Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T04:40:54.458Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

19 - Levi on Money Pumps and Diachronic Dutch Books

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 March 2010

Erik J. Olsson
Affiliation:
Lunds Universitet, Sweden
Wlodek Rabinowicz
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Lund University
Get access

Summary

It is with a great pleasure but also with some misgivings that I contribute to this volume. The pleasure comes from my feelings of friendship and gratitude toward Isaac Levi. We have known each other for a long time now. As I very well recall, it all started way back in the 1970s with his letter commenting on an article of mine dealing with his seminal Gambling with Truth. As a young and shy graduate student in Uppsala, I felt both overwhelmed and overjoyed by this great man's attention and encouragement. Suddenly, the distance between the faraway Columbia and my own university shrank to the manageable size of a philosophical argument. Thanks to Isaac, I realized, for the first time, that it was – perhaps – within my reach to join a larger community of minds that spanned the globe.

The pleasure is mixed with misgivings. Over the years my friendship and affection for Isaac deepened and matured, but philosophically we often found ourselves on opposite sides. He was highly critical of causal decision theory and I was one of its enthusiastic defenders; he was (and still is) a powerful advocate of the thesis that practical deliberation crowds out self-prediction, while I have been one of the doubters. Examples could be multiplied. In this chapter, as it happens, I want to examine another such bone of contention, more precisely the status of diachronic pragmatic arguments. I realize that Isaac may be tired of this ongoing controversy.

Type
Chapter
Information
Knowledge and Inquiry
Essays on the Pragmatism of Isaac Levi
, pp. 289 - 312
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aumann, R. 1995. “Backward Induction and Common Knowledge of Rationality.” Games and Economic Behavior 18: 6–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R. 1998. “A Note on the Centipede Game.” Games and Economic Behavior 23: 97–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-Hillel, M., and Margalit, A.. 1988. “How Vicious Are Cycles of Intransitive Choice?Theory and Decision 24: 119–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, C. 1989. “Backward Induction with Common Knowledge.” Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 329–43Google Scholar
Binmore, K. 1987. “Modelling Rational Players: Part 1.” Economics and Philosophy 3: 179–213CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, J., and Rabinowicz, W.. 1999. “Backwards Induction in the Centipede Game.” Analysis 59: 237–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. 1991. “Clever Bookies and Coherent Beliefs.” Philosophical Review 50: 229–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D., McKinsey, J. C. C., and Suppes, P.. 1955. “Outlines of a Formal Theory of Value, Part IPhilosophy of Science 22: 140–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joyce, J. M. 2002. “Levi on Causal Decision Theory and the Possibility of Predicting One's Own Actions.” Philosophical Studies 110: 69–102CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. 1988. “The Demons of Decision.” The Monist 70: 193–211CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. 1989. “Rationality, Prediction, and Autonomous Choice.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, suppl. vol. 19: 339–63Google Scholar
Levi, I. 1991. “Consequentialism and Sequential Choice.” In Bacharach, M. and Hurley, S. (eds.), Foundations of Decision Theory, pp. 92–122. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. 1997. The Covenant of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. 2002. “Money Pumps and Diachronic Dutch Books.” Philosophy of Science, suppl. to vol. 69: s235–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P. 1992. “Diachronic Rationality.” Philosophy of Science 59: 120–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClennen, E. 1990. Rationality and Dynamic Choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P., and Sugden, R.. 1989. “The Backward Induction ParadoxJournal of Philosophy 86: 169–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. 1995. “To Have One's Cake and Eat It, Too: Sequential Choice and Expected Utility Violations.” The Journal of Philosophy 92: 586–620CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. 1998. “Grappling with the Centipede.” Economics and Philosophy 14: 95–125CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. 2000. “Money Pump with Foresight.” In Almeida, Michael J. (ed.), Imperceptible Harms and Benefits. Dordrecht: Kluwer. pp. 123–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, W. 2002. “Does Practical Deliberation Crowd Out Self-Prediction?Erkenntnis 57: 91–122CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raiffa, H. 1968. Decision Analysis: Introductory Lectures on Choice under Uncertainty. Reading, Mass.: Addison-WesleyGoogle Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. 1990. “Truth and Probability” (1926). In Mellor, D. H. (ed.), F. P. Ramsey: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Reny, P. 1988. “Rationality, Common Knowledge and the Theory of Games.” Ph.D. dissertation, Princeton University
Reny, P. 1989. “Common Knowledge and Games with Perfect Information.” Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2: 363–9Google Scholar
Schick, F. 1986. “Dutch Bookies and Money Pumps.” Journal of Philosophy 83: 112–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schumm, G. F. 1986. “Transitivity, Preference and Indifference.” Philosophical Studies 53: 435–7Google Scholar
Schwartz, T. 1993. The Logic of Collective Choice. New York: Columbia University PressGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1980. “Higher Order Degrees of Belief.” In Mellor, D. H. (ed.), Prospects for Pragmatism. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B. 1986. “A Mistake in Dynamic Coherence Arguments?Philosophy of Science 60: 320–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sobel, J. H. 1993. “Backward Induction Arguments in Finitely Iterated Prisoners' Dilemmas: A Paradox Regained.” Philosophy of Science 60: 114–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teller, P. 1973. “Conditionalization and Observation.” Synthese 26: 218–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraassen, B. 1984. “Belief and the Will.” Journal of Philosophy 81: 235–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×