Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-c654p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-28T03:22:31.746Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter Two - Rule Following, Intellectualism, and Logical Reasoning: On the Importance of a Type Distinction between Performances and “Propositional Knowledge” of the Norms that Govern Them

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 December 2022

Get access

Summary

Wittgenstein has his interlocutor ask, “How many kinds of sentence are there? Say assertion, question, and command?” Wittgenstein's response is that there are countless kinds: countless different kinds of use of what we call “symbols,” “words,” “sentences.” And, he goes on, “this multiplicity is not something fixed, given once for all; but new types of language, new language-games, as we may say, come into existence, and others become obsolete and get forgotten.”

Ryle, for his part, constantly reminds his readers that sentences have a great number of different employments besides those of stating, asserting, describing, or reporting. (Commanding, cajoling, deriding, punishing, congratulating, praising, promising, giving vent, and expressing are just a few.) In particular, he urges,

We are constantly wanting to talk about what can be relied on to happen as well as to talk about what is actually happening; we are constantly wanting to give explanations of incidents as well as to report them; and we are constantly wanting to tell how things can be managed as well as to tell what is now going on in them.

As this anticipates, among the kinds of sentences that interest philosophers are ones whose primary aim, in the context of their use, is explanatory, justificatory, or actionguiding. Among such sentences may be those expressing laws, rules, dispositions, definitions, principles, or norms.

Now some of these sentences may be classified by logicians as statements, and thus, as truth-apt. “Murder is wrong,” “Any two bodies in the universe attract each other with a force that is directly proportional to the product of their masses and inversely proportional to the square of the distance between them,” and “John wants me to replace the bottle of Chablis I drank” are examples. But though they are evaluable as true or false and, indeed, that they are so evaluable is required for syntactic operations upon these sentences, this “surface grammar” tends to mislead philosophers. Overly impressed with their logical classification, they find themselves looking in the wrong place for the facts they are alleged to state, which are supposed to render the sentences true. When they cannot find them among what Ryle calls “witnessable events,” they tend to suppose they must be found among “unwitnessable” ones.

Type
Chapter
Information
Meaning, Mind, and Action
Philosophical Essays
, pp. 35 - 46
Publisher: Anthem Press
Print publication year: 2022

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×