Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T13:26:35.230Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2016

Howard Robinson
Affiliation:
Central European University, Budapest
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
From the Knowledge Argument to Mental Substance
Resurrecting the Mind
, pp. 260 - 267
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abbott, E. A. 1884. Flatland: A Romance in Many Dimensions. London: Seeley and Co. Republished many times, most recently by Princeton University Press, 2015.Google Scholar
Alter, T. 2007. ‘Does Representationalism Undermine the Knowledge Argument?’, in Alter, and Walter, : 6576.Google Scholar
Alter, T. and Walter, S. 2007. Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1968. A Materialist Theory of the Mind. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1978. A Theory of Universals. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 2010. Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1968. The Origins of Pragmatism. London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, M. 2011. ‘Brains and Souls; Grammar and Speaking’, in Baker, and Goetz, : 7393.Google Scholar
Baker, M. and Goetz, S. (eds). 2011. The Soul Hypothesis. New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
Balog, K. 1999. ‘Conceivability, Possibility and the Mind-Body Problem’, The Philosophical Review 108 (4): 497528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balog, K. 2012a. ‘Acquaintance and the Mind-Body Problem’, in New Perspectives on Type Identity: The Mental and the Physical, Hill, Christopher and Gozzano, Simone (eds). Cambridge University Press: 1643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balog, K. 2012b. ‘In Defence of the Phenomenal Concept Strategy’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beall, J. C. 2003. Liars and Heaps. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Blackburn, S. 1990. ‘Filling in Space’, Analysis 50 (2): 62–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Block, N. 2007. ‘Max Black’s Objection to Mind-Body Identity’, in Alter, and Walter, : 249306.Google Scholar
Block, N. and Stalnaker, R. 1999. ‘Conceptual Analysis, Dualism and the Explanatory Gap’, Philosophical Review 108: 146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burge, T. 1993. ‘Mind-Body Causation and Explanatory Practice’, in Heil, and Mele, (eds): 97120.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1934. The Unity of Science. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. 1955. ‘The Logical Foundations of the Unity of Science’, in Neurath, , Carnap, and Morris, (eds): 4262.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. 2003. ‘Consciousness and Its Place in Nature’, in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind, Stich, Stephen and Warfield, Ted (eds). Oxford: Blackwell, 102–42.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. (ed.). 2009. Metametaphysics. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charles, D. 1992. ‘Supervenience, Composition, and Physicalism’, in Charles, and Lennon, (eds): 265–96.Google Scholar
Charles, D. and Lennon, K. (eds). 1992. Reduction, Explanation and Realism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. 1991. ‘On the Simplicity of the Soul’, Philosophical Perspectives 5: 157–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. 1989a. The Neurocomputational Perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. 1989b. ‘Reduction, Qualia and the Direct Introspection of Brain States’, in Churchland, 1989a: 4766.Google Scholar
Churchland, P. 1989c. ‘Knowing Qualia: A Reply to Jackson’, in Churchland, 1989a: 6776.Google Scholar
Crombie, I. 1963. An Examination of Plato’s Doctrines, vols. I and II. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Cussins, A. 1992. ‘The Limitations of Pluralism’, in Charles, and Lennon, (eds): 179223.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1970. ‘Mental Events’, in Foster, and Swanson, (eds): 79101.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1984. ‘Truth and Meaning’, in his Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1736.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1987. ‘Problems in the Explanation of Action’, in Pettit, , Sylvan, and Norman, (eds): 3549.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1993. ‘Thinking Causes’, in Heil, and Mele, (eds): 317.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1987a. The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1987b. ‘True Believers’, in Dennett, 1987a: 1335.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness Explained. London: Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 2000. ‘With a Little Help from My Friends’, in Ross, , Brook, and Thompson, (eds): 327–88.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. 2007. ‘What RoboMary Knows’, in Alter, and Walter, , 1526.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. 1984. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, translated by Cottingham, John, Stoothoff, Robert and Murdoch, Dugald. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. 2000. Perception, Knowledge and Belief. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feigl, H., Scriven, M. and Maxwell, G. (eds). 1958. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. II. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Fine, G. 1993. On Ideas. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1974. ‘Special Sciences, or the Disunity of Science as a Working Hypothesis’, Synthese 28: 77115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. 1975. The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1979. Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Harvester Press (UK) and MIT Press (US).Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 1997. ‘Special Sciences: Still Autonomous After All These Years’. Philosophical Perspectives 11: 149–63.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. 2000. The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way: The Scope and Limits of Computational Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, J. 1982. The Case for Idealism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Foster, J. 1991. The Immaterial Self: A Defence of the Cartesian Dualist Conception of the Mind. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Foster, J. 2008. A World for Us. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foster, L. and Swanson, J. (eds). 1970. Experience and Theory. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Frege, G. 1952. ‘Concept and Object’, in Translations from the Writings of Gottlob Frege, Geach, P. and Black, M. (eds). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
French, S. 2006. ‘Identity and Individuality in Quantum Theory’, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qt-idind/Google Scholar
Geach, P. 1969. ‘What Do We Think With?’, in his God and the Soul. Cambridge University Press: 3041.Google Scholar
Goff, P. 2006. ‘Experiences Don’t Sum’, in Strawson, : 5361.Google Scholar
Graham, G. and Horgan, T. 2000. ‘Mary Mary, Quite Contrary’, Philosophical Studies 99: 5987.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, G. 1990. ‘The Intrinsic Qualities of Experience’, Philosophical Perspectives 4: 3152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, W. 1988. The Engines of the Soul. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Heil, J. and Mele, A. (eds). 1993. Mental Causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. 1980. ‘The Logical Analysis of Psychology’, in Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, vol. 1, Block, N. (ed.). London: Methuen: 1423. (Originally published in French in 1935.)Google Scholar
Hohwy, J. and Kallestrup, J. 2008. Being Reduced: New Essays on Reduction, Explanation, and Causation. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornsby, J. 2001. Simple Mindedness: in Defense of Naïve Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Horwich, P. 2006. Reflections on Meaning. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1739/2000. A Treatise on Human Nature, Norton, D. F. and Norton, N. J. (eds). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1982. ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’, Philosophical Quarterly 32: 127–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1986. ‘What Mary Didn’t Know’, Journal of Philosophy 83 (5): 291–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1998/2004. ‘Postscript on Qualia’, in his Mind, Methods and Conditionals. London: Routledge, 76–9. (Reprinted in Ludlow, et al., 417–20.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 2004. ‘Mind and Illusion’, in Ludlow, et al.: 421–42.Google Scholar
Jaworski, W. 2011. Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kemeny, J. and Oppenheim, P. 1956. ‘On Reduction’. Philosophical Studies 7: 619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 1993a. ‘Can Supervenience and “Non-Strict Laws” Save Anomolous Monism?’, in Heil, and Mele, (eds): 1926.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1993b. ‘The Non-Reductivist’s Troubles with Mental Causation’, in Heil, and Mele, (eds): 189210.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1998. Mind in a Physical World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. 2005. Physicalism, or Something Near Enough. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kirk, R. 1994: Raw Feels. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kirk, R. 2005. Zombies and Consciousness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, R. 2013. The Conceptual Link from the Mental to the Physical. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kovacs, D. 2010. ‘Is There a Conservative Solution to the Many Thinkers Problem?’, Ratio 23: 275–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. 1972. Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. 1976. Wittgenstein and Rule-Following. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Levin, Janet. 1983. ‘Functionalism and the Argument from Conceivability’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11: 85104.Google Scholar
Levin, Janet. 1986. ‘Could Love Be Like a Heatwave?’, Philosophical Studies, 49: 245–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, Janet. 2007. ‘What Is a Phenomenal Concept?’, in Alter, and Walter, (eds): 87110.Google Scholar
Levine, J. 1983. ‘Materialism and Qualia: The Explanatory Gap’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64: 354–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1983a. Philosophical Papers, vol. I. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1983b. ‘Mad Pain and Martian Pain’, Philosophical Papers I: 122–30.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1986. Philosophical Papers vol. II. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1995. ‘Should a Materialist Believe in Qualia?’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73: 140–4. (Reprinted in Lewis, (1999): 2531.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1999. Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 2004. ‘What Experience Teaches’, Ludlow, et al.: 77103. (Reprinted from Proceedings of the Russellian Society, 1988. University of Sydney, 13: 2957.)Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 2009, ‘Ramseyan Humility’, in Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism, Braddon-Mitchell, David and Nola, Robert (eds). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 203–22.Google Scholar
Loar, B. 1997. ‘Phenomenal States’, in The Nature of Consciousness, Block, N., Flanagan, O and Guzeldere, G. (eds). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 597616.Google Scholar
Lockwood, M. J. 1989. Mind, Brain and the Quantum. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lockwood, M. J. 1993. ‘The Grain Problem’, in Objections to Physicalism, Robinson, H. (ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press: 271–91.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. 2008. ‘Why There Is Anything Except Physics’, in Being Reduced. Oxford University Press: 149–62.Google Scholar
Loewer, B. 2009. ‘Why Is There Anything Except Physics?’, Synthese 170: 217–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 1996. Subjects of Experience. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2004. ‘Non-Cartesian Dualism’, in Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology, Heil, J. (ed.). Oxford University Press: 851–65.Google Scholar
Ludlow, P., Nagasawa, Y. and Stoljar, D. (eds). 2004. There’s Something about Mary: Essays on Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson’s Knowledge Argument. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Lycan, W. 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Macdonald, C. and Macdonald, G. 1986. ‘Mental Causation and Explanation of Action’. Philosophical Quarterly 36: 145–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Madell, G. 1981. The Identity of the Self. Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Maxwell, G. 1978. ‘Rigid Designators and Mind-Brain Identity’, in Perception and Cognition Issues in the Foundations of Psychology: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. IX, Wade Savage, C. (ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: 365403.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McDowell, J. 2008. ‘Responses’ in John McDowell: Experience, Norm, and Nature, Lingaard, J. (ed.). Oxford: Blackwell: 200–67.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1989. ‘Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?Mind 98: 349–66.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. 1993. The Problem of Consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Mc Laughlin, B. 1993. ‘Davidson’s Response to Epiphenomenalism’, in Heil, and Mele, (eds): 2740.Google Scholar
Molnar, G. 2003. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. 1961. The Structure of Science. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 1974. ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat?’, Philosophical Review 83: 435–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, T. 2012. Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature Is Almost Certainly False. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neurath, O., Carnap, R. and Morris, C. 1955. International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Oppenheim, P. and Putnam, H. 1958: ‘Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis’, in Feigl, , Scriven, and Maxwell, (eds): 336.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. 2002. Thinking about Consciousness. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, D. 2007. ‘Phenomenal and Perceptual Concepts’, in Alter, and Walter, : 111–44.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1979. Holistic Explanation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P., Sylvan, R. and Norman, J. (eds). 1987: Metaphysics and Morality. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Place, U. T. 1956. ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process?’, The British Journal of Psychology 47: 4450.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Plotinus, , 1958. Ennead VI, 6–9, translated by Armstrong, A. H.. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Price, H. 2004. ‘Naturalism Without Representationalism’, in Naturalism in Question, De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press: 7188. (Reprinted in Price, (2011): 184–99.)Google Scholar
Price, H. 2011. Naturalism Without Mirrors. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Priest, G. 2003. ‘A Site for Sorites’, in Liars and Heaps: New Essays on Paradox, Beall, J., (ed.). Oxford University Press: 923.Google Scholar
Prinz, J. 2012. The Conscious Brain. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975a. Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975b: ‘Minds and Machines’, in his 1975a: 362–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. 1981. ’Brains in a Vat’, in his Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press: 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reid, T. 1785/1969. Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rist, J. 1967. Plotinus: The Road to Reality. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 1982. Matter and Sense. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 1989. ‘Structural and Functional Criteria for the Identity of Mental States: A Dilemma for Physicalism’, Hermes 3: 128–42. (This is a journal of the Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique: the paper was delivered in English to a CNRS seminar in Paris, but published in French.)Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 1993a. ‘The Anti-Materialist Strategy and the “Knowledge Argument”’, in Objections to Physicalism, Robinson, H. (ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press: 159–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. (ed.), 1993b. Objections to Physicalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 1993c. ‘Dennett and the Knowledge Argument’, Analysis 53: 174–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 1994. Perception. London: Routledge.Google ScholarPubMed
Robinson, H. 2001. ‘Donald Davidson and Non-Reductive Physicalism: A Tale of Two Cultures’, in Physicalism and Its Discontents, Gillett, K. and Loewer, B. (eds). New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2003. ‘Dualism’, in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Mind, Stitch, S. and Warfield, T. (eds). Oxford: Blackwell: 85101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 2007. ‘The Self and Time’, in Persons, Human and Divine, van Inwagen, P. and Zimmermann, D. (eds). Oxford: Clarendon Press: 5583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 2008. ‘Why Frank Should Not Have Jilted Mary’, in The Case for Qualia, Wright, Edmond (ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 223–45.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2008–9. ‘Vagueness, Realism, Language and Thought’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109: 83101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 2009a. ‘Idealism’, in The Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Mind, McLaughlin, B., Beckermann, A. and Walter, S. (eds). Oxford University Press: 186205.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2009b ‘Reductionism, Supervenience and Emergence’, in The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, Simons, P. and LePoidevin, P. (eds). London: Routledge: 527–36.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2010. ‘Quality, Thought and Consciousness’, in The Metaphysics of Consciousness, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 67, Basile, P., Kiverstein, J. and Phemester, P. (eds). Cambridge University Press: 203–16.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2011. ‘Benacerraf’s Problem, Abstract Objects and Intellect’, in Truth, Reference and Realism, Novak, Z. and Simonyi, A. (eds). Budapest: CEU Press: 235–62.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2012a. ‘“Are There Any Fs?” How Should We Understand This Question?’, for a special edition of the Hungarian Philosophical Review, dedicated to ‘current issues in metaphysics’: 5568.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2012b. ‘Qualia, Qualities and Our Conception of the Physical World’, in The Case for Dualism, Goecke, Benedikt (ed.). Notre Dame: Notre Dame Press: 231–63.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2013. ‘The Failure of Disjunctivism to Deal with “Philosophers’ Hallucinations”’, in Hallucinations, Macpherson, Fiona and Platchias, Dimitris (eds). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 313–30.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2014a. ‘Naturalism and the Unavoidability of the Cartesian Perspective’, in Contemporary Dualism, Lavazza, and Robinson, (eds). London: Routledge: 154–70.Google Scholar
Robinson, H. 2014b. ‘Modern Hylomorphism and the Reality and Causal Power of Structure: A Skeptical Investigation’, Res Philosophica 91: 203–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, H. 2014c. ‘Substance’, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/substance/.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 1965–6. ‘Mind-Body Identity, Privacy and Categories’, Review of Metaphysics 17: 2454.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. 2010. ‘Naturalism and Quietism’, in Naturalism and Normativity, De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds). New York: Columbia University Press: 5568.Google Scholar
Ross, D., Brook, A. and Thompson, D. (eds). 2000. Dennett’s Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, B. 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Russell, B. 1931. The Scientific Outlook. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Ryle, G. 1963: The Concept of Mind. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Sainsbury, M. 1988. Paradoxes. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, N. 2005. Reference and Essence. Amherst: Prometheus Books. (Original edition, 1981, Princeton: Princeton University Press.)Google Scholar
Scerri, E. R. and McIntyre, L. 1997. ‘The Case for the Philosophy of Chemistry’, Synthese 111: 213–32.Google Scholar
Seager, W. 2000. ‘Real Patterns and Surface Metaphysics’, in Ross, , Brook, and Thompson, : 95129.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1981. ’Some Varieties of Functionalism’, Philosophical Topics 12: 93119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shoemaker, S. 1994. ‘The Mind-Body Problem’, in Warner, and Szubka, (eds): 5560.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1959. ‘Sensations and Brain Processes’, The Philosophical Review 68: 141–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. 1963. Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Smith, A. D. 1993. ‘Non-Reductive Physicalism?’, in Robinson, (ed.): 225–50.Google Scholar
Smith, P. 1992. ‘Modest Reductions and the Unity of Science’, in Charles, and Lennon, (eds): 1943.Google Scholar
Sosa, E. 1993. ‘Davidson’s Thinking Causes’, in Heil, and Mele, (eds): 4150.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. 2008. Our Knowledge of the Internal World. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stoljar, D. 2006. Ignorance and Imagination: On the Epistemic Origin of the Problem of Consciousness. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G. 1994. Mental Reality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G. 2006. Consciousness and Its Place in Nature edited by Freeman, A., keynote paper (pp. 331) and reply to commentaries (pp. 184280). Thorverton: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 2007. Real Materialism and Other Essays. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, G. 2009. Selves: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P. F. 1959. Individuals. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. 1984. Probabilistic Metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 1986/97. The Evolution of the Soul. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 2007. ‘From Mental/Physical Identity to Substance Dualism’, in Persons: Human and Divine, van Inwagen, P. and Zimmermann, D. W. (eds). Oxford University Press: 142–65.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 2013. Mind, Brain and Free Will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Swinburne, R. 2014. ‘What Makes Me Me ? A Defense of Substance Dualism’, in Contemporary Dualism: A Defense, Lavazza, A. and Robinson, H. (eds). New York and London: Routledge: 139–53.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1992. ‘Visual Qualia and Visual Content’, in The Contents of Experience, Crane, T. (ed.). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tye, M. 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Unger, P. 1980. Ignorance. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Van Inwagen, P. 1990. Material Beings. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Walker, R. 1993. ‘Transcendental Arguments Against Physicalism’, in Robinson, (ed.): 6180.Google Scholar
Warner, R. and Szuba, T. (eds). 1994. The Mind-Body Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wiggins, D. 1974. ‘Essentialism, Continuity, and Identity’, Synthese 28 (3/4): 321–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wiggins, D. 2001. Sameness and Substance Renewed. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. 1992. ‘Vagueness and Ignorance’, Aristotelian Society, suppl. 66: 145–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, T. 1994. Vagueness. London: Routledge.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Howard Robinson, Central European University, Budapest
  • Book: From the Knowledge Argument to Mental Substance
  • Online publication: 05 February 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316092873.018
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Howard Robinson, Central European University, Budapest
  • Book: From the Knowledge Argument to Mental Substance
  • Online publication: 05 February 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316092873.018
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Howard Robinson, Central European University, Budapest
  • Book: From the Knowledge Argument to Mental Substance
  • Online publication: 05 February 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316092873.018
Available formats
×