Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-cjp7w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-07T00:25:48.461Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

69 - Equal opportunity, democratic interpretation

from E

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2015

Jon Mandle
Affiliation:
State University of New York, Albany
David A. Reidy
Affiliation:
University of Tennessee, Knoxville
Get access

Summary

In Rawls’s very first statement of his two principles of justice, the second principle says that social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that “it is reasonable to expect that they will work out for everyone’s advantage, and provided the positions and ofices to which they attach . . . are open to all” (“Justice as Fairness” [1958] in CP 48). In subsequent writings in the 1960s and in his initial statement of the two principles in A Theory of Justice (TJ 53) the core formulation of the second principle, requiring “everyone’s advantage” and positions “open to all,” is retained.

Rawls recognizes the key terms, “everyone’s advantage” and “open to all” (or “equally open”), require explication. He provides this by developing (TJ §§12 and 13) three different ways to interpret the second principle of justice, and in each of these interpretations the two key terms are linked together. Here he closely follows the pattern set in his important 1968 paper “Distributive Justice: Some Addenda” (CP 158–164).

The first interpretation is called by Rawls the system of natural liberty (a term he takes from Adam Smith). Two distinct themes are involved here. One is that positions are “equally open” where there are no legal or institutional or customary barriers that restrict entry into an occupation to one class or kind of individual and no formal restrictions on the taking of opportunities. The result of ending such restrictions would be “careers open to talents’’; individuals would be free to exercise their talents or seize opportunities up to the limit of their own abilities. This leads directly to the second theme. In a system of natural liberty (assuming a self-stabilizing open and competitive supply–demand free market system), the ideal result would be a recurring tendency toward pareto-optimal efficiency in the exchange of goods and services.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×