Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-m8s7h Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T06:06:05.694Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Sen's capability approach and feminist concerns

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Ingrid Robeyns
Affiliation:
Senior Researcher in Political Theory Radboud University Nijmegen The Netherlands
Flavio Comim
Affiliation:
University of Cambridge
Mozaffar Qizilbash
Affiliation:
University of York
Sabina Alkire
Affiliation:
University of Oxford
Get access

Summary

Introduction

There is by now a vast feminist literature arguing that mainstream normative theories (whether they focus on inequality, poverty, well-being, social justice or policy reform) are often false gender-neutral and androcentric. Theories are false gender-neutral and androcentric when they pretend to be theories which apply equally to men and women, but upon closer scrutiny they are focusing mainly on male experiences and interests, thereby ignoring aspects of social institutions, or dimensions of well-being, that are of special importance to women and children. Often these theories have a poor underlying notion of gender, or implicitly rely upon sexist or androcentric assumptions, or incorporate empirical claims about gender issues that are highly contested. Susan Okin's (1989) seminal work in this area criticised several social justice theories, ranging from communitarian to libertarian, for failing to properly incorporate the interests of women and families. Elizabeth Anderson (1999) critiques the ‘luck egalitarian’ theories within liberal political philosophy for not being able to adequately deal with women's caring responsibilities and the dependency of children, the disabled and frail elderly. Iris Young (1990) and Nancy Fraser (1998) have argued that theories of distributive justice are structurally limited in dealing with key feminist concerns such as the gendered division of labour. Eva Kittay (1999) showed that Rawls's (1971) theory of justice cannot adequately deal with the interests and needs of dependants and caregivers, and therefore cannot adequately account for inequalities between women and men.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Capability Approach
Concepts, Measures and Applications
, pp. 82 - 104
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agarwal, Bina 1997. ‘ “Bargaining” and gender relations: within and beyond the household’, Feminist Economics 3(1): 1–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth 1999. ‘What is the point of equality?’, Ethics 109: 287–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhargava, Rajeev 1992. Individualism in the social sciences. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bourdieu, Pierre 2001. Masculine domination. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Bubeck, Diemut 1995. Care, gender and justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Folbre, Nancy 1994. Who pays for the kids? Gender and the structures of constraint. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Folbre, Nancy 1997. ‘Gender coalitions: extrafamilial influences on intrafamily inequality’, in Haddad, L., John, H. and Alderman, H. (eds.) Intrahousehold resource allocation in developing countries: models, methods, and policy. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 263–274.Google Scholar
Folbre, Nancy 2001. The invisible heart. Economics and family values. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Folbre, Nancy, and Nelson, Julie 2000. ‘For love or money – or both?’, Journal of Economic Perspectives 14(4): 123–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraser, Nancy 1998. ‘Social justice in the age of identity politics: redistribution, recognition, and participation’, in Peterson, G. (ed.) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, pp. 1–67.Google Scholar
Gershuny, Jonathan 2000. Changing times. Work and leisure in post-industrial societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldin, Claudia, and Rouse, Cecilia 2000. ‘Orchestrating impartiality: the impact of “blind” auditions on female musicians’, American Economic Review 90 (4): 715–741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gornick, Janet, and Meyers, Marcia 2003. Families that work. Policies for reconciling parenthood and employment. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
Himmelweit, Susan 1995. ‘The discovery of “unpaid work”: the social consequences of the expansion of “work”’, Feminist Economics 1(2): 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Himmelweit, Susan 2000. ‘Introduction’, in Himmelweit, S. (ed.) Inside the household: from labour to care. London: Macmillan, pp. xv–xxxiii.Google Scholar
Humphries, Jane 1982. ‘Book review of a treatise of the family, by Gary Becker’, The Economic Journal 92: 739–740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimmel, Michael 2000. The gendered society. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kittay Feder, Eva 1999. Love's labor. Essays on women, equality and dependency. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Komter, Aafke 1989. ‘Hidden power in marriage’, Gender & Society 3(2): 187–216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuklys, Wiebke, and Robeyns, Ingrid 2005. ‘Sen's capability approach to welfare economics’, in Kuklys, WiebkeSen's capability approach: theoretical insights and empirical applications. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Lipsitz-Bem, Sandra 1993. The lenses of gender: transforming the debate on sexual inequality. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Lipsitz-Bem, Sandra 1998. An unconventional family. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
MIT Committees on the Status of Women Faculty 2002. Reports. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT.
Neumark, David, Bank, Roy J., and Nort, Kyle D. 1996. ‘Sex discrimination in restaurant hiring: an audit study’, Quarterly Journal of Economics 111: 915–941.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha 2000. Women and human development: the capabilities approach. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Okin, Susan 1989. Justice, gender and the family. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Phillips, Anne 1999. Which inequalities matter?Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas 2002. ‘Can the capability approach be justified?’, Philosophical Topics 30(2): 167–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John 1971. A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid 2000. ‘An unworkable idea or a promising alternative? Sen's capability approach re-examined’, Center for Economic Studies Discussion paper 00.30. Leuven, Belgium: University of Leuven.Google Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid 2001. ‘Will a basic income do justice to women?’, Analyse und Kritik 23(1): 88–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid 2003a. ‘Does the gender division of labor result in unjust inequalities?’, paper presented at the Annual Meetings of the American Political Science Association, Philadelphia.
Robeyns, Ingrid 2003b. ‘Sen's capability approach and gender inequality: selecting relevant capabilities’, Feminist Economics 9(2/3): 61–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid 2005a. ‘The capability approach: a theoretical survey’, Journal of Human Development 6(1): 93–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid 2005b. ‘Assessing global poverty and inequality: income, resources and capabilities’, Metaphilosophy 36(1–2): 30–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robeyns, Ingrid 2005c. ‘Selecting capabilities for quality of life measurement’, Social Indicators Research 74(1): 191–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1980. ‘Equality of what?’, in McMurrin, S. (ed.) The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press, pp. 196–220.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1984a. ‘The living standard’, Oxford Economic Papers 36: 74–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1984b. ‘Rights and capabilities’, in his Resources, values and development. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, pp. 307–324.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1985a. Commodities and capabilities. Amsterdam: North Holland.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1985b. ‘Well-being, agency and freedom’, The Journal of Philosophy LXXXII (4): 169–221.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1987. ‘The standard of living’, in Hawthorn, G. (ed.) The standard of living. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1990. ‘Justice: means versus freedoms’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 19: 111–121.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1992. Inequality re-examined. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1993. ‘Capability and well-being’, in Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. (eds.) The Quality of Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 30–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1995. ‘Gender inequality and theories of justice’, in Nussbaum, M. and Glover, J. (eds.) Women, culture and development: a study of human capabilities. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 259–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya 1999. Development as freedom. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
United Nations Development Program 1995. Human development report. New York: Oxford University Press.
Valian, Virginia 1998. Why so slow? The advancement of women. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT press.Google Scholar
Parijs, Philippe 1995. Real freedom for all. What (if anything) can justify capitalism?Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Wennerås, Christine, and Wold, Agnes 1997. ‘Nepotism and sexism in peer-review’, Nature 387: 341–343.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woolley, Frances, and Marshall, Judith 1994. ‘Measuring inequality within the household’, Review of Income and Wealth 40(4): 415–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, Iris Marion 1990. Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion 2001. ‘Equality of whom? Social groups and judgments of injustice’, The Journal of Political Philosophy 9(1): 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×