Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-zzh7m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T17:28:27.355Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Unjust laws and legal systems

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 October 2014

W. Bradley Wendel
Affiliation:
Cornell University, New York
Get access

Summary

Consider the predicament of Captain Vere in Herman Melville’s novella Billy Budd. Billy, the protagonist, is a good but simple sailor who is wrongfully accused by the malevolent petty officer Claggart of conspiring to mutiny. Suffering from a speech impediment and thus unable to speak in his own defense, Billy strikes Claggart and kills him. Vere believes he has no choice but to convene a court martial to consider the capital charge against Billy of striking a superior officer during wartime. Many readers of Billy Budd are not aware that the character of Captain Vere was modeled on Melville’s father-in-law, Chief Justice Lemuel Shaw of the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts, who was renowned for his opposition to slavery yet was the author of several judgments enforcing the Fugitive Slave Act. Melville clearly means his readers to see Vere as a wise, humane, decent officer. At the same time, he has Vere represent the harshness and rigidity of the law in contrast with considerations of justice. Billy was innocent, framed by Claggart, and Vere knew of his innocence, but Vere nevertheless persuades the other officers to order Billy’s execution by reminding them that leniency might encourage mutiny in the Royal Navy during wartime.

Like the fictional Captain Vere, the real Justice Shaw was a righteous man, yet he saw no alternative to following the law and sending fugitive slaves back to their owners. In Justice Shaw’s eyes, the Fugitive Slave Act, however unjust, was a regrettable necessity in a nation sharply divided over the question of slavery; it was a political compromise that averted the far worse outcome of civil war (which, of course, came in the end anyway). Agree or disagree with Justice Shaw’s reasoning, most historians see him as a decent person faced with a genuine conflict of obligations, not an Eichmann-type official mindlessly serving as a cog in a monstrous machine. Like Captain Vere, Justice Shaw believed he had an obligation to follow the law, despite the clear injustice of the cases before him.

Type
Chapter
Information
Ethics and Law
An Introduction
, pp. 106 - 128
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Cover, Robert M., Justice Accused (New Haven: Yale University Press 1975)Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah, Eichmann in Jerusalem (New York: Viking 1963)Google Scholar
Neiman, Susan, Evil in Modern Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press 2002), pp. 270–77Google Scholar
Hutchinson, Allan C., “Calgary and Everything After: A Postmodern Re-Vision of Lawyering,” Alberta Law Review 33: 768–86 (1995)Google Scholar
Bedau, Hugo Adam, ed., Civil Disobedience in Focus (London: Routledge 1991), pp. 68–84CrossRef
Muller, Ingo, Hitler’s Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1992)Google Scholar
Fuller, Lon L., “Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart,” Harvard Law Review 71: 630–72 (1958), pp. 650–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, Lon L., The Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, rev’d edn., 1964)Google Scholar
Smith, Clive Stafford, Eight O’clock Ferry to the Windward Side: Seeking Justice in Guantánamo Bay (New York: Nation Books 2007)Google Scholar
Margulies, Joseph, Guantánamo and the Abuse of Presidential Power (New York: Simon & Schuster 2006)Google Scholar
Lahav, Alexandra D., “Portraits of Resistance: Lawyer Responses to Unjust Proceedings,” UCLA Law Review 57: 725–87 (2010)Google Scholar
Luban, David, “Lawfare and Legal Ethics in Guantánamo,” Stanford Law Review 60: 1981–2026 (2008), p. 1987Google Scholar
Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U. S. 507 (2004)
Young, Iris Marion, Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton: Princeton University Press 1990), p. 59Google Scholar
Horwitz, Morton, The Transformation of American Law, 1780–1860 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1977)Google Scholar
Kelman, Mark, A Guide to Critical Legal Studies (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1987)Google Scholar
Binder, Guyora, “Critical Legal Studies,” in Patterson, Dennis, ed., A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell 1996)Google Scholar
Kennedy, Duncan, A Critique of Adjudication {fin de siècle} (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1997)Google Scholar
Unger, Roberto Mangabeira, Knowledge and Politics (New York: Free Press 1987)Google Scholar
Crenshaw, Kimberle, “A Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Law and Politics,” in Kairys, David, ed., The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (New York: Pantheon Books, rev’d edn., 1990)Google Scholar
Williams, Patricia J., “The Pain of Word Bondage,” in The Alchemy of Race and Rights (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1991)Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1986), p. 52Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1979), pp. 16–17Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, “Authority, Law, and Morality,” in Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1994), p. 214Google Scholar
Simmons, A. John, Political Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2008), p. 40Google Scholar
Raz, Joseph, “A Right to Dissent? Civil Disobedience,” in The Authority of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1979)Google Scholar
Vischer, Robert K., Martin Luther King Jr. and the Morality of Legal Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2013), pp. 210–13Google Scholar
Lyons, David, Ethics and the Rule of Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1984), pp. 84–85Google Scholar
Southall, Ashley and Healy, Jack, “U.S. Won’t Sue to Reverse States’ Legalization of Marijuana,” N.Y. Times (Aug. 29, 2013)Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, “Civil Disobedience,” in Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1977), pp. 207–11Google Scholar
Rhode, Deborah L., In the Interests of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2000), pp. 76–79Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A., “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals,” Harvard Law Review 71: 593–629 (1958), p. 618CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ziv, Neta, “Lawyers Talking Rights and Clients Breaking Rules: Between Legal Positivism and Distributive Justice in Israeli Poverty Lawyering,” Clinical Law Review 11: 209–39 (2004), p. 228Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald, Law’s Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1986), p. 225Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×