. Clanahan, “Drone-Sourcing? United States Air Force Unmanned Aircraft Systems, Inherently Governmental Functions, and the Role of Contractors” (2012) 22 Federal Circuit Bar Journal, https://perma.cc/C238-2JVA; A. Fielding-Smith et al., “Revealed: Private firms at heart of US drone warfare,” The Guardian, February 12, 2015, https://perma.cc/XG4Q-XVKL; see also A. Fielding-Smith and C. Black, “Pentagon’s ‘Insatiable Demand’ for Drone War Intelligence,” The Bureau of Investigative Journalism, July 30, 2015, https://perma.cc/F95V-6SZT (describing the many layers of a drone mission, including the number of people reviewing the instructions, relaying information, and operating the chain of command).

19 Cloud, “Civilian Contractors”; Fielding-Smith et al., “Revealed.”

20 See Fielding-Smith et al., “Revealed”; A. Fielding-Smith and C. Black, “Civilians who are drone pilots’ extra eyes,” The Guardian, August 2, 2015.

21 Fielding-Smith et al., “Revealed.”

22 D. Priest, “NSA growth fueled by need to target terrorists,” The Washington Post, July 21, 2013, https://perma.cc/4JYS-BJQ6.

23 Fielding-Smith and Black, “Pentagon’s ‘Insatiable Demand’.”

24 “International Humanitarian Law and the Challenges of Contemporary Armed Conflicts,” Report of the 31st International Conference of the Red Cross and Red Crescent (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 2011), p. 39, https://perma.cc/ML3F-RUZB. Other organizations have defined autonomous weapons differently. For example, The US Department of Defense (DoD) distinguishes between fully and semi-autonomous weapon systems based on the machine’s ability to make an autonomous choice. It defines fully autonomous weapon system as a “weapon system that, once activated, can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human operator.” See “DoD Directive on Autonomy in Weapon Systems,” ICRAC, November 27, 2012, https://perma.cc/U46R-9WUS. Human Rights Watch, by contrast, focuses on human involvement, classifying autonomous weapons as either “human-in-the-loop weapons,” “human-on-the-loop weapons,” or “human-out-of-the-loop weapons.” Human-in-the-loop weapons are “robots that can select targets and deliver force only with a human command,” while human-on-the-loop weapons are “robots that can select targets and deliver force under the oversight of a human operator who can override the robots’ actions.” Finally, human-out-of-the-loop weapons are “capable of selecting targets and delivering force without any human input or interaction.” B. Docherty, “Losing Humanity: The Case against Killer Robots,” Human Rights Watch, November 19, 2012, p. 2, https://perma.cc/N77J-EASX. The United Nations defines autonomous weapons as systems that “once activated, can select and engage targets without further intervention by a human operator.” Report of the Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial, Summary or Arbitrary Executions, Christof Heyns, U.N. Doc. A/HRC/23/47 (April 9, 2013).

25 Footnote Ibid., p. 39; see also “Autonomous weapons: States must address major humanitarian, ethical challenges,” International Committee of the Red Cross, February 9, 2013, https://perma.cc/PD33-Z5M7.

26 P. Scharre and M. Horwoit, “An Introduction to Autonomy in Weapon Systems,” Center for a New American Security (February 13, 2015), https://perma.cc/3BDX-SGW6.

27 These countries are: Australia, Bahrain, Belgium, Canada, Chile, China, Egypt, France, Germany, Greece, India, Israel, Japan, Kuwait, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Norway, Pakistan, Poland, Portugal, Qatar, Russia, Saudi Arabia, South Africa, South Korea, Spain, Taiwan, the United Arab Emirates, the United Kingdom, and the United States. Footnote Ibid.

28 Scharre and Horwoit, “An Introduction to Autonomy in Weapon Systems,” pp. 8–10.

32 See, e.g., P. Jones, “Aegis Combat System’s Newest Baseline Demonstrates Over the Horizon Capability in Series of Three Tests,” Lockheed Martin, July 8, 2014, https://perma.cc/APE6-5YUL; “Patriot Missile Long-Range Air-Defence System, United States of America,” army-technology.com, https://perma.cc/3JUS-FZE7; “Terminal High Altitude Area Defense, United States of America,” army-technology.com, https://perma.cc/T88S-Y4NG; “Taranis is an unmanned combat aircraft system advanced technology demonstrator programme,” BAE Systems, https://perma.cc/K3J8-46AJ.

33 S. J. Freedberg Jr., “X-47B Drone & Manned F-18 Take Off & Land Together in Historic Test,” Breaking Defense, August 17, 2014, https://perma.cc/5JZE-9NHR.

34 For example, Raytheon received a $115.5 million contract in 2014 to “remanufacture, overhaul and provide upgrades” to the MK 15 Phalanx system. “Raytheon awarded $115.5 million Phalanx upgrade contract,” Raytheon, June 11, 2014, https://perma.cc/DA5P-U8MS.

35 “Northrop wins US Army’s C-RAM contract,” army-technology.com, January 31, 2012, https://perma.cc/WH37-44ZM.

36 “Raytheon receives $109 million contract for Patriot Air and Missile Defense System: US and international Patriot partners strengthen defense against evolving threats,” Raytheon, September 10, 2014, https://perma.cc/B462-8D4Q.

37 “Aegis Combat System’s Newest Baseline.”

38 “Northrop Wins US Army’s C-RAM Contract.”

39 “NBS MANTIS Air Defence Protection System, Germany” army-technology.com, https://perma.cc/Y49B-FHEC.

40 US Const., art. I, § 8, cl. 11.

41 US Const., art. I, § 8, cls. 12–13.

42 US Const., art. I, § 2.

43 Compare the Prize Cases, 67 U.S. (2 Black) 635 (1863) (upholding the constitutionality of President Lincoln’s unilateral decision to impose naval blockade during the Civil War, when Congress was not in session) with Little v. Barreme, 6 U.S. (2 Cranch) 170 (1804) (concluding that a US naval captain’s seizure of a ship sailing from a French port during the naval war with France was unjustified because Congress had only authorized seizures of ships sailing to French ports).

44 The United States has not formally declared war since World War II. See Joint Resolution Declaring That a State of War Exists Between the Government of Rumania and the Government and the People of the United States and Making Provisions to Prosecute the Same, ch. 325, 56 Stat. 307 (June 5, 1942) (last declaration of war by the United States).

45 See, e.g., L. Meeker, “The Legality of United States Participation in the Defense of Viet-Nam” (1966) 54 Department of State Bulletin 474, reprinted in (1966) 75(7) Yale Law Journal 1085–108; J. Yoo, “The Continuation of Politics by Other Means: The Original Understanding of War Powers” (1996) 84(2) California Law Review 167305.

46 See, e.g., H. Koh, The National Security Constitution (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990); D. Barron and M. Lederman, “The Commander in Chief at the Lowest Ebb – Framing the Problem, Doctrine, and Original Understanding” (2008) 121(3) Harvard Law Review 689804.

47 War Powers Resolution, 50 U.S.C. §§ 1541–48 (1973); see P. Holt, The War Powers Resolution (Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research, 1978).

48 Joint Resolution to use the United States Armed Forces against those responsible for the recent attacks launched against the United States, Pub. L. No. 107–40, § 2(a), 115 Stat. 224 (2001).

49 Authorization for Use of Military Force Against Iraq Resolution of 2002, Pub. L. No. 107–243, 116 Stat. 1498 (2002).

50 See President William Jefferson Clinton, “Statement on Kosovo,” March 24, 1999; President William Jefferson Clinton, “Letter to Congressional Leaders Reporting on Airstrikes Against Serbian Targets in the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia (Serbia and Montenegro)” (1999) 35 Weekly Compilation of Presidential Documents 527, https://perma.cc/ZQ2Q-U8SK; see also “The Kosovo Air Campaign: Operation Allied Force,” North Atlantic Treaty Organization, November 11, 2014, https://perma.cc/ESU5-4C27.

51 Clinton, “Letter to Congressional Leaders.”

52 S. Bowman, Kosovo and Macedonia: U.S. and Allied Response (CRS Issue Brief) (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2003), https://perma.cc/VDP5-M25F.

55 President William Jefferson Clinton, Address on the Kosovo Agreement, June 10, 1999, https://perma.cc/F99V-DCMJ.

56 Human Rights Watch, The Crisis in Kosovo (2000), https://perma.cc/MBX4-7M3P.

57 Report to Congress: Kosovo Operation Allied Force After-Action Report (Department of Defense, 2000), https://perma.cc/VF2L-NH99.

59 Footnote Ibid.; see also E. Becker, “Military Leaders Tell Congress of NATO Errors in Kosovo,” The New York Times, October 15, 1999.

60 Department of Defense, Report to Congress (describing statements of Pentagon officials that drones provided “indispensable” assistance in US air campaign).

61 Footnote Ibid., p. 116.

62 M. Schwartz and J. Church, Department of Defense’s Use of Contractors to Support Military Operations: Background, Analysis and Issues for Congress (Congressional Research Service, 2013), https://perma.cc/JUT9-6JY8.

63 Department of Defense, Report to Congress.

64 See R. Fontaine and J. Nagl, “Contractors in American Conflicts: Adapting to a New Reality,” Center for a New American Security, December 16, 2009, https://perma.cc/V4RP-HVSH; see also “Contingency Contracting throughout U.S. History,” Office of Defense Procurement and Acquisition Policy, https://perma.cc/W588-NBWB.

65 H.J. Res. 44, 106th Cong. (1999), 145 Cong. Rec. H2441 (daily ed. April 28, 1999); Footnote ibid., H2451-52 (recording vote).

66 145 Cong. Rec. H2474 (daily ed. April 28, 1999); Footnote ibid. at H2440-41 (recording vote).

67 H. Con. Res. 82, 106th Cong. (1999), 145 Cong. Rec. H2414 (daily ed. April 28, 1999) (reprinting H. Con. Res. 82); Footnote ibid. at H2426-27 (recording vote).

68 H.R. 1569, 106th Cong. (1999), 145 Cong. Rec. H2400 (reprinting measure); Footnote ibid. at H2413-14 (recording votes).

69 H.R. 1664, 106th Cong. (1999), 145 Cong. Rec. H2634 (daily ed. May 4, 1999); see also A. Taylor, “Paying for the Kosovo Air War: How Much Is Too Much?,” CQ Weekly, May 1, 1999, p. 1014. Following a floor debate on May 6, the House passed H.R. 1664 the same day by a vote of 311–105. 145 Cong. Rec. H2895 (daily ed. May 6, 1999).

70 “Authorization for Continuing Hostilities in Kosovo” (2000) 24 Opinions of the Office of Legal Counsel 327, https://perma.cc/C52J-TSA7; see also “Proposed Deployment of United States Armed Forces into Bosnia,” 19 Opinions of the Office of Legal Counsel 327 at 333, https://perma.cc/9V49-4FEE.

71 “Authority to Use Military Force in Libya,” 35 Opinions of the Office of Legal Counsel 1 at 13, https://perma.cc/9A2C-56XS.

72 See, e.g., Security Council Res. 1970, U.N. Doc. S/RES/1970 (February 26, 2011), https://perma.cc/QAR9-6VLR (“condemning the violence and use of force against civilians” and “deploring the gross and systematic violation of human rights” in the country); “In Swift, Decisive Action, Security Council Imposes Tough Measures on Libyan Regime, Adopting Resolution 1970 in Wake of Crackdown on Protesters,” UN Security Council Press Release SC/10187/Rev. 1 (February 26, 2011), https://perma.cc/BKQ7-99CH.

73 See Security Council Res. 1973, U.N. Doc. S/RES/1973 (March 17, 2011), https://perma.cc/65UX-XLFC; “Security Council Approves ‘No-Fly Zone’ Over Libya, Authorizing ‘All Necessary Measures’ to Protect Civilians, by Vote of 10 in Favour with 5 Abstentions,” UN Security Council press release SC/10200 (March 17, 2011), https://perma.cc/63RT-SJAX.

74 See D. Bilefsky and M. Landler, “Military Action against Qaddafi Is Backed by U.N.,” The New York Times, March 18, 2011, p. A1.

75 The White House, “Remarks by the President in Address to the Nation on Libya,” Press Release, March 28, 2011, https://perma.cc/2UU6-F6M6.

76 J. Gertler, Operation Odyssey Dawn (Libya): Background and Issues for Congress (CRS Report No. R41725) (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2011), https://perma.cc/74WT-WJN4.

79 President Barack Obama, Letter from the President regarding the commencement of operations in Libya, March 21, 2011, https://perma.cc/2HAL-P93Q.

81 Footnote Ibid.; see also “Authority to Use Military Force in Libya.”

82 Gertler, Operation Odyssey Dawn.

83 “Security Council votes to end Libya operations,” BBC News, October 27, 2011, https://perma.cc/7WZZ-SCHX.

84 See C. Pellerin, “Gates: Obama OKs Predator Strikes in Libya,” Department of Defense News, April 21, 2011, https://perma.cc/56SW-YTJ9; see generally J. Walsh, The Effectiveness of Drone Strikes in Counterinsurgency and Counterterrorism Campaigns (Carlisle, PA: Strategic Studies Institute and US Army War College Press, 2013).

85 See Pellerin, “Gates: Obama OKs Strikes in Libya.”

86 See S. Ackerman, “Libya: The Real U.S. Drone War,” Wired, October 20, 2011, https://perma.cc/24XG-JYRB; C. Woods and A. Ross, “Revealed: US and Britain Launched 1,200 Drone Strikes in Recent Wars,” The British Bureau of Investigative Journalism, December 4, 2012, https://perma.cc/T787-QL6U.

87 See S. Ackerman, “U.S. Drones Never Left Libya; Will Hunt Benghazi Thugs,” Wired, September 12, 2012, https://perma.cc/XR56-LG9K.

88 J. Risen, “After Benghazi Attack, Private Security Hovers as an Issue,” The New York Times, October 12, 2012, www.nytimes.com/2012/10/13/world/africa/private-security-hovers-as-issue-after-embassy-attack-in-benghazi-libya.html?_r=1; see also A. Mehra, “Time to Put Security Contractors Under the Gun,” Huffington Post, February 28, 2013, https://perma.cc/K7HN-F8ER.

90 Associated Press, “New Benghazi Investigation Finds No Fault in Response,” The New York Times, November 21, 2014, www.nytimes.com/2014/11/22/us/new-benghazi-investigation-finds-no-fault-in-response.html.

91 Footnote Ibid.; see also D. Kirkpatrick, “A Deadly Mix in Benghazi,” The New York Times, December 28, 2013, www.nytimes.com/projects/2013/benghazi/#/?chapt=0.

92 A joint resolution authorizing the limited use of the United States Armed Forces in support of the NATO mission in Libya, S.J. Res. 20, June 21, 2011, https://perma.cc/5JZ5-TFJH. The resolution also would have prohibited deployment of security contractors. See Kirkpatrick, “A Deadly Mix in Benghazi.”

93 See generally L. Fisher, “Senate Should Protect War Powers on Libya,” Roll Call, June 28, 2011, https://perma.cc/6Q72-69QU.

94 “Authority to Use Military Force in Libya,”

95 For a discussion of these arguments, see C. Savage, Power Wars: Inside Obama’s Post-9/11 Presidency (New York: Little, Brown, and Company 2015), pp. 635-654.

96 C. Blanchard and C. Humud, The “Islamic State” Crisis and U.S. Policy (CRS Report No. R43612) (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2015), https://perma.cc/CV2E-PV9A.

100 E. Schmitt, “Obstacles Limit Targets and Pace of Strikes against ISIS,” The New York Times, November 9, 2014, www.nytimes.com/2014/11/10/world/middleeast/trouble-pinning-down-isis-targets-impedes-airstrikes.html?mcubz=2.

101 C. Drew and D. Philipps, “As Stress Drives Off Drone Operators, Air Force Must Cut Flights,” The New York Times, June 16, 2015, www.nytimes.com/2015/06/17/us/as-stress-drives-off-drone-operators-air-force-must-cut-flights.html?_r=1.

102 “Transforming Wartime Contracting.”

103 Contractor Support of U.S. Operations in the USCENTCOM Area of Responsibility (Department of Defense, 2016), https://perma.cc/FFE8-SXFZ.

104 See J. Risen and M. Rosenberg, “Blackwater’s Legacy Goes Beyond Public View,” The New York Times, April 14, 2015, www.nytimes.com/2015/04/15/world/middleeast/blackwaters-legacy-goes-beyond-public-view.html.

105 See discussion below at text accompanying nn. 12–23.

106 Blanchard and Humud, The “Islamic State” Crisis and U.S. Policy.

107 President Barack Obama, Letter to the Congress of the United States, February 11, 2015, https://perma.cc/9SJN-K4X6; Draft Joint Resolution for Congress to Authorize the Limited Use of Force Against the Islamic State of Iraq and the Levant, February 11, 2015, https://perma.cc/FMQ9-BJVR.

108 Joint Resolution to Authorize the Use of United States Armed Forces Against Those Responsible for the Recent Attacks Against the United States, Pub. L. No. 107-40, § 2(a), 115 Stat. 224 (2001).

109 Authorization for Use of Military Force Against Iraq Resolution of 2002, Pub. L. No. 107-243, 116 Stat. 1498 (2002).

110 See, e.g., D. Byman, “Comparing Al Qaeda and ISIS: Different goals, different targets” (prepared testimony before the Subcommittee on Counterterrorism and Intelligence of the House Committee on Homeland Security), April 29, 2015, https://perma.cc/L7UH-KS4Z.

111 See DaCosta v. Laird, 448 F.2d 1368 (2d Cir. 1971); see also Koh, The National Security Constitution.

112 See J. Ely, War and Responsibility: Constitutional Lessons of Vietnam and Its Aftermath (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993). Indeed, during the Korean War, Truman administration officials referred to the conflict as a “police action,” despite the deployment of more than five million US troops to the region.

113 See, e.g., M. Wagner, “The Dehumanization of International Humanitarian Law: Legal, Political, and Ethical Implications of Autonomous Weapons Systems” (2014) 47 Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 1371–424; Docherty, “Losing Humanity.”

114 See, e.g., U.N. Report of the Special Rapporteur, Heyns; M. Waxman and K. Anderson, “Law and Ethics for Autonomous Weapon Systems: Why a Ban Won’t Work and How the Laws of War Can,” The Hoover Institution, April 13, 2013, https://perma.cc/C4UA-7DJN; R. Arkin, “The Case for Ethical Autonomy in Unmanned Systems” (2010) 9 Journal of Military Ethics 332–41, https://perma.cc/6K99-248D; see also D. Cohen, “Drones off the Leash,” U.S. News, July 25, 2013, https://perma.cc/XT35-LB2H.

115 For an excellent overview of the debate about autonomous weapons and a moderate approach to the issue, see J. Vilmer, “Terminator Ethics: Should We Ban ‘Killer Robots’?,” Ethics & International Affairs (March 23, 2015), https://perma.cc/U6QD-TMDE.

116 See Wagner, “The Dehumanization of International Humanitarian Law.”

117 Footnote Ibid.; J. Thurnher, “Examining Autonomous Weapon Systems from a Law of Armed Conflict Perspective,” in H. Nasu and R. McLaughlin (eds.), New Technologies and the Law of Armed Conflict (Den Haag, the Netherlands: T. M. C. Asser Press, 2014), p. 225; M. Sassòli, “Autonomous Weapons and International Humanitarian Law: Advantages, Open Technical Questions and Legal Issues to Be Clarified” (2014) 90 U.S. Naval War College, International Law Studies 308; see also B. Keller, “Smart Drones,” The New York Times, March 16, 2013, www.nytimes.com/2013/03/17/opinion/sunday/keller-smart-drones.html.

118 Department of Defense, Autonomy in Weapon Systems, DoD Directive 3000.09, Washington, DC: U.S. Department of Defense, 2012, https://perma.cc/NLG5-ETGS.

119 United Nations Meeting of Experts on Lethal and Autonomous Weapons Systems (April 13–17, 2015), https://perma.cc/ZC4Q-PMPJ.

120 See generally Avant, The Market for Force; L. Cameron and V. Chetail, Privatizing War: Private Military and Security Companies under International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013); Dickinson, Outsourcing War and Peace; McFate, The Modern Mercenary; Singer, Corporate Warriors; International Committee of the Red Cross, The Montreux Document: On pertinent legal obligations and good practices for States related to operations of military and security companies during armed conflict (Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross, 2009), https://perma.cc/6THJ-XV68.

121 See, e.g., S. Percy, Mercenaries: A History of a Norm in International Relations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).

122 Dickinson, Outsourcing War and Peace; L. Dickinson, “Regulating the Private Security Industry: The Promise of Public/Private Governance” (2013) 63 Emory Law Journal 417–54.

123 See Wagner, “The Dehumanization of International Humanitarian Law.”

124 See R. Crootof, “War Torts: Accountability for Autonomous Weapons” (2016) 164(6) University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1347–402.

125 Footnote Ibid., 1377.

127 H. Roff, “Killing in War: Responsibility, Liability and Lethal Autonomous Robots,” in A. Henschke et al. (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Ethics and War: Just War Theory in the 21st Century (New York: Routledge Press, 2013); see also Crootof, “War Torts.”

128 Jens David Ohlin has argued that international criminal law can nonetheless provide a framework for accountability with respect to the use of semi-autonomous and autonomous weapons. He observes that the origins of the command responsibility and other doctrines emerging out of the Nuremberg trials are premised on the notion of actions in a bureaucratic context, in which the bureaucracy itself is the instrument of harm. He suggests that the critical element of criminal responsibility of the commander in this context is control, not whether the subordinate possesses the requisite intent. J. Ohlin, “The Combatant’s Stance: Autonomous Weapons on the Battlefield,” (2016) (92) Int’l Leg. Stud. 130. The challenge for Ohlin’s view is that the concept of effective control in the context of ordinary bureaucracy is not easily applied to those operating autonomous weapons. Even in the case of semi-autonomous weapons, meaningful human control will not always be possible, particularly when systems are complex and involve multiple components. Moreover, Ohlin acknowledges that while the doctrine of command responsibility does not necessarily require commanders to intend harm, at a minimum a showing of recklessness is required. But in many cases involving autonomous or even-semi-autonomous weapons, there may be no human being within the bureaucracy who could be deemed to be reckless.

129 Dickinson, Outsourcing War and Peace.

130 In addition to charges against twenty-two individual defendants, the prosecution alleged that six organizations constituted criminal organizations due to their role in perpetrated acts of aggression, war crimes, and crimes against humanity, the three crimes within the jurisdiction of the tribunal. The six organizations were the Leadership Corps of the Nazi Party, the Gestapo, the SS, the SA, the Reich Cabinet, and the general staff and high command of the Nazi Party.

131 The Charter of the Tribunal specifically provided that “[a]t the trial of any individual member of any group or organization the Tribunal may declare (in connection with any act of which the individual may be convicted) that the group or organization of which the individual was a member was a criminal organization.” Charter of the International Military Tribunal, August 8, 1945, 59 Stat. 1546, 82 U.N.T.S. 284 § II, art. 9. The charter also specified that, in subsequent proceedings before national courts of states parties to the charter, individuals could be tried for mere membership in organizations deemed criminal by the IMT. Footnote Ibid., art. 10.

132 Trial of the Major War Criminals Before the International Military Tribunal, Nuremberg, November 14, 1945 – October 1, 1946, Second Day, Wednesday, November 21, 1945, Morning Session, p. 104 (1947). For a detailed account of the case against the Nazi organizations at Nuremberg, see D. Fraser, “(De)Constructing the Nazi State: Criminal Organizations and the Constitutional Theory of the International Military Tribunal” (2017) 39(1) Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review 117–86.

133 Judgment of the International Military Tribunal for the Trial of German Major War Criminals, pp. 67–80 (1946).

134 Footnote Ibid., p. 67.

136 The tribunal noted: “[It] should exclude persons who had no knowledge of the criminal purposes or acts of the organization and those who were drafted by the State for membership, unless they were personally implicated in the commission of acts declared criminal … in the Charter as members of the organization. Membership alone is not enough to come within the scope of these declarations.” Footnote Ibid.

137 For example, the IMT stated that “[w]here an organization with a large membership is used for such [criminal] purposes, a declaration [of criminality] obviates the necessity of inquiring as to its criminal character in the later trial of members who are accused of participating through membership in its criminal purposes and thus saves much time and trouble.” Footnote Ibid.

138 D. Luban, Legal Modernism: Law, Meaning, and Violence (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994), p. 362.

139 Footnote Ibid., p. 363 (quoting R. Conot, Justice at Nuremberg [New York: Basic Books, 1983], pp. 210–11).

140 Footnote Ibid. (quoting Conot, Justice at Nuremberg).

141 Footnote Ibid. (quoting H. Arendt, On Violence [Orlando, FL: Harcourt Publishing, 1970], p. 38).

142 Footnote Ibid., p. 372.

143 A. Danner and J. Martinez, “Guilty Associations: Joint Criminal Enterprise, Command Responsibility, and the Development of International Criminal Law” (2005) 93(1) California Law Review 77170 at 79.

144 Footnote Ibid., at 79.

146 See Wagner, “The Dehumanization of International Humanitarian Law”; see also Roff, “Killing in War.”

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×