Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-k7p5g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T23:32:49.257Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Legislatures and intentions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2012

Neil Duxbury
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
Get access

Summary

Legisprudence, once cast as an argument in favour of majority decision and against judicial review of the constitutionality of legislation, looks to be a more provocative project than it has ever appeared hitherto. But it would be uncharitable to suggest that legisprudence offers only one argument of note; it has on its agenda certainly one other topic of long-standing concern to jurists and political theorists, a topic which ranks as one of the core conundrums of legal philosophy. This is the problem of legislative intent. If intentions can reasonably be ascribed to legislatures, then courts and other interpretive agencies – if they are to abide by the separation of powers doctrine, and if they are to treat legislatures as vested with a mandate to enact laws for the citizenry – have a prima facie obligation to strive to respect those intentions. But how, if at all, could it ever make sense to speak of ‘legislative intent’, given that legislatures, as corporate bodies, cannot form and act on intentions as individual agents do?

One response to this question delivers it short shrift. If we accept that ‘one cannot look at the marks on a page and understand those marks to be a text (i.e., a meaningful writing) without assuming that an author made those marks intending to convey a meaning by them’, then it matters not whether the text is ascribed to an individual or corporate author. The text was intended. Interpreting a statute simply means working out (and, if we are to avoid interpolation, not going beyond) the intention of the statute’s author in the same way that we work out a speaker’s intention in everyday life – by taking into account not only the words used but also what we know about the author and the context of the author’s pronouncement. If there appear to be inconsistent intentions embodied in a legislature’s rules, the interpreter should take it that ‘the meanings of the rules are … what binding effects the rule maker would declare the rules to have when confronted with such conflicts and inconsistencies’. The fact that intentions may be difficult to discern – because of such inconsistencies, or because legislators sometimes use words which express more or less than what they meant to say, or because a legislature may have more than one intention when enacting a statute – does not mean that no legislative intention exists. It has to exist. There cannot be a statute without it.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexander, LarrySherwin, EmilyDemystifying Legal ReasoningCambridge University Press 2008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J.A Difficulty in the Concept of Social Welfare 1950 58 Jnl Pol. Econ.328CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shepsle, Kenneth A.Congress is a “They”, Not an “It”: Legislative Intent as Oxymoron 1992 12 Int. Rev. L. & Econ.239CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, CalebA Response to Professor Manning 2005 91 Virginia L. Rev.451Google Scholar
Dworkin, RonaldLaw’s EmpireLondonFontana 1986Google Scholar
Goldsworthy, JeffreyDworkin as an Originalist 2000 17 Constitutional Commentary49Google Scholar
Michelman, Frank H.Statutes 1983 50 Univ. Chicago L. Rev.533Google Scholar
Dworkin, RonaldJustice for HedgehogsCambridge, Mass.Belknap Press 2011Google Scholar
1839
Lauterpacht, HerschSome Observations on Preparatory Work in the Interpretation of Treaties 1935 48 Harvard L. Rev.549CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, JohnCollected Essays. Volume IV: Philosophy of LawOxford University Press 2011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, J. H.Statutory Interpretation and Parliamentary Intention 1993 52 CLJ353CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steyn, Johan; A Re-examination 2001 21 OJLS59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, John ChipmanThe Nature and Sources of the LawNew YorkMacmillan 1921Google Scholar
Pound, RoscoeCourts and Legislation 1913 77 Central L. J.219Google Scholar
Radin, MaxStatutory Interpretation 1930 43 Harvard L. Rev.863CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horak, Frank E.In the Name of Legislative Intention 1932 38 W. Virginia L. Q.119Google Scholar
1999
Frankfurter, FelixSome Reflections on the Reading of Statutes 1947 47 Columbia L. Rev.527CrossRefGoogle Scholar
1956
Waldron, JeremyThe Dignity of LegislationCambridge University Press 1999CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatton, ChristopherA Treatise Concerning Statutes, or Acts of Parliament: And the Exposition thereofLondonprinted for Richard Tonson 1677Google Scholar
MacCallum, Gerald C.Legislative Intent 1966 75 Yale L. J.754Google Scholar
Solan, Lawrence M.Private Language, Public Laws: The Central Role of Legislative Intent in Statutory Interpretation 2005 93 Georgetown L. J.427Google Scholar
Hurd, Heidi M.Sovereignty in Silence 1990 99 Yale L. J.945CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCubbins, Mathew D.Noll, Roger G.Weingast, Barry R.Legislative Intent: The Use of Positive Political Theory in Statutory Interpretation 1994 57 Law & Contemporary Problems3Google Scholar
Dworkin, RonaldA Matter of PrincipleOxfordClarendon Press 1986Google Scholar
Searle, JohnIntentions in CommunicationCambridge, Mass.MIT Press 1990Google Scholar
Goldsworthy, JeffreyThe Sovereignty of Parliament: History and PhilosophyOxfordClarendon Press 1999Google Scholar
Gardner, JohnCommon Law TheoryCambridge University Press 2007Google Scholar
Bix, BrianLaw, Language, and Legal DeterminacyOxfordClarendon Press 1993Google Scholar
Raz, JosephBetween Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical ReasonOxford University Press 2009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schauer, FrederickPlaying by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in LifeOxfordClarendon Press 1991Google Scholar
Landis, James M.A Note on “Statutory Interpretation” 1930 43 Harvard L. Rev.886CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, JohnNatural Law and Natural RightsOxfordClarendon Press 2011Google Scholar
Shepsle, Kenneth A.Weingast, Barry R.Structure-Induced Equilibrium and Legislative Choice 1981 37 Public Choice503CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luppia, ArthurMcCubbins, MathewLost in Transation: Social Choice Theory is Misapplied against Legislative Intent 2005 14 Jnl of Contemporary Legal Issues585Google Scholar
Mackie, GerryDemocracy DefendedCambridge University Press 2005Google Scholar
Ekins, Richard 2009
List, ChristianPettit, PhilipGroup Agency: The Possibility, Design, and Status of Corporate AgentsOxford University Press 2011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easterbrook, Frank H.The Role of Original Intent in Statutory Construction 1988 11 Harvard J. Law & Pub. Pol.59Google Scholar
Marmor, AndreiInterpretation and Legal TheoryOxfordHart 2005Google Scholar
Skinner, QuentinMeaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas 1969 8 History and Theory3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
The Law Commission and the Scottish Law CommissionThe Interpretation of StatutesLondonHMSO 1969Google Scholar
Vogenauer, StefanWhat is the Proper Role of Legislative Intention in Statutory Interpretation? 1997 18 Statute L. Rev.235CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, Arthur S.Statutory Language and the Purposive Use of Ambiguity 1956 42 Virginia L. Rev.23CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Legislatures and intentions
  • Neil Duxbury, London School of Economics and Political Science
  • Book: Elements of Legislation
  • Online publication: 05 December 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139135009.008
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Legislatures and intentions
  • Neil Duxbury, London School of Economics and Political Science
  • Book: Elements of Legislation
  • Online publication: 05 December 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139135009.008
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Legislatures and intentions
  • Neil Duxbury, London School of Economics and Political Science
  • Book: Elements of Legislation
  • Online publication: 05 December 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139135009.008
Available formats
×