Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-m9pkr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T23:08:25.221Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Fidelity to text

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 December 2012

Neil Duxbury
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
Get access

Summary

When we interpret something, we find meaning in it. This is not to claim that all cognition is interpretive, for we can react to something without detecting meaning. Nor would it be correct to say that when we interpret we must be seeking to explain, for we can draw inferences about matters within our awareness without trying to provide an explanation of them (even an explanation to ourselves). It does seem right, however, to say that interpretation and explanation are close cousins in the sense that, often, the point of interpretation is to make a case regarding how something might be understood, or how it is best understood.

The meaning we find in something may be that which we put there, as when we attribute significance to omens or certain types of memento. But often interpretation is a matter of purporting to find in something a meaning which is in some way attributable to someone else, as when a musician interprets a composer’s score. Meaning, understood in this attributive sense, is sometimes used as a synonym: what the interpreter took the author to have meant is what he took the author to have intended. But – this point surfaced in the last chapter, and is worth keeping in mind when thinking about statutory interpretation – meaning and intention are distinguishable concepts. The meaning of a text does not have to connect to the intentions of the person who produced or endorsed it. If I randomly plagiarise from a variety of sources, without even bothering to read the passages that I cut and paste, the resultant text may still be interpreted as having meaning, even though I had no intentions as to what the text ought to be taken to mean. Even when communicative intention is discernible, it might still be possible to distinguish intention and meaning. The language we use when addressing others, for example, may contain meanings which our addressees infer but which we never intended.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2012

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Raz, JosephBetween Authority and Interpretation: On the Theory of Law and Practical ReasonOxford University Press 2009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oliver, LordA Judicial View of Modern Legislation 1993 14 Statute L. Rev.1Google Scholar
Stephen, James FitzjamesThe Criminal Code (1879) 1880 7 The Nineteenth Century136Google Scholar
Easterbrook, Frank H.The Role of Original Intent in Statutory Construction 1988 11 Harvard Jnl of Law & Public Policy59Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A.The Road to SerfdomLondonRoutledge and Kegan Paul 1944Google Scholar
Raz, JosephThe Authority of Law: Essays on Law and MoralityOxfordClarendon Press 1979CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hart, Henry M.Sacks, Albert M.The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making and Application of LawWestbury, N.Y.Foundation Press 1994Google Scholar
Nelson, CalebWhat is Textualism? 2005 91 Virginia L. Rev.347Google Scholar
Endicott, Timothy A. O.Vagueness in LawOxford University Press 2000CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Orman Quine, WillardWord and ObjectCambridge, Mass.MIT Press 1960Google Scholar
Schauer, FrederickPlaying by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in LifeOxfordClarendon Press 1991Google Scholar
Dickerson, ReedThe Interpretation and Application of StatutesBostonLittle Brown & Co. 1975Google Scholar
Nelson, CalebStatutory InterpretationNew YorkFoundation Press 2011Google Scholar
Derrida, JacquesOf GrammatologyBaltimoreJohns Hopkins University Press 1976Google Scholar
Derrida, JacquesWriting and DifferenceLondonRoutledge and Kegan Paul 1978Google Scholar
Austin, JohnLectures on Jurisprudence or the Philosophy of Positive LawLondonMurray 1885Google Scholar
Scalia, AntoninAssorted Canards of Contemporary Legal Analysis 1990 40 Case Western Reserve L. Rev.581Google Scholar
Posner, Richard A.Legal Formalism, Legal Realism, and the Interpretation of Statutes and the Constitution 1986 37 Case Western Reserve L. Rev.179Google Scholar
Llewellyn, Karl N.Remarks on the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons about How Statutes are to be Construed 1950 3 Vanderbilt L. Rev.395Google Scholar
Scalia, AntoninA Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the LawPrinceton University Press 1997Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R.Interpreting Statutes in the Regulatory State 1989 103 Harvard L. Rev.405CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elhauge, EinerPreference Eliciting Statutory Default Rules 2002 102 Columbia L. Rev.2162CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Willis, JohnStatute Interpretation in a Nutshell 1938 16 Can. Bar Rev.1Google Scholar
Radin, MaxStatutory Interpretation 1930 43 Harvard L. Rev.863CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutteridge, H. C.A Comparative View of the Interpretation of Statute Law 1933 8 Tulane L. Rev.1Google Scholar
Cross, RupertStatutory InterpretationOxford University Press 2005Google Scholar
Elhauge, EinerStatutory Default Rules: How to Interpret Unclear LegislationCambridge, Mass.Harvard University Press 2008Google Scholar
Johnstone, QuintinAn Evaluation of the Rules of Statutory Interpretation 1954 3 Kansas L. Rev.1Google Scholar
Lieber, FrancisLegal and Political Hermeneutics, or Principles of Interpretation and Construction in Law and Politics, with Remarks on Precedents and AuthoritiesBostonLittle & Brown 1839CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vermeule, AdrianCycles of Statutory Interpretation 2001 68 Univ. Chicago L. Rev.149CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, CalebA Response to Professor Manning 2005 91 Virginia L. Rev.451Google Scholar
Diplock, KennethThe Courts as LegislatorsBirminghamHoldsworth Club 1965Google Scholar
The Law Commission and the Scottish Law CommissionThe Interpretation of StatutesLondonHMSO 1969Google Scholar
1975
Jaffe, Louis L.English and American Judges as LawmakersOxfordClarendon Press 1969Google Scholar
Munday, RoderickThe Common Lawyer 1983 14 Rechtstheorie191Google Scholar
Steyn, JohanThe Intractable Problem of The Interpretation of Legal Texts 2003 25 Sydney L. Rev.5Google Scholar
Frankfurter, FelixSome Reflections on the Reading of Statutes 1947 47 Columbia L. Rev.527CrossRefGoogle Scholar
1950
Nietzsche, FriedrichNachlaß 1885–1887Berlinde Gruyter/DTV 1999Google Scholar
de Montaigne, MichelThe Complete EssaysLondonPenguin 2003Google Scholar
Lavigne, Claire-HélèneDroit, traduction, langue et idéologie: ou la traduction pas à pas selon Justinien 1er 2005 18 Traduction, terminologie, rédaction183CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maclean, IanInterpretation and Meaning in the Renaissance: The Case of LawCambridge University Press 1992Google Scholar
Pringsheim, FritzJustinian’s Prohibition of Commentaries to the Digest 1950 5 Revue internationale des droits de l’antiquité383Google Scholar
Berger, AdolfThe Emperor Justinian 1945 3 Quarterly Bulletin of the Polish Institute of Arts and Sciences in America656Google Scholar
Mandarikis, Georg S.Justinians Verbot der Gesetzeskommentierung 1956 78 Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte: Romanistische Abteilung369Google Scholar
Klingenberg, EberhardText und Kommentar. Archäologie der literarischen Kommunikation IVMunichFink 1995Google Scholar
Solan, Lawrence M.The Language of Statutes: Laws and their InterpretationPrinceton University Press 2010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
1997
1998
1945
Easterbrook, Frank H.Text, History, and Structure in Statutory Interpretation 1994 17 Harvard Jnl of Law & Public Policy61Google Scholar
Steyn, LordDynamic Interpretation Amidst an Orgy of Statutes 2004 3 European Human Rights L. Rev.245Google Scholar
Traynor, Roger J.Statutes Revolving in Common-Law Orbits 1968 17 Catholic Univ. L. Rev.401Google Scholar
Atiyah, P. S.Common Law and Statute Law 1985 48 MLR1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatson, JackThe Role of Statute in the Development of Common Law Doctrine 2001 117 LQR247Google Scholar
Finn, PaulInterpreting StatutesSydneyFederation Press 2005Google Scholar
Bennion, FrancisThe Need for Training in Statute Law 1982 79 Law Soc. Gaz.219Google Scholar
1999
Holmes, O. W.Holmes–Laski Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Harold J. Laski 1916–1935Cambridge, Mass.Harvard University Press 1953Google Scholar
1921
Holmes, O. W.The Theory of Legal Interpretation 1899 12 Harvard L. Rev.417CrossRefGoogle Scholar
1918
1901
Posner, Richard A.The Problems of JurisprudenceCambridge, Mass.Harvard University Press 1990Google Scholar
Craies, William FeildenA Treatise on Statute LawLondonStevens & Haynes 1911Google Scholar
Sedgwick, TheodoreA Treatise on the Rules Which Govern the Interpretation and Application of Statutory and Constitutional LawNew YorkVoorhies 1857Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, LudwigPhilosophical InvestigationsOxfordBlackwell 1978Google Scholar
Greenawalt, KentThe Nature of Rules and the Meaning of Meaning 1997 72 Notre Dame L. Rev.1449Google Scholar
Friendly, Henry J.BenchmarksUniversity of Chicago Press 1967Google Scholar
Frank, JeromeWords and Music: Some Remarks on Statutory Interpretation 1947 47 Columbia L. Rev.1259CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, Carleton KempLaw in the MakingOxfordClarendon Press 1939Google Scholar
Posner, Richard A.Statutory Interpretation – in the Classroom and in the Courtroom 1983 50 Univ. Chicago L. Rev.800CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuller, Lon L.The Case of the Speluncean Explorers 1949 62 Harvard L. Rev.616CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eskridge, William N.The New Textualism 1990 37 UCLA L. Rev.621Google Scholar
1953
1979
1910
1922
1939
Stevens, RobertLaw and Politics: The House of Lords as a Judicial Body, 1800–1976Chapel HillUniversity of North Carolina Press 1978Google Scholar
F. W. M[aitland]Encyclopædia BritannicaNew YorkCambridge University Press 1910Google Scholar
Driedger, E. A.Statutes: The Mischievous Literal Golden Rule 1981 59 Can. Bar Rev.780Google Scholar
Corry, J. A.Administrative Law and the Interpretation of Statutes 1936 1 Univ. Toronto L. J.286CrossRefGoogle Scholar
1936
Hopkins, E. RussellThe Literal Canon and the Golden Rule 1937 15 Can. Bar Rev.689Google Scholar
Williams, GlanvilleThe Meaning of Literal Interpretation 1981 131 New LJ1128Google Scholar
de Sloovère, Frederick J.Preliminary Questions in Statutory Interpretation 1932 9 New York Univ. Law Q. Rev.407Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Fidelity to text
  • Neil Duxbury, London School of Economics and Political Science
  • Book: Elements of Legislation
  • Online publication: 05 December 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139135009.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Fidelity to text
  • Neil Duxbury, London School of Economics and Political Science
  • Book: Elements of Legislation
  • Online publication: 05 December 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139135009.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Fidelity to text
  • Neil Duxbury, London School of Economics and Political Science
  • Book: Elements of Legislation
  • Online publication: 05 December 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139135009.010
Available formats
×