Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T23:28:09.551Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

27 - American neopragmatism and its background

from PHILOSOPHY, AESTHETICS AND LITERARY CRITICISM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Christa Knellwolf
Affiliation:
Australian National University, Canberra
Christopher Norris
Affiliation:
University of Wales College of Cardiff
Get access

Summary

The lure of euphoric certainty: C. S. Peirce and William James

Pragmatism may not be uniquely American in its origins. The German thinkers F. A. Lange and Hans Vaihinger are pragmatist when they hold that believing something unproven by experiment could still be good for you. G. T. Fechner and the French philosopher Charles Renouvier encouraged William James to believe whatever James found to contribute in the long run to human happiness. Judith Ryan detects in James traces of Austrian thought, namely Ernst Mach: ‘What is valid for me is not what is true, but what I need.’ Whatever its provenance, pragmatism comes to have an instinctive appeal to Americans, with whom common sense comes robustly into play, the same national feature that John Dewey in ‘The Practical Character of Reality’ (1908) will call ‘gumption’ or ‘horse sense’, ‘taking hold of things right end up’. Charles Sanders Peirce says that pragmatism is nothing more than the application of the old saw that ‘by their fruits ye shall know them’, acknowledging James’ view that the value of a concept lies in the future conduct that issues from that concept. The meaning of a belief is the action that the belief makes possible. The Greek word pragma, as James points out, means action. It is a word from which ‘practice’ and ‘practical’ derive. Americans are thought to be both restlessly active and future-oriented, hence the native appeal to them of pragmatism. They are said to be impatient with making unnecessary, impractical distinctions. They are blessedly unreflective and optimistic, hence their resentment at Grübelsucht, a word William James uses to refer to the morbid melancholy brooding supposedly characteristic of Germans.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Appleby, Joyce, Hunt, Lynn, and Jacob, Margaret, Telling the Truth About History, New York: Norton, 1994.Google Scholar
Begley, Adam, ‘Souped-Up Scholar’, The New York Times Magazine, 3 May, 1992.Google Scholar
Bloom, Allan, The Closing of the American Mind, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987.Google Scholar
Bourdieu, Pierre, Distinction, A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, trans. Nice, Richard, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Buchler, Justus (ed.), Philosophical Writings of Peirce, New York: Dover, 1955.Google Scholar
Copleston, Frederick, Modern Philosophy: Empiricism, Idealism, and Pragmatism in Britain and America, New York: Doubleday, 1994.Google Scholar
De Man, Paul, Aesthetic Ideology, ed. Warminski, Andrzej, Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press, 1996.Google Scholar
De Man, Paul, The Rhetoric of Romanticism, New York: Columbia University Press, 1984.Google Scholar
Dewey, John, Art as Experience (1934), New York: Berkley Perigree Books, 1980.Google Scholar
Fish, Stanley, ‘Boutique Multiculturalism, or Why Liberals are Incapable of Thinking about Hate Speech’, Critical Inquiry 23 (Winter 1997).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fish, Stanley, Doing What Comes Naturally: Change, Rhetoric, and the Practice of Theory in Literary and Legal Studies, Durham: Duke University Press, 1989.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fish, Stanley, Is There a Text in This Class?: The Authority of interpretive communities, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980.Google Scholar
Fish, Stanley, Professional Correctness, Literary Studies and Political Change, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.Google Scholar
Fish, Stanley, There's No Such Thing as Free Speech and It's a Good Thing, Too, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994.Google Scholar
Heidegger, Martin, Being and Time, trans. Macquarrie, John and Robinson, Edward, New York and Evanston: Harper and Row, 1962.Google Scholar
James, William, Pragmatism (1907), New York: Dover, 1995.Google Scholar
James, William, Varieties of Religious Experience (1902), New York and London: Collier Books, 1961.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Critique of Judgement (1790), trans. Bernard, J. H., New York: Hafner, 1951.Google Scholar
Knapp, Steven and Michaels, Walter Benn, ‘Against Theory’, Critical Inquiry 8 (1982).Google Scholar
McDermott, John J.The Writings of William James, A Comprehensive Edition, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1977.Google Scholar
McDermott, John J. (ed.), The Philosophy of John Dewey, vol. 1, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1973.Google Scholar
Menand, Louis (ed.), Pragmatism, A Reader, New York: Random House, 1997.Google Scholar
Mitchell, W. J. T. (ed.), Against Theory, Literary Studies and the New Pragmatism, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985.Google Scholar
Norris, Christopher, What's Wrong with Postmodernism, Critical Theory and the Ends of Philosophy, New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1990.Google Scholar
Pavel, Thomas, ‘Lettre d'Amérique: la liberté de parole en question’, Commentaire 69 (Printemps 1995).Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Achieving our Country, Cambridge, Mass. and London: Harvard University Press, 1998.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Consequences of Pragmatism, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Essays on Heidegger and Others, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979.Google Scholar
Ryan, Judith, ‘American Pragmatism, Viennese Psychology’, Raritan 8.3 (Winter 1989).Google Scholar
Shusterman, Richard, Practising Philosophy, Pragmatism and the Philosophical Life, New York and London: Routledge, 1997.Google Scholar
Shusterman, Richard, Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living Beauty, Rethinking Art, Oxford and Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell Publishers, 1992.Google Scholar
Shusterman, Richard, Pragmatist Aesthetics: Living Beauty, Rethinking Art, Oxford: Blackwell, 1992.Google Scholar
Thayer, H. S. (ed.), Pragmatism, The Classic Writings, Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett, 1982.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×