Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-x5cpj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-29T13:25:38.461Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Chapter 5 - Problems with a rationalist account of classical mechanics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 February 2010

Get access

Summary

Introduction: Some philosophers on the logic of science and classical mechanics

From Mill to Popper

Our ultimate aim in Part II is to understand the sense in which microeconomic studies such as the income maintenance experiments may perhaps be science experiments, or realizations of a rationalist program of social inquiry. To achieve that aim, it will help to first develop a concept of physical science with which to compare our income maintenance examples. Just as in Chapters 2 and 4 we focused on the logics of statistical inference, here we shall consider the logic of classical mechanics experiments. We develop our view of the logic of such experiments by distillation of the views of J. S. Mill, Karl Popper, and Thomas Kuhn on science generally and through close scrutiny of some examples from classical mechanics.

In explaining a feature of his Deductive Method, Mill offers an embryonic rationalist account of science:

… that of collating the conclusions of the ratiocination with the concrete phenomena themselves, or, when such are obtainable, with the empirical laws. The ground of confidence in any concrete deductive science is not the a priori reasoning itself, but the accordance between its results and those of observation a posteriori.

(1973, pp. 896–7)

On Mill's account, then, one begins (at least on reconstruction) with a set of propositions, deduces some conclusions, and compares the deduced conclusions with observations or perhaps with observed regularities (= “empirical laws”). So on Mill's view, a science experiment seems unproblematic.

Type
Chapter
Information
Conceptual Anomalies in Economics and Statistics
Lessons from the Social Experiment
, pp. 119 - 149
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1989

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×