Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-fbnjt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T18:08:26.902Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Music and the subjects of Romanticism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 October 2009

Andrew Bowie
Affiliation:
Royal Holloway, University of London
Get access

Summary

The task of philosophy

In early German Romantic philosophy communication and understanding are often regarded more as ways of acting and being in the world than as forms of representation of a pre-given reality. Music becomes particularly significant because it involves norm-based interpretation, on the part both of players and of listeners, and yet resists wholesale incorporation into representational and theoretical discourse. The question is what this means for philosophy. The interrogation of the nature of philosophy occasioned by the changes in thinking about language in Romanticism need not imply that, because modern philosophy fails to achieve some of the tasks it sets itself, it is therefore at an end, in the way the later Heidegger claims by his equation of philosophy and metaphysics. Such an implication would contradict the pragmatist side of Romanticism, which assesses discourses and practices in terms of their contribution to human flourishing, and so abstains from final judgements on the status of particular cultural practices. There is, however, no doubt that a significant strand of modern philosophy, from the Romantics, to Nietzsche, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, Adorno, Merleau-Ponty, and Gadamer, can be interpreted as questioning the assumptions of science-oriented philosophy in terms of the issues that we have been exploring via music.

Ernst Tugendhat has criticised this strand of philosophy as follows: ‘it is characteristic for the entire tradition of philosophical Romanticism from Schelling and Hegel to Heidegger and Gadamer that, in ever new ways, an ontologically inflated conception of art became a substitute for the question of the justification of norms, and it was in every instance an obfuscation of the concept of truth’ (Tugendhat 1992: 430).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2007

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×