Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-2lccl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-27T04:19:20.729Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

18 - Social Facts and Legal Facts: Perils of Hume’s Guillotine

from Part IV - Main Tenets

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 January 2021

Torben Spaak
Affiliation:
Stockholms Universitet
Patricia Mindus
Affiliation:
Uppsala Universitet, Sweden
Get access

Summary

Gizbert-Studnicki considers how we are to understand the social thesis and whether the social thesis, properly understood, can handle Hume’s guillotine, that is, the problem also known as the fact-value gap or the is-ought problem that Hume first articulated in book III, part I, section I of his A Treatise of Human Nature (1739), according to which one may not logically derive an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’. Having distinguished three interpretations of the social thesis – the social sources thesis, the sources thesis and the social fact thesis – he focuses on the social fact thesis, which is a metaphysical thesis according to which legal facts are ultimately determined by social facts alone. Gizbert-Studnicki then considers three different ways of understanding the relation between social facts and legal facts along the lines of the social fact thesis, namely, reduction, supervenience and grounding. He maintains that while all three relations are more or less problematic, the grounding relation is to be preferred, and that adopting the idea of grounding helps us avoid Hume’s guillotine, since grounding is not a matter of entailment but a metaphysical relation that holds between facts.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Audi, P. 2012. ‘Grounding: Towards a Theory of the In-Virtue-Of Relation’. Journal of Philosophy CIX 12: 685711.Google Scholar
Levenbook, B. 2013. ‘How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis: A Reply to Greenberg and Toh’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law vol. 2. Oxford University Press: 75103.Google Scholar
Burazin, L. 2018. ‘Legal Systems as Abstract Institutional Artifacts’. In Burazin, L., Himma, K. E. and Roversi, C. (eds.). Law as an Artifact. Oxford University Press: 112–35.Google Scholar
Chilovi, C. and Pavlakos, G. 2019. ‘Law-Determination as Grounding: A Common Grounding Framework for Jurisprudence’. Legal Theory 25: 5376.Google Scholar
Coleman, J. 2001. The Practice of Principles. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Correira, F. and Schnieder, B. 2012. ‘Grounding: An Opinionated Introduction’. In Correira, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.). Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press: 210.Google Scholar
Dyrda, A. 2015. ‘Are Fundamental Legal Reasons Internal? A Few Remarks on the Hartian Idea of Internal Point of View’. In Araszkiewicz, M., Banas, P., Gizbert-Studnicki, T. and Pleszka, K. (eds.). Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule-Following. Springer: 229–42.Google Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011a. Taking Morality Seriously: A Defence of Robust Realism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, D. 2011b. ‘Reason Giving and the Law’. In Green, L. and Leiter, B. (eds.). Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law vol. I. Oxford University Press: 138.Google Scholar
Finley, S. 2010. ‘Recent Work on Normativity’. Analysis 70 (2): 331–46.Google Scholar
Gardner, J. 2001. ‘Legal Positivism: 5½ Myths’. The American Journal of Jurisprudence 46: 199227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gizbert-Studnicki, T. 2016. ‘The Social Sources Thesis, Metaphysics and Metaphilosophy’. In Banas, P., Dyrda, A. and Gizbert-Studnicki, T. (eds.). Metaphilosophy of Law. Hart: 121–46.Google Scholar
Gizbert-Studnicki, T. 2017. Legal Theory’s Claim to Necessity. http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3050442.Google Scholar
Gkouvas, T. 2016. ‘Legal Truth without Legal Fact: A Metaontological Argument’. In de Paula, A. F. L., Santacoloma, A. S. and Rosas, G. F. (eds.). Truth and Objectivity in Law and Morals II. ARSP Beiheft, Band 151: 2548.Google Scholar
Green, M. S. 2020. ‘The Semantic Thesis in Legal Positivism’. In Mindus, P. and Spaak, T. (eds.). The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2004. ‘How Facts Make Law’. Legal Theory 10: 157–98.Google Scholar
Greenberg, M. 2006. ‘Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II’. In Hershovitz, S. (ed.). Exploring Law’s Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin. Oxford University Press: 265–90.Google Scholar
Hale, B. 2019. ‘Realism/Philosophy’. Encyclopedia Britannica. www.britannica.com/topic/realism-philosophy.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. 2012. The Concept of Law. 3rd ed. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. [1979]2016. ‘The New Challenge to Legal Positivism’. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 36: 459–75.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1960. A Treatise on Human Nature. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kim, J. 1993. ‘Postscripts on Supervenience’. In Kim, J.. Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge University Press: 161–73.Google Scholar
Kramer, M. 2018. Hart and the Metaphysics and Semantics of Legal Normativity. http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3116861.Google Scholar
Marmor, A. 2011. Philosophy of Law. Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marmor, A. 2013. ‘Farewell to Conceptual Analysis’. In Waluchow, W. and Sciaraffa, S. (eds.). Philosophical Foundations of the Nature of Law. Oxford University Press: 209–29.Google Scholar
McLaughlin, B. and Bennett, K. 2018. ‘Supervenience’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/supervenience/.Google Scholar
Pavlakos, G. 2017. ‘The Metaphysics of Law: From Supervenience to Rational Justification’. In Brozek, B., Rotolo, A. and Stelmach, J. (eds.). Supervenience and Normativity. Springer: 139–60.Google Scholar
Plunkett, D. 2012. ‘A Positivistic Route for Explaining How Facts Make Law’. Legal Theory 18: 139207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Postema, G. 1982. ‘Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law’. Journal of Legal Studies XI: 165203.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 1979. The Authority of Law. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Rosen, G. 2010. ‘Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction’. In Hale, B. and Hoffman, A. (eds.). Modality: Metaphysics, Logic and Epistemology. Oxford University Press: 109–35.Google Scholar
Searle, J. 2006. ‘Social Ontology: Some Basic Principles’. Anthropological Theory 6(1): 1229.Google Scholar
Schaffer, J. 2012. ‘Grounding, Transitivity, and Contrastivity’. In Correira, F. and Schnieder, B. (eds.). Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Cambridge University Press: 122–38.Google Scholar
Shapiro, S. 2011. Legality. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schauer, F. 2017. Deconstructing Law’s Normativity. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=3080437.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2005. ‘Kelsen and Hart on the Normativity of Law’. In Wahlgren, P. and Zamboni, M. (eds.). Perspectives on Jurisprudence: Essays in Honour of Jes Bjarup. Stockholm Institute for Scandinavian Law: 397414.Google Scholar
Spaak, T. 2018. ‘Legal Positivism, Conventionalism and the Normativity of Law’. Jurisprudence 9(2): 319–44.Google Scholar
Tahko, T. and Lowe, E. J. 2016. ‘Ontological Dependence’. In Zalta, E. N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/dependence-ontological/.Google Scholar
Toh, K. 2008. ‘An Argument against the Social Fact Thesis (and Some Additional Preliminary Steps Towards a New Conception of Legal Positivism’. Law and Philosophy 27: 445504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Toh, K. 2014. ‘Four Neglected Prescriptions of Hartian Legal Philosophy’. Law and Philosophy 33: 689724.Google Scholar
Trogdon, K. 2013. ‘An Introduction to Grounding’. In Hoeltje, M., Schnieder, M. and Steinberg, A. (eds.). Varieties of Dependence: Ontological Dependence, Grounding, Supervenience, Response-Dependence (Basic Philosophical Concepts). Philosophia Verlag: 97122.Google Scholar
Vayrynen, P. 2013. ‘Grounding and Normative Explanation’. Proceedings of Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume) 87: 155–78.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×