Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T07:10:54.645Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false
This chapter is part of a book that is no longer available to purchase from Cambridge Core

2 - Sensibility: space and time, transcendental idealism

from PART I - THEORETICAL PHILOSOPHY

Emily Carson
Affiliation:
McGill University
Will Dudley
Affiliation:
Williams College, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

Kant's characteristic distinction between sensibility and understanding is generally taken to mark the shift from his pre-critical period to the mature critical period. It is at the heart both of his explanation of the possibility of synthetic a priori cognition and of his critique of speculative metaphysics. As we shall see, for Kant, sensibility both extends our cognition, allowing us to go beyond mere concepts to synthetic a priori cognition, and constrains our synthetic a priori cognition to objects of possible experience.

Sensibility in the pre-critical period

Kant introduced a fundamental distinction between the faculties of sensibility and intellect in his Inaugural Dissertation of 1770, De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis forma et principiis (On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and Intelligible World), in which he makes clear the importance of this distinction for metaphysics. He describes De mundi as a specimen of a “propaedeutic science” for metaphysics that “teaches the distinction between sensitive cognition and the cognition which derives from the understanding” (ID 2:395). If we keep straight the sources of our concepts, Kant claims, we can avoid certain longstanding metaphysical disputes. One such dispute that had concerned Kant at least as early as 1755 revolved around an apparent conflict between the metaphysical doctrine of indivisible monads and the infinite divisibility of geometrical space. In his Physical Monadology, Kant asked:

How, in this business, can metaphysics be married to geometry, when it seems easier to mate griffins with horses than to unite transcendental philosophy with geometry? For the former peremptorily denies that space is infinitely divisible, while the latter, with its usual certainty, asserts that it is infinitely divisible. […]

Type
Chapter
Information
Immanuel Kant
Key Concepts - A Philosophical Introduction
, pp. 28 - 44
Publisher: Acumen Publishing
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×