Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T17:08:27.714Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

8 - ‘Rationalisation’, ‘reification’, ‘instrumental reason’

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2013

Fred Rush
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame
Nicholas Boyle
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Liz Disley
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
John Walker
Affiliation:
Birkbeck College, University of London
Get access

Summary

Idealism in the history of European philosophy has taken, broadly speaking, two main forms. In the first, the term ‘idealism’ refers to the view that the ultimate constituents of reality, and thus the ultimate objects of possible human intellection are entities called ‘ideas’. Such entities are mind-independent; cognitive access to them involves decreasing to a minimum obstacles native to being human impinging on that access, sharpening special capacities that enable such access, or both. Plato's theory of forms is this sort of account. An idea or form (εἶδος, ἰδέα) is a fundamental structure of the world and knowing one, or a system of them, is a matter both of diminishing the effect on human cognition of transient, misleading sensuous and dispositional elements in experience and developing a special sort of intuition that can ‘see’ the idea in question.

The second type of idealism conceives of the structure of what is real on the model of structuring, i.e. in roughly intentional terms. In this tradition, ideas are mental items, hence not mind-independent, and are only with substantial qualification fundamental constituents of reality. What systematises such items is a theory of human reason and this, more than anything else, is why it is appropriate to consider idealist philosophy of this mien under the heading ‘rationalism’. There are several differing and systematic renderings of why rationalism emerged as one of the dominant trends in modern philosophy, but all stress in various ways the advent of new and powerful models in physics and other sciences that had the effect of leaching out of the idea of reality any purposive structure. Ideas are closely related to ends, even in antiquity, and the problematic status of de re purposes in modern philosophy, which was strongly responsive to the accumulation of scientific discoveries leading up to Newtonian mechanics, resulted in ideas being relegated to the subjective side of the cognitive equation and a consequent exacerbation of the problem of access to reality through such ideas. The word ‘through’ is no throwaway: ideas both are the means by which one can comprehend reality and potential blocks to that comprehension. It is only by the dual processes of policing the content of the ideas and by soundly accumulating them that objectivity is preserved.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Impact of Idealism
The Legacy of Post-Kantian German Thought
, pp. 186 - 207
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Henrich, Dieter, Die Einheit der Wissenschaftslehre Max Webers (Tübingen: Mohr, 1952)Google Scholar
Ringer, Fritz, Max Weber's Methodology: the unification of the cultural and social sciences (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000)Google Scholar
Weber, Max, Die protestantische Ethik und der ‘Geist’ des Kapitalismus (1904/5) (Bodenheim: Athenaeum, 1993)Google Scholar
Weber, Marianne, Max Weber: ein Lebensbild (Tübingen: Mohr, 1926), 292–317Google Scholar
Simmel, Georg, Philosophie des Geldes (1907), in Gesamtausgabe vi, ed. Rammstedt, O. (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1992)Google Scholar
Weber, Max, Politik als Beruf (Stuttgart: Reclam, 1992), 90Google Scholar
Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich, Marx-Engels-Werke (Berlin: Dietz, 1956–)Google Scholar
‘Die Verdinglichung und das Bewußtsein des Proletariats’ (1923), in Geschichte und Klassenbewußtsein (Berlin: Luchterhand, 1968), 257–397
Tönnies, Ferdinand, Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft (1887) (2nd rev. edn, Berlin: Curtius, 1912)
Horkheimer, Max, ‘Traditionelle und kritische Theorie’ (1937), in Kritische Theorie, in Studienausgabe (Frankfurt am Main: Fischer, 1968), 521–75Google Scholar
The Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Harper & Row, 1973)
Malinowski, see, Argonauts of the Western Pacific: an account of native enterprise and adventure in the archipelagoes of Melanesian New Guinea (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1922)Google Scholar
Evans-Pritchard, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1937)
Winch, Peter, The Idea of a Social Science (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1958)Google Scholar
Morgenbesser, Sidney, ‘Is it a science?’, in Emmet, D. and MacIntyre, A. (eds.), Sociological Theory and Philosophical Analysis (New York: Macmillan, 1970), 20–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marcuse, Herbert, ‘Industrialisierung und Kapitalismus im Werk Max Webers’, in Kultur und Gesellschaft (Frankfurt am Main: Fischer, 1968), 281–303Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel, Reification: a new look at an old idea (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘Hegel on skulls and faces’, in Hegel: a collection of critical essays, ed. MacIntyre, A. (New York: Macmillan, 1972), 219–36Google Scholar
‘Die Aktualität Schopenhauers’, in Zur Kritik der instrumentellen Vernunft (Frankfurt am Main: Fischer, 1967), 248–68
Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung (1818), in Sämmtliche Werke (Frankfurt am Main: Cotta Insel, 1982)
Bakunin, Mikail, Государственность и анархия [Statism and anarchy] (1873), in Archives Bakounine iii, ed. A. Lehnung (Leiden: Brill, 1967)Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×