Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-5nwft Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-21T00:45:35.886Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part II - Patent Holdup, Royalty Stacking, and the FRAND Standard

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 December 2023

Jonathan M. Barnett
Affiliation:
University of Southern California
Sean M. O'Connor
Affiliation:
George Mason University Antonin Scalia Law School, Virginia

Summary

Type
Chapter
Information
5G and Beyond
Intellectual Property and Competition Policy in the Internet of Things
, pp. 51 - 108
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

3 Cellular SEP Royalties and 5G What Should Competition Policy Be?

Alexander Galetovic , Stephen Haber , and Lew Zaretzki
I. Introduction

For the past four decades, technological progress in semiconductors and wireless technology has been driven by specialized firms that develop technologies and license them to downstream chip manufacturers and implementers in exchange for royalties. Specialization and trade in technology along the vertical chain has been one of the hallmarks of fast technological progress, and in wireless communications this pattern has repeated itself across multiple rounds of change in standards. Indeed, 5G is being developed in significant part by the same specialized technology firms that previously helped to develop 3G and 4G. As with previous wireless generations, standardization, patents, and licensing support vertical specialization.

As in all markets, 5G market demand determines the amount of economic surplus produced. Over the past 20 years, technology developers and implementers have battled over the surplus and have sought to leverage policy, regulation, legislation, jurisprudence, popular sentiment, and other dynamics to capture the largest possible share for their stakeholders. Their duty to capture maximum surplus for their stakeholders discourages concern for unintended or unexpected consequences for the market as a whole and for other critical institutions in society.

Meanwhile, however, the battle over surplus has taken place in a market where technology developers compete. We have shown in previous work (which we discuss later) that an equilibrium emerged in wireless 3G and 4G licensing. In this equilibrium, innovators license standard-essential patents (SEPs) and implementers (chiefly, smartphone Original Equipment Manufacturers (OEMs)) pay royalties under a licensing regime in conformity with “fair, reasonable and nondiscriminatory” (FRAND) principles. We estimated that for more than 10 years the cumulative royalty yield paid by the entire phone manufacturing value chain hovered between a market average of 3% and 3.5% of the average selling price of a phone, which seems to be the agreed market price for the technologies that make phones work. We have also shown that the transition between 3G and 4G licensing occurred smoothly, as licensing practices and aggregate royalty levels did not change, despite substantial changes in products and the manufacturers involved.

5G will allow wireless technologies to become part of a broader array of products. When compared with current 4G networks, 5G promises to provide between 10 times and 100 times faster data rates, at latencies up to 10 times smaller. Faster data rates and lower latencies, in turn, may enable new technologies for automated manufacturing, private mobile networks, and fixed wireless access (FWA). These new technologies will create new markets and attract new entrants. For example, Multi-Access Edge Computing (MEC) will invite new participants into the 5G system, which may include firms in semiconductors (for example, Intel), computing (for example, Dell, VMWare), cloud services (for example, AWS) and more.Footnote 1 These new participants may take advantage of opportunities for specialization to create and patent innovations, and may implement external innovations to create new products and services. As such, they may become part of the 5G licensing landscape, whether as licensor, licensee, or both.

What role should competition policy play in emerging 5G markets? The seeming uncertainty about the practices and royalties that will emerge in new licensing markets may tempt antitrust authorities to intervene to regulate licensing or fix and apportion aggregate royalties. Indeed, for many years the Federal Trade Commission, the Department of Justice, the European Commission, and several academics and industry consultants have argued that the market prices that emerge from royalty agreements are the result of “excessive royalties” wrought by the additional monopoly power conferred by standardization. The central point of this chapter, however, is that economic theory and actual experience with royalty setting in 3G and 4G suggest that the revenues that patent holders obtain are not monopoly rents. Indeed, the level of royalties indicate that rents enjoyed by patent holders are Ricardian – that is, these rents reflect the fact that the selected technology creates more value per unit of input than the alternatives, not the exercise of economic market power.Footnote 2 Thus, the rents enjoyed by technology developers are the result of competition among technologies.

Indeed, 5G technology developers and implementers continue to collaborate to develop, produce, and deploy 5G products and services. Further, as with prior cellular technologies, consumers, enterprises, and implementers can choose among many alternatives to 5G for various tasks. Thus, 5G is being deployed under the same conditions that characterize the well-functioning cellular SEP licensing market. This market has achieved a long-term equilibrium across the period of our research (2007–2021), spanning the deployment and use of 2G, 3G, 4G, and 5G technologies. In this equilibrium, cumulative royalties have converged to market values, and the market has apportioned them according to the incremental value generated by each holder’s intellectual property (IP) assets. 5G and prior cellular technologies earn Ricardian rents determined by the differential value that those technologies create over alternatives.

We are, therefore, not aware of a prima facie argument to justify the intervention of competition authorities to regulate 5G royalties. Competition authorities should instead be watchful over the equilibrium that has existed in the market for cellular SEPs over the past decade or more, ensuring that parties do not undermine it through tactics employed to maximize their own share of economic surplus. If parties undermine the equilibrium in this manner, the results could be tragic for the associated technology, product, and service markets.

Further, competition policy should anticipate the arrival of new market participants, and the important role that 5G technology developers will play in the emergence of new markets. It should also anticipate that these new participants and markets may differ from present 5G-enabled participants and markets in terms of structures, behavioral norms, and other salient features. These new participants may lack a history of cellular SEP licensing. Such markets may need to find new solutions to adopt 5G or may need to adopt or adapt approaches from current 5G-enabled cellular SEP markets. Based on the experience of the past two decades across multiple cellular technology generations, it is our view that these markets will find their way to remunerate investments in R&D, so long as SEPs and SEP licensing transactions can be reliably enforced as elsewhere and as appropriate.

The rest of the chapter is organized as follows. In Section II, we briefly describe 5G and how its technological characteristics expand capabilities and alter network architecture. In Section III, we argue that the incremental value that the technology creates at the margin is a rent, and the source of this rent is the factor that informs competition policy. Section IV reviews substitutes that perform part of the functions that 5G can execute. Section V concludes.

II. What Is 5G?

5G provides an integrated cellular system performing the useful and relevant functions typical of prior cellular networks. Like 3G and 4G, 5G also provides a new radio technology (5GNR) and expands technical scope and functionality. In addition, 5G provides revolutionary new options for deployment architecture and opens the door to a broad range of entirely new applications.

A. New 5G Technologies and Capabilities

Table 3.1 shows that 5G will provide data rates potentially up to 20 gigabytes per second (gbps) (v. 4G: 20 megabytes per second (mbps)) and latencies as low as ~1 millisecond (ms) (v. 4G: 20–30 ms), and allow for considerably denser networks, of more than one million connections per square kilometer, which can support massive Internet of Things (IoT) deployments. In addition, 5G networks facilitate private networks (a network built for a specific organization – for example, on a university or corporate campus) and network slicing – that is, reserving part of the network for tailor-made applications for one or more specific clients.

Table 3.1. New 5G technologies and capabilities

CapabilityDescription
eMBBEnhanced Mobile Broadband, providing data rates potentially up to 20 gbps. Enabled in part by 5G improvements such as New Radio (NR) and Millimeter Wave (24–40 GHz frequency band).
URLLCUltra-Reliable Low-Latency Communication, providing latency as low as ~1 ms, for highly sensitive applications such as manufacturing automation.
mMTCMassive Machine Type Communication (>1 m device connections/ km), supporting colossal IoT deployments.
Private NetworksIndependent 5G networks, providing organizations with greater control of deployment, performance levels, and security. This may be useful for the most security conscious organizations, as well as for those most reliant upon network performance (for example, for mission critical industrial operations).
Network SlicingVirtual 5G networks, enabling network operators to tailor services to specific users or uses on their general network. For example, a carrier could offer an IoT-optimized slice to IoT users, or a custom slice to one organization in lieu of building and operating its own private network.

5G also provides greater integration of useful capabilities that were formerly typically located outside cellular systems. For example, MEC (Mobile Access Edge Computing) incorporates processing capabilities at the edges of the network, in part to achieve broader system goals such as low latency. Integration also serves new applications through new specialized subsystems such as C-V2X (Cellular Vehicle to Everything) for safety coordination among vehicles, infrastructure, and other connected devices as well as UAS (Unmanned Aerial Systems) for 5G control of aerial drones.

These new subsystems stand to create value, which mobile operators, infrastructure vendors, users, and suppliers of the attendant new technologies may appropriate. Table 3.2 contains an exemplary list of markets and suppliers that could benefit.

Table 3.2. Potential beneficiary suppliers

System/ featureDescription
MEC
  • Compute hardware vendors (Dell, HPE, Supermicro)

  • Compute software vendors (VMWare, RedHat, etc.)

  • Compute processor vendors (Intel, NVIDIA, AMD)

  • Cloud service providers (AWS, Google Cloud, Microsoft Azure)

C-V2X
  • Automotive OEMs (Toyota, Volkswagen)

  • Automotive tier 1 suppliers (Denso, Bosch, Continental)

  • Automotive other suppliers (embedded, module, TCU, drive computer)

UAS
  • Drone OEMs (DJI, Yuneec, 3D Robotics, Parrot)

Private Networks
  • Enterprises (perhaps especially large/sophisticated organizations)

Network Slicing
  • Enterprises (perhaps especially SMEs or specialist firms)

B. New 5G Distributed Architecture Options

The providers of radio access networks (RANs) for 2G, 3G, and 4G have long provided deeply integrated solutions comprising network equipment, software, and services. The situation resembles that of IBM in the mainframe era, in that a small number of incumbents provide end-to-end solutions to mobile operators. These incumbents, along with their consolidated predecessors such as Nortel and Motorola Networks, helped create the mobile industry. At present, four firms dominate the RAN market. Of these, Huawei and ZTE dominate the market in the People’s Republic of China (PRC) but are excluded from several markets, including the United States, where Nokia and Ericsson enjoy an effective duopoly, as seen in their market revenue shares depicted in Figure 3.1.Footnote 3

Figure 3.1. RAN market revenue by OEM

Source: Base Station Market Poised for Strong Year Thanks to 5G and China According to Omdia, Microwave J. (Dec. 7, 2020)

As we see in Figure 3.2, however, 5G enables new underlying architecture options, including vRAN and Open RAN, which provide network operators with additional supplier options to help build their networks. This architectural opening resembles the move from IBM mainframe to Client/Server, which launched a computing revolution. This change potentially provides opportunities for highly competitive vendors to participate in the 5G system, making it more efficient, less expensive, and more innovative. Leading industry analyst Dell’Oro forecasts Open RAN as 15% of the market by 2026, while vRAN will be 5–10%, and combined these will represent 20–25% of the market within four years.Footnote 4

Figure 3.2. Comparison of RAN architecture options

Open RAN and vRAN enable network operators to move workloads to Commercial-Off-The-Shelf (COTS) equipment from leading computing vendors. Providers can base their equipment on world-class silicon, hardware, and software from some of the most competitive firms in the world, as well as from innovative startups, providing further diversification in the mobile value chain. Operators could use cloud service providers who can further enhance efficiency and handle these workloads as a service. Table 3.3 lists firms that potentially can participate as decentralized providers.

Table 3.3. Firms that potentially can participate as decentralized providers

ElementPotential new beneficiaries

Centralized Unit

Distributed Unit

  • Compute hardware vendors (Dell, HPE, Supermicro)

  • Compute software vendors (VMWare, RedHat, open source)

  • Compute processor vendors (Intel, NVIDIA, AMD)

  • Cloud compute providers (AWS, Google Cloud, Microsoft Azure)

NFV Software
  • OpenRAN startups (Mavenir, Rakuten Symphony, Airspan)

Radio Unit
  • RU providers (Airspan, Casa Systems)

  • Modem providers (Qualcomm, for small cells)

In the special case of Open RAN, operators can obtain radio units from competing vendors beyond the incumbent leaders such as Ericsson and Nokia. Qualcomm’s 5G RAN Platform for Small Cells and FSM200xx processors promises a ready avenue for small-cell entrant providers to provide competitive radio unit products. Enhanced competition in this area appears particularly desirable given the national security imperative to exclude Huawei and ZTE from many key markets.

These new architecture and vendor options promise to enable new players to enter the market for cellular services. Examples include Rakuten in Japan and, following their example, DISH in the United States. New entrants may be very helpful in the United States given the merger of T-Mobile and Sprint, which leaves just three major wireless carriers to serve the US market. The US market suffers from higher wireless prices than many other countries.Footnote 5

The nature of the new system enables new and superior applications. For example, the combination of 5G’s wireless nature and the improved performance through eMBB make 5G FWA a practical alternative to fixed broadband services based on FTTx and DOCSIS. This should benefit wireless carriers, FWA vendors, and broadband consumers.

In short, 5G brings an array of new technologies, scope improvements, features, and applications. While each may create value, the value may accrue to different market segments and participants in each case based on the nature of each improvement. Most improvements may chiefly benefit carriers, while others may chiefly benefit enterprises, vendors of particular types of equipment, software or services, or others. Interestingly, the expanded scope of 5G means that many mobile device vendors may be agnostic to many of these improvements since they are targeted at other markets and other parts of the mobile value chain.

C. The 5G Value Chain

A notable feature of the 5G value chain is that it involves multiple, specialized firms that act in a decentralized fashion, coordinated by standards and market interactions. In that respect, the 5G value chain is like the value chain of previous technological generations, only more advanced and perhaps more complex.

As is well known, the theory of patent holdup and royalty stacking predicts that a market characterized by multiple agents contributing to a standardized technology will be able to exploit monopoly power. According to the theory, the existence of multiple monopolies strangles markets and most of the price paid by consumers will redound to the profit margins of the technology development firms.Footnote 6

A testable implication of the theory is that implementers “see down” the game tree, and therefore refrain from making investments. It is therefore curious that implementers in 5G do not seem to be concerned about this possibility. They are making sizable investments. We think that they are likely drawing on the history of 3G and 4G in making their investment decisions.

III. What Determines Royalties? Lessons from 3G and 4GFootnote 7

In this section, we argue that the appropriate framework to think about royalties in new markets is standard price theory, which explains where value comes from and how it is distributed among the factors of production that create value in any given market. In 5G, IP is one of these factors of production, and its market price – the royalties paid by implementers – will indicate the incremental value that the technology creates at the margin. The main point is that this incremental value is a rent, and the source of this rent informs competition policy.

A. Value and Distribution in Wireless Mobile Markets

Price theory observes that in equilibrium the price paid by consumers equals the value created by the entire production chain at the margin, as determined by the good’s demand curve. This is true whether the good or service is a pound of bread, a bundle of pins, or a phone.

Price theory also shows that the total revenues generated by sales in a market are distributed among the factors of production – those inputs that were involved in the production of the final good – based on the value each adds to total revenues at the margin. It follows that revenues are exhausted by the payments made to the input suppliers along the value chain. These revenues remunerate the opportunity cost of the inputs used in the production of the final good and any rent that factors of production receive.

We follow our 2021 paperFootnote 8 and illustrate these insights with a simple supply and demand graph. Figure 3.3 depicts the observed equilibrium in the smartphone market in 2016. For simplicity, we parameterize the world market with a single linear demand curve and assume that all consumers paid the average selling price of a smartphone.Footnote 9

Figure 3.3. Value and distribution in the smartphone value chain

In 2016, phone manufacturers sold 1.42 billion units for $425.1 billion, at an average selling price of $298.Footnote 10 Because consumers are free to buy a phone, the demand curve shows how much consumers value a smartphone at the margin. On average, $298 is what the least willing consumer in 2016 was willing to pay for a smartphone. Figure 3.3 also shows that most consumers valued their phones at more than $298 and obtained a net surplus when they bought a phone, the difference between their willingness to pay, as shown by the demand curve, and the market price. It follows that the total consumer surplus was equal to the area between the demand curve and the market price for phones. According to the demand curve depicted in Figure 3.3, consumer surplus in 2016 was equal to $784 billion.Footnote 11

Figure 3.3 also shows how the revenues generated by the sale of smartphones were distributed among phone manufacturers and input suppliers. Roughly 20% of the revenues accrued to semiconductor manufacturers ($85 billion; $60 per smartphone, on average); 5% accrued to manufacturers of baseband processors ($22 billion; $15 per smartphone, on average); and 60% of the revenues ($254.1 billion; $178 per smartphone, on average) accrued to the producers of other inputs, such as the firms that made the cameras, gorilla glass, and housings, as well as the firms, such as Foxconn, that assembled the phones. Around 12% ($50 billion; or $35 per smartphone) reached the firms that sold the phones in the form of profits, most of which accrued to Apple.

IP is an asset, and royalties are the revenues that this asset generates. As can be seen in Figure 3.3, 3.4% of the revenue generated by the smartphone market reached the owners of patents ($14.2 billion, or roughly $10 per smartphone). Most of this ($12.4 billion) was earned by SEP owners. The remainder was largely earned by non-SEP patents, held by firms such as Microsoft (which earned royalties mainly on the patents on its operating system and software technologies), the patent pools that license audio and video codecs, and patent assertion entities that own the patents necessary to manufacture semiconductors.

Figure 3.4. Monopoly licensor sets the royalty rate

The distribution of the $425.1 billion in revenues among input providers reflects the choices that firms in the production chain made to substitute away from more expensive inputs toward less expensive inputs. Thus, firms at the end of the production chain, which designed and marketed the phones (for example, Samsung, Apple), combined inputs from many suppliers to minimize the costs of producing the smartphones that consumers valued. Similarly, the firms that produced the intermediate inputs and IP for those smartphones (for example, Corning, Ericsson) also combined inputs from many suppliers to minimize costs. Those suppliers, in turn, purchased the necessary inputs from firms even further up the production chain, and so on. Each input in the production chain had its own demand curve. That is, the demand curve each producer faced was derived from the demand for smartphones, and the elasticities of each demand curve depended in part on the possibilities for substituting away from that input. Consequently, firms along the production chain equalized the value created by each input at the margin with the input’s market price.

The share of each input in the $425.1 billion in revenues in the smartphone market was therefore the equilibrium outcome of a complex process of cost minimization. Because the output of an upstream firm is the input of firms further downstream, and all value stems ultimately from consumers’ willingness to pay, no stage of the production chain is independent of, and separable from, the others – prices are determined simultaneously in all of them.

What does price theory tell us about how to value the IP necessary to produce a smartphone? The royalty is the rental price of IP and is a function of the value that consumers were willing to pay for the capabilities created by those patented technologies, at the margin, and the possibilities that producers had to substitute away from using those IP assets toward alternative technologies. The finding that the patent holders earned 3.4% of the value of the average smartphone in 2016 has three complementary interpretations. First, the purchaser with the lowest willingness to pay for the average smartphone valued those technologies at the equivalent of just 3.4% of the price she paid for her smartphone. Second, there must have been alternative technologies toward which producers could eventually substitute. If that had not been the case, then the owners of the IP property would have operated as monopolists and charged far more than 3.4% of the value of a phone, a point to which we return later. Third, and importantly, IP owners did not enjoy market power; they could not constrain output to raise prices.

B Economic Rent and the Distribution of Value across the Stages of the Production Chain

Should competition authorities care about the level of royalties? Some argue that patent holders can charge royalties because they enjoy monopoly power, even beyond that granted by the patent. According to this argument, the profits that patent owners obtain are rents wrought by market power, and there is a natural role for competition policy. A different explanation, however, is that the revenues that patent holders obtain are the fair remuneration of their investment, given the risks they took when researching and developing the technology. In this view, the rents enjoyed by patent holders are Ricardian – their origin is that the selected technology creates more value per unit of input than the alternatives, not the exercise of market power. According to this argument, rents are the result of competition among technologies, and there is little, if any, role for competition policy.

Thus, the nature and origin of the rents made by patent holders are central to assessing whether competition policy must do something, if anything, about royalties. To appreciate the difference between a monopoly rent and a Ricardian rent, a few diagrams help.

Consider first a royalty set by a patent holder who holds a monopoly because nobody can produce without infringing the monopolist’s patent. To keep the argument simple, we assume that the monopolist licenses the technology to competitive manufacturers that can produce phones at constant cost c. As Figure 3.4 shows, when fixing the royalty rate, the monopolist patent holder confronts the market demand for the final good, and reasons that if she sets the royalty equal to R, competitive manufacturers will pass on the royalty and set a price p = c + R for a phone.

Thus, by fixing R, the monopolist patent holder controls the final price p. Also, by setting R, the monopolist patent holder controls the per-unit rent. Standard economic theory says, and Figure 3.4 shows, that the monopolist patent holder will increase R to contract output until the marginal revenue from selling phones is equal to the manufacturing cost c. In equilibrium, the price of a phone will be equal to pM = c + RM and then

pMcpM=RMpM=1η,(3.1)

where η is the elasticity of the demand for phones. It follows that, just as for a standard monopolist, pricing is determined by the classic Lerner formula.

A Ricardian rent, by contrast, emerges when a firm produces more or higher quality output per unit of input than its competitors. Because a Ricardian rent remunerates a competitive advantage, it can emerge in a competitive market. Observed royalties have nothing to do with market power.

To appreciate this point, Figure 3.5 draws the standard average and marginal cost curves of a competitive licensee. The figure shows an innovation that increases quality and consumers’ willingness to pay by a factor λ > 1 over the alternative, and in equilibrium, products that use the technology command a market premium equal to (λ − 1)pc. Thus, the licensee obtains additional revenues equal to the shaded rectangle. This rectangle is the Ricardian rent wrought by the technology, which the patent holder can appropriate through licensing and charging royalties. But its origin is the market premium (λ − 1)pc, and its total amount is capped by the incremental value created by the technology.

Figure 3.5. Patents and Ricardian rents

As can be seen in Figure 3.5, the royalty is part of the licensee’s average cost. The licensee covers all her costs, and the good’s market price equals its long-run marginal cost. But because a better technology commands a price premium, which is equal to consumers’ differential willingness to pay, well-functioning markets naturally create the rents and rewards that incentivize investments in R&D. This rent may be transferred to the patent holder via per-unit royalties, a lump-sum payment, or a combination of both. Whatever the means whereby the Ricardian rents are transferred, they remunerate those technologies that are more productive and deliver more output or value per unit of input.

It follows that competition policy may have a role if the source of the rents is the exercise of market power – that is, if technology developers are able to raise the running royalty to create scarcity at the margin. By contrast, competition policy does not have much of a role if technology developers earn Ricardian rents, which emerge in competitive markets. The point we make next is that the observed level of the royalties charged by technology developers is informative about the source of the rents.

C. Monopoly Power and Royalty Stacking in the Mobile Phone Industry

As Figure 3.6 shows, a patent holder acting as a monopolist would exploit market power by restraining output, raising the market price of the final good, and extracting the monopoly rent through the royalty. A direct test for the existence of a monopoly therefore uses the Lerner margin, as shown in (3.1) to predict the level of the royalties that patent holders would charge if they acted as a monopoly. We apply this reasoning to the smartphone market.

Figure 3.6. Value and distribution in the smartphone value chain with a single Monopoly Patent Holder (2016)

Figure 3.6 shows the same demand curve as Figure 3.3 but assumes that patent holders act as a single profit-maximizing monopolist. The main result is that patent holders would have earned 66% of all revenues of the value chain, instead of 3.3%. Higher royalties would have multiplied the average selling price of a smartphone by a factor of almost three – from $298 to $844. Consequently, only 722 million units would have been sold, instead of 1.42 billion. Despite the decline in unit sales, however, total revenues would have risen from $425.1 billion to $609.4 billion. More than two-thirds of those revenues (about $400 billion) would have accrued to the patent holders. Those revenues would have been pure rent, as they exceeded the long-run cost of the inputs used to produce the patented technologies.Footnote 12

An influential literature, known as patent holdup and royalty stacking, implies that the situation should have been even worse than outlined in the prior paragraph. The theory claims that because multiple firms own the IP that is essential to make a phone interoperable and compatible, each can exploit its monopoly independently.Footnote 13 That is, the magnitude of the cumulative royalty in the smartphone value chain predicted by the theory of royalty stacking grows with the number of patent holders.Footnote 14 Monopoly will stack upon monopoly, strangling the industry. Formally, if the number of patent holders is n, then the Lerner margin is:

pscps=Rsps=nη>1η(3.2)

In our 2017 paper,Footnote 15 we parameterize a standard royalty stacking model. We observe that in 2016, there were 21 identified patent licensors who received royalty revenue, and that the cumulative royalty yield predicted by the theory of patent holdup and royalty stacking is 79%. That is, if patent holders were each exploiting their monopoly power independently, they would receive four out of every five dollars paid for a smartphone.

A predicted royalty of 67% (a single monopolist) or 79% (21 monopolists) compares with the observed average cumulative royalty yield from the 21 identified patent licensors of 3.4% in 2016.Footnote 16 That is to say, the actual yield is more than 20 times lower than either the yield predicted by the theory of patent holdup and royalty stacking or by the predicted royalty that would be charged by a single profit-maximizing monopolist.

The implication is that patent holders in the smartphone value chain do not exercise any meaningful monopoly power. On the contrary, the remuneration that patent holders receive is a Ricardian rent. Thus, the evidence from 3G and 4G is that there is no evidence that standardization creates market power. Because of this, there is little ground to claim that competition authorities have any meaningful role to play in cellular SEP licensing as traditionally practiced within the smartphone industry.

D. 3G and 4G: A Functioning Licensing Market

As we have seen, in 2016, the average royalty yield for a smartphone was 3.4% of the average selling price of a smartphone. In our 2018 paper,Footnote 17 we estimated royalty yields from 2007 through 2016 and found that they showed remarkable stability. Figure 3.7 shows the average royalty yield since 2007 for 16 licensors, which accounted for 78.2% of all royalty revenues in 2016. Since 2009, we have data for 21 licensors, which accounted for 92.5% of all royalty revenues in 2016. As Figure 3.7 shows, both series are remarkably stable. The average cumulative royalty yield of firms with data since 2007 hovers between 2.1% and 3%; the average cumulative royalty yield of firms with data since 2009 hovers between 3% and 3.5%, falling only marginally during the last three years. Note that, as can be seen in Figure 3.8, the composition of sales between feature and smartphones changed significantly during the period, and the value of sales roughly doubled, and yet the average cumulative royalty yield remained stable.

Figure 3.7. Patent royalties as percentage of the value of mobile (smart and feature) phones shipped (2007–2016)

Figure 3.8. WW mobile subscriptions by cellular generation

Source: Ericsson Mobility Visualizer, Sept. 16, 2023
E. New Estimates of the Cumulative Royalty Yield

Since our research described above, we have continued to monitor the market for cellular SEP licenses, although we have modified our methodology so that we now focus on cellular SEP licensing specifically.Footnote 18 The leading cellular SEP licensors are Qualcomm, Nokia, Huawei, Ericsson, and Interdigital. These constituted 84% of royalties in 2016, the last year covered in our prior studies.Footnote 19

As can be seen in Table 3.4, these five licensors obtained $82 billion in royalty revenues during 2015–2022, on average about $10.2 billion per year. On average, royalties were $9.05 per smartphone. If we make room for other licensors, average royalties per mobile device are about $9.79, in line with the orders of magnitude in our previous research. Basically stated, the data are consistent with our earlier estimates. In conclusion, little seems to have changed since the period covered in our previous research – a profound observation given the passage of so many years and the corresponding changes in markets, technologies, products, and companies.

Table 3.4. Leading cellular SEP licensing businesses (2015–2022)

Cellular SEP licensorTotal royalties identified ($b)Implied effective royalties/cellular mobile device unit
Excluding past unitsIncluding past units
Qualcomm$55,601$5.07$5.05
Nokia$10,806$1.47$1.30
Huawei$3,216$0.69$0.59
Ericsson$8,865$1.28$1.13
Interdigital$3,238$0.54$0.46
Subtotal (5 licensors)$81,726$9.05$8.54
Others (est. 10%)$8,173$0.74$0.74
Total$89,899$9.79$9.29
Sources: IDC, Mobile Phone, Tablet, and Wearables, 2015–2022; Ericsson, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Interdigital, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Nokia, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Qualcomm, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Qualcomm QTL Licensee Search; CNBC, “Huawei to start charging royalties to smartphone makers using its patented 5G tech,” Arjun Kharpal, Mar. 16, 2021, “Huawei announces royalty rates for its patent license programs,” Huawei, July 13, 2023
IV. Lessons for 5G Licensing

We have seen that the R&D investments that yielded the previous technological generations have been remunerated by Ricardian rents, which emerge in competitive markets and reflect that the selected technology creates more value per unit of input than the alternatives. What does this suggest about the licensing equilibrium that will emerge in 5G?

So far, the evolution of 5G suggests that technology developers and implementers have and will continue to collaborate to develop, produce, and deploy 5G products and services. Thus, 5G replicates the conditions that yielded the functioning licensing market for 2G, 3G, and 4G. An additional reason to think that investments in 5G will be remunerated by Ricardian rents is that consumers, enterprises, and implementers can choose among alternatives to perform many of the tasks that 5G will perform. In a competitive market, therefore, 5G will earn a rent, but it will be determined by the differential value that the technology creates over the alternatives.

Indeed, parties in each market are likely to consider the appropriateness of 5G for their specific situations in light of alternatives and substitutes. Different jobs for different customers may be accomplished with different devices, on different networks with different underlying network technologies.Footnote 20 This may depend upon the required data rates, latencies, ranges, power consumption limitations, mobility characteristics, and costs. These factors may determine whether and when a substitute or alternative displaces 5G and when it cannot. In what follows, we briefly review several potential alternative technologies that perform at least some of the tasks that 5G can accomplish, effectively acting as substitutes.

A. 5G Alternatives and Substitutes
1. Competition from Predecessors

5G must contend with its predecessors, 4G/LTE and 2G/ GSM. GSM remains highly useful and popular in specific geographic regions, powering roughly the same number of devices shipped in 2020 as in 2007. What does this mean? We can look at this from the perspective of the “Jobs to be Done”Footnote 21 framework developed by Clayton Christensen and colleagues. In this framework, it is critical to understand the “progress a consumer is trying to make in particular circumstances.” The answer can indicate which products consumers will “hire” for a job. The decisions by consumers here suggest that 2G continues to sufficiently address the job-to-be-done for some customer segments. Interestingly, as Figure 3.8 shows, consumers quickly moved on from 2G’s immediate successors, 2.5G and 3G, to 4G. Time will tell whether such segments move on to 5G, relegating 4G to the historical record, or whether 4G can, like 2G, retain a segment of consumers over the longer term.

Similarly, 4G has successfully addressed smartphone-based jobs such as getting to a meeting, arranging a dinner, or planning a vacation. Some 5G-capable smartphones continue to enable such tasks over 4G networks to save power, moving users to 5G only for select tasks where higher bandwidth justifies higher power consumption. Such tasks might include the much-discussed use case of preparing for a long trip by instantly downloading entire movies, but more likely will involve fundamentally new jobs most of us cannot currently foresee.

2. IoT Applications

From an IoT use case standpoint, 5G provides support through its mMTC capabilities. However, some IoT use cases may continue to employ traditional proprietary wireless technologies such as DJI OccuSync for UAV control, or standardized alternatives such as Wi-Fi, Bluetooth LE, Wireless HART, LoRaWAN, or other options. In each case, markets can consider performance, cost, and suitability for the use case at hand. For example, within the home or enterprise, many IoT devices do not require a mobile network to connect, and so Wi-Fi or Bluetooth may be satisfactory and lower in cost. For some IoT deployments in the field, LoRaWAN may remain appropriate, while in others 5G may provide advantages. At a minimum, 5G’s mMTC capabilities should provide value in massive field deployments.

3. Fixed Wireless Access Applications

5G delivers a legitimate mobile broadband service, which should enable it to deliver a highly competitive FWA service that its predecessors could not deliver in many geographic areas. This may enhance competition in areas with fixed broadband build-outs, such as suburbs, and also provide a first true broadband option in areas presently lacking fixed broadband services. FWA can also serve vehicles such as buses, RVs, and mobile duty trailers. Even here, 5G should face competition, however, for example, from SpaceX’s Starlink service (see Section 5, SpaceX Starlink).

4. Network Combinations and Offload

Users operating from homes, workplaces, and well-equipped “third places” such as airports, libraries, university campuses, and chain restaurants often enjoy Wi-Fi connectivity with fixed broadband backhaul for both better coverage and bandwidth. Historically, the worldwide Wi-Fi mobile data offloadFootnote 22 from 4G was 59%, and forecasts call for 70% offload from 5G. This may be desirable, as it reduces the burden on cellular networks in use cases where cellular network attributes such as mobility do not add value. The Wi-Fi plus FTTx combination may continue to address many jobs to be done for mobile device users.

Note that many jobs may leverage such network combinations. For example, the major Japanese cellular carrier KDDI will use Starlink backhaul for rural base stations. This may enable 5G or other cellular coverage to serve customers in remote locations, but only through combination with Starlink.

Different geographic locations and even regions may present different preferred combinations. For example, outstanding fixed broadband offerings in Pacific Rim metro areas may enable Wi-Fi substitutes and derivatives such as Amazon Sidewalk networks. Rural areas within the United States may lend themselves to combinations involving cellular networks plus SpaceX’s Starlink backhaul. When performing a job requires multiple networks working together, the different networks and technologies involved create value commensurate with their roles in completing the entire job.

B. Future Developments

During the lifespan of 5G, we can expect much improvement in 5G itself, as well as in some of these substitute and alternative technologies. Cisco’s Annual Internet Report observes the following trajectories for some key 5G alternatives and substitutes:Footnote 23 Fixed broadband speeds will more than double by 2023, to 110 mbps (v. 46 mbps in 2018); Wi-Fi speeds from mobile devices will triple by 2023, to 92 mbps (v. 30 mbps in 2018); Wi-Fi hotspots will grow four times, to 628 million public hotspots (v. 169 million in 2018). Cisco forecasts these improvements in the context of rapidly growing quantities of users, connected devices, and changing use cases, including for UHD video and IoT devices.

For nascent technologies, the trajectory is more uncertain and speculative, but perhaps has greater potential upside. We look at three interesting cases to consider.

5. SpaceX Starlink

This is a satellite constellation of 3,185 operating satellites,Footnote 24 with FCC approval obtained for 12,000 and plans filed with ITU regulators for an additional 30,000,Footnote 25 to reach a total of 42,000. It would provide fixed wireless access for 25 countries, and there are pending applications to serve many more. Starlink can serve vehicles such as RVs and mobile duty trailers and promises to soon serve vehicles in motion, including planes, boats, trucks, and cars.Footnote 26

6. Amazon Sidewalk

This is a LoRaWAN network technology embedded into Amazon devices such as Echo (Alexa voice assistants) and Ring (surveillance camera, doorbell, and flood light) devices, as well as Sidewalk network devices. Amazon has distributed, and continues to distribute, millions of these devices, creating a rapidly growing global Sidewalk network. There is no end-user charge for Sidewalk technology or usage. Ultimately, this network could become highly useful, at least in particular geographic areas and, for certain use, cases such as IoT deployments in those areas. Tile and similar tracker tags provide an early use case. Amazon could expand the capabilities of Sidewalk in the future to do more jobs, perhaps including some jobs presently performed by Wi-Fi or cellular networks such as messaging.

7. Helium

Another LoRaWAN network is Helium. While Sidewalk is centralized under Amazon control, Helium is decentralized. As with Sidewalk, any party can deploy one or more network nodes at their convenience and personal cost on their site. For example, a homeowner could deploy in their neighborhood, while a business property owner could deploy across its locations. In both cases, the parties can create a new revenue stream while also serving their own users. Helium coordinates these actors using a crypto-based system where node operators earn HNT crypto tokens, and network users can “burn” such tokens to obtain service. Helium has deployed over 966,000 nodes across over 180 countries and 74,000 cities.Footnote 27

Helium is now deploying a 5G network with plans for over 40,000 small cells (6,300 deployed to date) and has formed a partnership with DISH to supplement Dish’s new network build-out. It could also provide its node operators with improved or additional wireless technologies to deploy in the future under this model.

In general, we should expect these alternatives and substitutes to do various wireless networking jobs in competition with 5G technologies, and for that competition to continue over years to come (Table 3.5).Footnote 28

Table 3.5. Comparison of 5G and substitutes, alternatives, and complementsFootnote a

CategoryTechnologyMax rate (mbps)Latency (ms)Range (km)
Cellular5G mm Wave20,000 (down)Footnote b1 (URLLC)Footnote c<0.5Footnote c
5G Sub 6900 (down)Footnote d<10Footnote e30Footnote e
4G/ LTE (excl. advanced)150 (down)Footnote f<35Footnote f200Footnote g
WiFiWi-Fi 7Footnote h46,000 (down)<5n/a
Wi-Fi 6EFootnote h 9,600 (down)<10n/a
PANBluetooth Classic (v1.0-3.0)Footnote i<3<1000.01
Wireless IoTBluetooth LE (v4.0-5.x)Footnote i<161.0Footnote j
ZigbeeFootnote k0.250n/a0.1
LoRaWAN Footnote k0.006n/a10
Fixed BroadbandStarlink (satellite constellation)Footnote l<50025–50n/a
DOCSIS 4.0 (cable)10,000 (down)Footnote m<1Footnote nn/a
DOCSIS 3.1 (cable)10,000 (down)Footnote o<5 (LLD)Footnote pn/a
50G-PON (fiber)Footnote q50,000 (down)n/an/a
ProprietaryDJI OccuSync 3.0 (Drone)Footnote r15 (down)13015

a These figures provide a basic perspective on these technologies’ capabilities and position to compete to do specific jobs-to-be-done. Some of these figures may be theoretical maximums, while others may be viewed as practical maximums. Many may represent estimates of varying rigor and quality. In either case, a host of assumptions may apply; for example, one might achieve a maximum rate at a minimal range. Future advances in technology, or perhaps in implementation techniques, may improve upon these figures.

b Report ITU-R M.2410-0 (11/2017), Minimum requirements related to technical performance for IMT-2020 radio interface(s), www.itu.int/dms_pub/itu-r/opb/rep/R-REP-M.2410-2017-PDF-E.pdf.

c Ronan McLaughlin, “5G low latency requirements,” Broadband Library, https://broadbandlibrary.com/5g-low-latency-requirements/.

d Jeremy Horwitz, “The definitive guide to 5G low, mid, and high band speeds” (Dec. 10, 2019), https://venturebeat.com/mobile/the-definitive-guide-to-5g-low-mid-and-high-band-speeds/.

e Ronan McLaughlin, “5G low latency requirements,” Broadband Library.

f “How fast are 4G and 5G?,” 4G.co.uk, www.4g.co.uk/how-fast-is-4g/.

g “Ericsson and Telstra extend reach on an LTE network up to 200km,” Ericsson (Feb. 27, 2020), www.ericsson.com/en/press-releases/2/2020/2/ericsson-and-telstra-extend-reach-on-an-lte-network-up-to-200km.

i “Bluetooth low energy basics: classic Bluetooth vs. Bluetooth LE,” How to Electronics (May 20, 2023), https://how2electronics.com/classic-bluetooth-vs-bluetooth-low-energy-comparison/

j Jon Gunnar Sponås, “Things You Should Know About Bluetooth Range,” Nordic Semiconductor (Jan. 25, 2023), https://blog.nordicsemi.com/getconnected/things-you-should-know-about-bluetooth-range.

k “Comparison of Wireless Technologies: LoRaWAN and Zigbee, WiFi, NB-IoT,” DFRobot (Apr. 12, 2023), www.dfrobot.com/blog-1646.html.

l Anthony Spadafora, “Starlink internet coverage, cost, speeds and the latest news,” Tom’s Guide, (June 16, 2023), www.tomsguide.com/news/starlink-internet-coverage-speed-cost-satellites-ipo-and-latest-news.

m “DOCSIS 4.0 Technology,” CableLabs (July 3, 2023), www.cablelabs.com/technologies/docsis-4-0-technology.

n Vivian Susko, “DOCSIS 4.0, Explained,” Minim (Apr. 21, 2021), www.minim.com/blog/docsis-4.0-explained.

o “DOCSIS 4.0 Technology,” CableLabs (July 3, 2023).

p Vivian Susko, “DOCSIS 4.0, Explained,” Minim (Apr. 21, 2021).

q Jeff Heynen, “50G PON moves closer to deployment,” Dell’Oro (Apr. 19, 2023), www.delloro.com/50g-pon-moves-closer-to-deployment/.

r “Consumer Drones Comparison” (July 5, 2023), DJI.com, www.dji.com/products/comparison-consumer-drones.

V. Conclusion

We started this chapter by asking what role competition policy should play in emerging 5G markets. Our analysis suggests that the R&D investments that brought about previous technological generations have been remunerated by Ricardian rents, which emerge in competitive markets and reflect that the selected technology creates more value per unit of input than the alternatives. Moreover, the evidence shows that royalty yields are an order of magnitude smaller in prior wireless generations (through 4G) than those that would obtain if technology developers enjoyed market power. In short, there is evidence that royalty rates are determined in a competitive market, and there is no evidence that technology holders operate as monopolists.

So, royalty rates have been determined in a competitive market, and as we have observed, the market for mobile device cellular SEPs appears to be in a long-term equilibrium. What might enable such an equilibrium? Cellular SEP licensing typically relies upon long-term agreements, often on the order of five years but occasionally as long as 10 years and often involving one or more parties with long-term involvement in the industry. These agreements also tend to span periods of time during which cellular technologies arrive and depart, and during which their relative utility changes. These license agreements often cover several or even all such technologies simultaneously (for example, 5/4/3/2G and even “future generation” rights), in the form of license grants and/or in complex combinations with other rights such as covenants. Some license agreements provide this coverage for a fixed amount of royalties paid out in a structured fashion within the term of the agreement.

Because of this, cellular SEP royalties appear “sticky” in the aggregate, and do not change quickly as might prices for commodities traded in spot markets. Many implementers may have entered the 5G market while operating under agreements established years before. Of those who entered the market with 5G licenses, some may have done so through serendipity when prior licenses happened to expire in a timely fashion to parallel their product roadmap transition to 5G. Note that individual parties may conduct their licensing activities differently on one or more of the deal parameters described earlier.

There are indications that Ricardian rents drive 5G as well. 5G has been developed in decentralized fashion with collaboration among specialists and others, as has been the norm. 5G confronts competition for the jobs-to-be-done from alternative technologies, including from 4G/LTE and 2G/GSM. This suggests that the equilibrium will continue, with royalties converging to market values and apportionment among licensors according to the incremental value generated by their respective intellectual property assets.

For these reasons, competition authorities should remain vigilant as always in observing the market but should not presume that monopolistic market power or other problems will distort the market for 5G cellular SEPs. Instead, competition authorities should be watchful over the equilibrium that has determined cellular SEP royalties for many years lest market participants employ tactics that undermine it and produce tragic consequences for its corresponding product and service markets.

4 The Fair Division of Surplus from a FRAND License Negotiated in Good Faith

J. Gregory Sidak
I. Negotiating FRAND Licenses in Good Faith

Government agencies in Japan, China, the European Union, the United States, and other countries have issued guidelines to facilitate private negotiation to license the use of SEPs that a patent holder has voluntarily committed to a standard-setting organization (SSO) to offer to license on FRAND terms to a third party seeking to implement the standard.Footnote 1 In 2022, government agencies renewed their efforts to issue or reissue such guidelines.Footnote 2 Although those guidelines differ in several respects, a common theme that emerges is the proposal that each counterparty negotiate a FRAND license in good faith.

Judicial opinions in SEP cases also refer to the duty to negotiate a FRAND license in good faith, but judges so far have failed to explain that duty’s precise origin or its metes and bounds. For example, in two European decisions, Sisvel v. Haier and Unwired Planet International Ltd. v. Huawei Technologies Co., the German Federal Court of Justice and the High Court of England and Wales, respectively, have emphasized that patent implementers must be willing participants in a FRAND negotiation.Footnote 3 In the United States in TCL v. Ericsson, Judge James Selna of the US District Court for the Central District of California quoted the relevant part of the FRAND commitment established by the European Telecommunications Standards Institute (ETSI), but he never determined the precise obligations that this contract imposed on the SEP holder, much less any obligation that ETSI imposed on the implementer as an implicit condition of its being empowered to enforce that FRAND contract as that contract’s intended third-party beneficiary.Footnote 4

The agencies issuing guidelines have conspicuously neglected to define good faith negotiation, let alone determine the steps that each party must take (and how quickly each must act) before a court may declare the negotiation to be at an impasse, such that contract formation has failed and the SEP holder may enforce its remedies against the unlicensed implementer as provided in the national law of the jurisdiction that issued the patents in suit. The Antitrust Division of the US Department of Justice (DOJ) has pontificated about the problem of implementers refusing to act in good faith, but it has not proposed any meaningful solution.Footnote 5 In a September 2020 supplement to a 2015 business review letter, the Antitrust Division merely requested that “any SDO policy updates should encourage good-faith bilateral licensing negotiation by both patent holders and implementers.”Footnote 6 That supplement was shelved in April 2021, early in the Biden administration, approximately seven months after it had been issued by the Trump administration.Footnote 7

In this section, I seek to make two points regarding a duty to negotiate in good faith. My first point is that mechanism design – a field of study within economics and game theory – can add rigor to the policy prescriptions and nebulous statements of government agencies about good faith negotiation. For the SEP holders and implementers that have experienced protracted litigation over the licensing of SEPs for smartphones, it is possible to draw lessons from what economists managed to fashion from whole cloth two decades ago to create the functioning market for the public auctioning and subsequent transferability of licenses to 3G spectrum. Without the groundwork laid by those economists, the smartphone today, if it existed at all, would be little more than an expensive pocket camera or portable media player searching for a Wi-Fi signal.Footnote 8

My second point is that courts and policymakers possibly have failed to recognize the inadequate design of the current mechanism for FRAND licensing negotiations because that foundational economic question has become intertwined with, if not obscured by, the question of which jurisdiction’s law controls a court’s interpretation of the FRAND contract. Simply put, as I explained in my 2018 article “The FRAND Contract,” the existing body of American contract law concerning offer, acceptance, and contract formation is concise and relatively unambiguous, and thus it provides a turnkey legal framework for resolving FRAND licensing disputes.Footnote 9 In a word, the American jurisprudence on contract formation is efficient. No further guidelines are necessary to apply that jurisprudence productively to interpreting the rights and duties surrounding negotiations for the licensing of SEPs. The wheel needs no reinventing.

A. The Phenomenon of Differential Ambiguity in Matters of Contract Formation and Good Faith Negotiation

Building on the English common law tradition, but insulated from Europe by an ocean, American contract law appears to have evolved in its own distinctly didactic manner, which I attribute to the long shadow cast by Oliver Wendell HolmesFootnote 10 and his intellectual heir in American jurisprudence, Richard Posner.Footnote 11 With respect to the principles of contract formation, that American demand for crisp answers implicitly conduces to what economists call activity rules and closing rules, which simplify the task of definitively confirming whether a meeting of the minds has or has not occurred (much in the spirit, as I shall explain in the following pages, of economists realizing that national governments needed to define unambiguous activity rules and closing rules if they were to succeed in creating a workable market mechanism to auction licenses for 3G spectrum). By default, American law provides a clear closing rule for determining when contract formation has failed. The SEP holder makes an offer that is legitimately FRAND. Either the offer is accepted, or it is rejected explicitly or by counteroffer or by the passage of a commercially reasonable period of time. The licensee is not permitted to initiate rounds of offer and counteroffer. Following the licensee’s failure to accept a legitimately FRAND offer, negotiations of course may continue between the parties, but no longer under the FRAND framework. Instead, those negotiations revert to the framework of public patent law.

In contrast to this American veneration of transactional efficiency (and a concomitant abhorrence of ambiguity or euphemism), the bodies of contract law of other jurisdictions (in Europe and the rest of the world) evidently do not offer, and do not aspire to offer, such black-and-white rules on whether and when a contract has been formed.Footnote 12 For example, when and for whom does the duty of good faith negotiation commence, and how long does it remain in effect once an offer has been made? Some scholars of French law impute to the duty to negotiate in good faith an explicitly noneconomic origin.Footnote 13 As one treatise on French law has observed, incompatible interpretations among scholars of the purpose and effect of the doctrine of good faith indicate that “the notion of good faith and its use by the courts is likely to remain contested.”Footnote 14 If SEP holders, implementers, and their attorneys fail to recognize that the monochrome character of American contract law differs from the Technicolor character of contract law in many other nations, they will expose themselves to an unmarked hazard in SEP licensing negotiations and SEP litigation whenever American contract principles do not control.

That hazard exists in very practical business terms because ETSI plays such a dominant role in the setting of wireless standards, and its FRAND commitment is, of course, controlled by French contract law.Footnote 15 In contrast, New York law controls the RAND contract of another prominent SSO, the Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (IEEE).Footnote 16 It is quite possible that the differences between French contract law and New York contract law – to take only one example – will produce substantively different conclusions about the legal duties owed under the FRAND or RAND contract in question. Indeed, the scope of a SEP holder’s obligations and the scope of the rights granted to third-party beneficiaries by virtue of a FRAND or RAND contract depend on both that contract’s actual language and the controlling law governing the interpretation (if needed) of that contract. The key point is that, whenever American contract law does not apply, to know when the negotiation has failed to achieve contract formation, we need a closing rule.

This perspective on contract formation causes me to disfavor and avoid using the terminology of “holdup” and “holdout” to describe the presence or absence of good faith during the negotiation to license SEPs pursuant to the FRAND contract. I find it simpler and more germane to ask whether, and when, the offeror and the offeree have discharged whatever duties they bear under the FRAND contract between the SEP holder and the SSO. What is called “holdout” is a manifestation of the failure of the controlling law to declare in a timely manner that the contract negotiations have become futile, such that the SEP holder has discharged its contractual duty to the SSO (and to the implementer as the third-party beneficiary of the SEP holder’s FRAND contract with the SSO). Calling the problem “holdout” supplies an epithet, but it does nothing to help answer the legal or economic question; to the contrary, that nomenclature is arguably counterproductive in the sense that it falsely suggests that the SEP holder must make some further evidentiary showing that “holdout” has occurred before it may pursue its legal remedies under the national law of the country that issued the patents in suit.

To begin the task of reducing legal and economic ambiguity concerning the determination of whether a SEP holder and an implementer have conducted a FRAND licensing negotiation in good faith, I propose here the formulation of a specific activity rule and a specific closing rule when American contract jurisprudence does not control interpretation of the FRAND contract in question. My proposed activity rule is that, in each round of offer and counteroffer – and to the extent that the SEP holder has not already discharged its contractual obligation to ETSI (such as by its already having made a legitimately FRAND offer at the very outset of the negotiation) – a party must revise its bid or ask price by the minimum agreed-upon increment for that party to be deemed still to be negotiating in good faith. My proposed closing rule is that a party will be deemed to have made its final offer or counteroffer if it does not, within a commercially reasonable amount of time after receiving an offer or counteroffer, sweeten its price relative to its price in the previous round of offer and counteroffer. These rules of market design are proposals, which will surely benefit from scrutiny and refinement by others, but these proposals should suffice to invite a needed discussion.

Considering how controversial and how consequential these issues have been in the licensing of SEPs for smartphones, I see no reason why they will prove to be simpler to resolve in the licensing of SEPs for connected cars, smart homes, and the multitude of other 5G devices that will constitute the Internet of Things.

Parties in litigation over SEPs in the United States and England routinely solicit the expert opinions of scholars on French contract law to assist the court’s interpretation of a SEP holder’s FRAND contract with ETSI. Yet, as I have remarked elsewhere, the public trial testimony, expert reports, and judicial decisions describing those expert opinions on French law cast doubt on the determinacy of French contract law.Footnote 17 An American observer might conclude that French contract law on its own is incapable of defining good faith, or at least that it is ill equipped to supply a definition. Principles defining good faith in the evidentiary records of these cases are simply not percolating through into the public domain to shed light on how parties should behave or how judges should judge. Economic insights from the field of mechanism design can cure that indeterminacy.

1. How Have EU Courts Interpreted the FRAND and RAND Obligations?

Notwithstanding the variation in due care as to the source of and content of a given FRAND or RAND obligation, what is clear is that US courts almost uniformly have been reluctant to conclude that the breach of a FRAND or RAND obligation amounts to a violation of antitrust law.

Contrast the experience in the United States with the experience in the European Union. Having become a favored jurisdiction for SEP enforcement, Germany has established itself as the lodestar in the European Union for the development of jurisprudence on the meaning of FRAND. Courts in Germany conclude that FRAND and RAND are synonymous, and that FRAND is simply a holistic concept ultimately rooted in EU competition law (as opposed to the particular contract between a particular holder of SEPs and a particular SSO acting on behalf of implementers, who are the intended third‑party beneficiaries of that contract). When an implementer in patent litigation in Germany presents its statement of defense, it typically frames its arguments concerning violation of the FRAND obligation as emanating from Article 102 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union (TFEU).Footnote 18 The differing interpretations of particular FRAND or RAND obligations under contract law collapse to a uniform interpretation of FRAND as defined by the Court of Justice of the European Union or national courts (or some combination thereof). This source of law or authority for purposes of interpreting the duties of a particular SEP holder pursuant to a specific FRAND or RAND contract is unsatisfying to an American lawyer or jurist, who might be tempted to ask: What treaty or statute or regulation or court decision made these variegated FRAND and RAND obligations synonymous with the jurisprudence of Article 102?

The approach in the European Union is quite different from saying, as one does in the United States, that the FRAND obligation is a contract that is unique to the SEP holder and the SSO; that that contract is not a uniform statute or even a standard-form contract; and that interpretation of that contract is influenced by choice of law. The stark fork in the road between the understanding of the FRAND obligation in Anglo-American law versus EU law has important practical consequences for licensing and for dispute resolution. Rarely (if ever) do courts in the European Union make a finding of economic fact that a particular offer is (or is not) FRAND because it does (or does not) repose within the bargaining range between a SEP holder and a particular implementer. To avoid making such detailed findings of economic fact, courts in the European Union tend instead to analyze whether the antiphonal negotiating conduct of the licensor and the potential licensee exhibits the good faith that Huawei v. ZTE requires.Footnote 19

In the United States, advocates cannot properly treat every FRAND or RAND obligation as uniform and fail to specify the precise legal and economic questions that the court must answer. Expert economic testimony on whether a patent holder has discharged its FRAND or RAND obligation is relevant in a strict evidentiary sense only if the expert’s instructions are sensitive to the language contained in a given SSO’s bylaws. In contrast, in Germany, the “fair” and “reasonable” components of the FRAND obligation merge and require analysis of whether the SEP holder’s offer falls within the bargaining range – or whether the SEP holder’s conduct is “fair” and “reasonable” within the meaning of Huawei v. ZTE. With respect to the “nondiscrimination” component of the FRAND obligation, it seems likely that EU courts will uniformly engraft the meaning that “discrimination” has been given within the jurisprudence applying Article 102(c) of the TFEU onto every FRAND or RAND contract. That is, courts in the European Union will likely find that a SEP holder’s offer to license is discriminatory only if the offer (1) treats similarly situated parties in an unjustifiably dissimilar manner, and (2) the dissimilar treatment proximately causes a distortion of competition in a relevant market.

In FRAND litigation and arbitration, an attorney instructing an expert economic witness should tailor his instructions to ensure that the economic evidence is relevant to the mode of interpretation of FRAND that the particular court will apply. Doing so will avoid the presentation of expert testimony that is ultimately unhelpful to the finder of economic fact. Law firms must take care to give rudimentary instructions on the applicable legal principles within which the expert economic witness must frame an economic opinion if that opinion is to be relevant in an evidentiary sense to the question that the finder of fact must decide – as well as being not prejudicial, confusing, or misleading. Once opposing counsel has shown that a party has incorrectly instructed its economic expert on the controlling law (or has failed to correct the expert’s own misconception of the controlling law), that expert economic witness cannot blithely ignore, or feign ignorance of, the controlling meaning of FRAND in a particular court.

Courts less accustomed to expert economic testimony (and which do not allow live cross-examination at trial, as is the case in Germany) need to scrutinize such testimony with greater skepticism and rigor than currently appears to be the norm. Does the expert economic witness tacitly hold the condescending view that legal distinctions are insignificant details that do not rise to being relevant considerations that properly inform an intellectually rigorous economic analysis, even when that analysis has been undertaken specifically for the purpose of assisting the court’s resolution of a consequential legal dispute? Regardless of whether the expert economic witness can genuinely profess ignorance, plainly the eminent law firm responsible for retaining and instructing the expert cannot profess such ignorance in good faith.

2. Is There a Duty to Negotiate in Good Faith?

No American court deciding a dispute over SEPs has publicly explained the origin in French law of the duty to negotiate in good faith. In particular, no American court has explained why the implementer – as the third-party beneficiary to the SEP holder’s FRAND contract with ETSI, not a party to that contract – has a duty to negotiate in good faith.Footnote 20 Indeed, judges and commentators take as given that the duty to negotiate in good faith applies symmetrically to the third-party beneficiary before contract formation between the SEP holder and the third-party beneficiary of the SEP holder’s FRAND contract with ETSI.Footnote 21 Every judicial opinion is a public good that can shed light on the law.Footnote 22 If the proposition is uncontroversial that a duty of good faith and fair dealing applies to the negotiation between a SEP holder and an implementer of an ETSI standard, then it would be helpful for judges to explain for the benefit of those less perspicacious than they why and whence that duty arises.Footnote 23

Reading ETSI’s FRAND contract alongside the Civil Code of France, which specifies in Article 1104 that “[c]ontracts must be negotiated, formed and performed in good faith,”Footnote 24 supports at least the following conclusions concerning the duty to negotiate in good faith. For at least four reasons, these conclusions are not to the exclusion of other conclusions that might follow from French law or the law of other nations.

First, to the extent that the FRAND contract between the SEP holder and ETSI is enforceable under French law, the SEP holder must perform the obligations that arise from that FRAND contract in good faith. That is, the SEP holder has an obligation to ETSI to act in good faith in its preparedness to grant a license to an implementer that qualifies as an intended third-party beneficiary. The same conclusion would likely apply under American contract law, because the SEP holder that is offering to license its SEPs to an implementer is performing its contractual obligations under the FRAND contract; and American contract law, which of course is state law and therefore might vary across the United States, generally provides that parties must perform their contractual duties in good faith.Footnote 25

Second, to the extent that the implementer is itself a SEP holder that has entered into a FRAND contract with ETSI, the implementer also has a duty under French contract law to negotiate in good faith. Such a duty would typically arise when counterparties negotiate a cross-license, wherein the implementer offers to license to the SEP holder the implementer’s own SEPs that are subject to a FRAND commitment to ETSI. For example, in HTC v. Ericsson, Chief Judge Rodney Gilstrap of the Eastern District of Texas found that HTC, the implementer, had a duty to negotiate a cross-license in good faith because it was also a SEP holder that had entered into its own FRAND contract with ETSI.Footnote 26 Again, American contract law would support a similar conclusion. An implementer that itself had executed a FRAND contract (because it is also a SEP holder) has a contractual duty to perform in good faith the obligations that it accepted pursuant to that FRAND contract.Footnote 27

Third, to the extent that the negotiation over SEPs between the SEP holder and the implementer culminates in the execution of a license agreement that is subject to the Civil Code of France (or to some equivalent law of a different nation that imposes a duty comparable to Article 1104 of the Civil Code of France), both the SEP holder and the implementer are obligated to negotiate their contract in good faith, because the Code explicitly directs parties to act in good faith when negotiating a contract.

Fourth, to the extent that the FRAND contract between the SEP holder and ETSI is properly characterized as un accord de principe (an agreement in principle), as a matter of French law, the accord de principe might impose the duty on both the SEP holder and the implementer to negotiate in good faith.Footnote 28

However, if the SEP holder and an implementer are not negotiating in the shadow of the Civil Code of France, and if that implementer has not entered into its own binding FRAND contract with ETSI, it is far from apparent what source of law or what equitable principle would force the implementer to negotiate in good faith. In particular, I am aware of no state in the United States whose contract law imposes a general duty to negotiate in good faith, as does Article 1104 of the Civil Code of France. As Judge Posner explained in 1991, the general contractual duty to negotiate before contract formation in good faith in the United States is so vanishingly small as to be virtually nonexistent.Footnote 29 In other words, under American contract law principles, an implementer has no duty to negotiate in good faith a license agreement for FRAND-committed SEPs. If the FRAND agreement does not create a contractual duty to negotiate a license in good faith, then it appears American contract law will not itself create such a duty.Footnote 30

Despite not having a legal obligation to negotiate in good faith under American contract law principles, an implementer that fails to negotiate in good faith might nevertheless face legal consequences for such conduct. For example, a US court might order the implementer to pay enhanced damages for willful infringement of SEPs.Footnote 31 Similarly, an implementer that fails to negotiate in good faith might forfeit its right, as an intended third-party beneficiary of a FRAND contract, to receive a FRAND offer. As a separate matter, whether or not the implementer has a preexisting duty to negotiate in good faith with the SEP holder,Footnote 32 the implementer could also incur liability in tort law for fraud or deceit.

3. Why Does It Matter Whether a Duty Exists to Negotiate in Good Faith?

My purpose in this chapter is not to attempt to answer the preceding questions concerning choice-of-law principles and the source of the possible duty, borne by a third-party beneficiary of the SEP holder’s FRAND contract with ETSI, to negotiate a license to the committed SEPs in good faith. Instead, I simply and briefly expose the ambiguity of French law concerning the certainty of whether and when contract formation has occurred in FRAND cases, as well as the substantive implications of that ambiguity.Footnote 33 And I now submit that the solution to overcoming that ambiguity lies in reframing the problem as one of efficient market design.

That such questions would arise in SEP disputes tells us that a rift exists between American contract law and French contract law on matters of contract formation, and that the existence of that divide, much less the depth of its economic significance, again, has eluded courts and scholars. American law, it would seem, differs from the law of much of the rest of the world, evidently even common law jurisdictions, with respect to the negotiation and formation of a contract. American law presents a regimented view of when offer, acceptance, and contract formation each occurs. A more European approach evidently envisions an elongated process permitting multiple rounds of offer and counteroffer. Yet that European process lacks any explicit rule for determining whether a given offer or counteroffer is sufficiently sweetened, relative to the prior offer or counteroffer, to contribute materially to closing the bid–ask spread separating the parties. And that European process also lacks any explicit rule declaring when the negotiation must end because the parties have reached an impasse and therefore deserve to have it recognized as a matter of law that they have failed in their efforts to form a contract.

The quiddity of this characteristic, which materially differs in degree between American contract law and European contract law, I will call expedition. It neatly illustrates how Americans and citizens of other advanced nations sometimes understand quite differently a concept so foundational to legal or economic reasoning that it is commonly presumed to admit no dispute. Expedition is the impatient foot tapping of the marketplace. The enemy of indecision, dithering, sloth, torpor, and indolence, expedition despises dilatory guile and circumlocution. In the arena of commerce and all its works and days of hands, expedition is how one acts upon Seneca’s admonition: “It is not that we have a short time to live, but that we waste a lot of it.”Footnote 34

Being expeditious in the licensing of SEPs increases economic welfare in both the short run and the long run. In the short run, expedition reduces ambiguity, facilitates contract formation, and reduces the need to resort to litigation (as well as the opportunity to use litigation for strategic reasons). In the long run, in the context of licensing SEPs, expedition hastens the creation of consumer surplus and producer surplus from the commercialization of products practicing a new voluntary standard.

The presence or absence of efficient activity rules and closing rules could spell the difference between an SSO’s success or its failure and withering away. There has been an evident poverty of foresight in regard to designing the end of the process of licensing SEPs. In the absence of some other scapegoat coming forward, I will blame that deficiency of market design on the engineers for having failed to recognize the economic and legal significance of setting in place the mechanism necessary to ensure the expeditious completion of negotiations between a SEP holder and third-party beneficiaries of the SEP holder’s FRAND contract. Although we can infer that the vast majority of bilateral negotiations for the licensing of SEPs produce successful commercial agreements, those that do not have cost billions of dollars in litigation over the past decade.

B. Activity Rules, Closing Rules, and “Best Practices” in Negotiations over FRAND-Committed SEPs

I have previously argued that time is of the essence in the implementation of a standard – in particular because to waste time in the introduction of an entirely new generation of products featuring standard-dependent technological innovations is to harm the public interest by sacrificing consumer surplus irreparably.Footnote 35 To the extent that one can properly impute a duty (or covenant) to negotiate in good faith to an intended third-party beneficiary of ETSI’s FRAND contract with a particular SEP holder, that duty reflects the understanding that a public interest inheres in the expeditious negotiation of SEP licenses. Whether the implementer’s behavior after receiving a legitimately FRAND offer adheres to the standard of good faith will depend ultimately on how quickly the implementer seeks to close the bid–ask spread and converge on an agreement – which is to say, contract formation.Footnote 36 Following that interpretation to its logical conclusion, the point at which the implementer ceases to sweeten its counteroffer from one round of the negotiation to the next defines the point of impasse.

Implicit in this rule is the understanding that the parties also must define how long a given round lasts during their negotiation. How long may a party take to sweeten its bid or ask? If the parties provide no answer of their own to this question, the default answer becomes “a commercially reasonable amount of time.” But, rather than have a court rule what amount of time is commercially reasonable, the parties can create considerable value by agreeing on a framework that is both more precise and more expeditious than what is merely commercially reasonable.

The obvious analogy here is to the activity charge required of a bidder to maintain its right to keep bidding in the simultaneous multi-round ascending auction for 3G spectrum licenses in the United Kingdom. Economist Paul Klemperer of Oxford, who advised the UK government, explains:

Our design entailed multiple rounds of simultaneous bids. In the first round, each bidder makes a bid on one license of its own choice. To remain in the auction, a bidder must be “active” in every subsequent round. An active bidder either currently holds the top bid on a particular license, or else raises the bid on a license of the bidder’s choice by at least the minimum bid increment. A bidder who is inactive in any round is eliminated from the rest of the auction.Footnote 37

As I observed at the opening of this part, governmental agencies around the world have promoted “best practices” in negotiations over FRAND‑committed SEPs. The most useful thing left undone in such statements of best practices is to endorse the concept of an activity charge for good faith FRAND negotiations, and then to identify an unambiguous economic methodology for determining the minimum bid increment by which an implementer must sweeten its counteroffer to the SEP holder’s legitimately FRAND offer for the implementer to be deemed still to be negotiating in good faith.

The next most useful thing left undone in statements of best practices for good faith FRAND negotiation is to identify an unambiguous economic methodology for determining when the negotiation has ended in failure. Again, it bears emphasis that this question is legally relevant only for FRAND obligations not controlled by American-style contract principles of offer and acceptance – which, I have explained earlier, inherently have the admirable (but evidently underappreciated) quality of unambiguously defining a closing rule for a bilateral negotiation.Footnote 38 Evan Kwerel, a highly respected economist who spent a career at the Federal Communications Commission and made important contributions to the design and execution of American spectrum auctions there, explained that “[t]he closing rule was one of the major [market] design issues for a simultaneous auction” for spectrum in the United States.Footnote 39 Stanford professors Robert Milgrom and Robert Wilson, who shared the Nobel Prize in economics in 2020 for their work on auction theory, “proposed a simultaneous closing rule whereby the auction closes on all licenses only after a round has passed with no bidding on any license.”Footnote 40 In contrast, conspicuously absent from the current conception of the FRAND negotiation is any guidance on when it reaches its end in terms of rounds of offer and counteroffer. Instead, the negotiation is like a baseball game with an infinite number of innings, or a poker game in which a player may remain in the hand without calling his opponent’s bet.

Because of the failure of SSOs or courts or other institutions in positions of authority to impose both an activity rule and a closing rule, a contentious negotiation for a FRAND license, if not controlled by the law of a jurisdiction having American-style principles concerning contract formation, will regrettably resemble Zeno’s Dichotomy paradox. The journey’s end becomes ever closer in incrementally smaller half steps, but it is never reached.

II. What Makes FRAND Fair?

SSOs generally permit each SEP holder to set a FRAND or RAND royalty for its SEPs through private bilateral negotiations with each implementer, rather than require the SEP holder to post tariffed rates for all customers. Such voluntary exchange benefits both parties, who divide their aggregate gains from trade, which economists call surplus.Footnote 41 This economic principle – that voluntary exchange is mutually beneficial – is as profound as it is simple, and for that reason, economists call it “The Fundamental Theorem of Exchange.”Footnote 42

In any negotiation, the total surplus from a successful transaction is equivalent to the bargaining range – the distance between the buyer’s maximum willingness to pay and the seller’s minimum willingness to accept. Put differently, the gains from trade (that is, the gains from voluntary exchange) consist of the sum of consumer surplus and producer surplus.Footnote 43 As Jack Hirshleifer, Amihai Glazer, and David Hirshleifer emphasize in their pellucid undergraduate textbook on price theory, this terminology about consumption and production should not detract from the essential characteristic of voluntary exchange: “The names of these measures are somewhat misleading. The benefits stem from trading, not from consuming or producing. Instead of Consumer Surplus and Producer Surplus one should, properly speaking, refer to Buyer Surplus and Seller Surplus.”Footnote 44 Elsewhere within economics, auction theory uses still other terminology – the reserve price or reservation price – to identify the same concepts, respectively, of the seller’s minimum willingness to accept and the buyer’s maximum willingness to pay.Footnote 45

One question regarding the bilateral negotiation of SEPs on FRAND terms has received surprisingly little attention in either court decisions or scholarly writings: What is a fair division of the surplus generated by a voluntary negotiation successfully concluded between the SEP holder and the implementer?Footnote 46

A. Defining the Fair Division of Surplus

John Rawls famously argued that “fair” means “just.”Footnote 47 “Justice as fairness,” he asserted, “is an example of … a contract theory.”Footnote 48 Rawls argued that “[t]he word ‘contract’ suggests,” among other things, “the condition that the appropriate division of advantages must be in accordance with principles acceptable to all parties.”Footnote 49 One would expect the same of the FRAND contract. How can we go about imputing to the fairness component of the FRAND contract – a meaning that is intellectually rigorous in both legal and economic respects?

This question of the meaning of a fair price turns out to have very real legal ramifications in the present day. Rarely do I disagree with Judge Posner, but I do with respect to his view that “fair” is surplusage in the FRAND contract. Judge Posner, sitting by designation as the trial judge in Apple, Inc. v. Motorola, Inc. in 2012 in the Northern District of Illinois said that, in the context of FRAND, “the word ‘fair’ adds nothing to ‘reasonable’ and ‘nondiscriminatory.’”Footnote 50 My previous writings have followed this convention of making no legal or economic distinction between FRAND and RAND royalties, though I have never excluded the possibility that someone might eventually make a compelling argument for why “fair” is not a throwaway word for parties to insert into a contract.Footnote 51 And so, for example, I have previously analyzed at length the differences between actual FRAND contracts and actual RAND contracts with respect to how fairness creeps into the constraint to license SEPs on nondiscriminatory terms.Footnote 52 This part of this chapter will show why courts should take the distinction between FRAND contracts and RAND contracts more seriously.

More than 30 years ago, Robert Frank of Cornell University proposed a precise economic definition that is directly relevant to the question of what makes a FRAND royalty fair:

Using the notions of reservation price and surplus, we can construct the following operational definition of a fair transaction: A fair transaction is one in which the surplus is divided (approximately) equally. The transaction becomes increasingly unfair as the division increasingly deviates from equality.Footnote 53

Frank then explained the problem that unfairness presents: “People will sometimes reject transactions in which the other party gets the lion’s share of the surplus, even though the price at which the product sells may compare favorably with their own reservation price.”Footnote 54

This reasoning is very close to the conclusion I had reached before benefiting, late in the process of revising an earlier incarnation of this text over the course of several years, from reading Frank’s 1988 book. Frank and I each find ourselves using Judge Posner as our foil, though for different reasons. Frank criticized Judge Posner’s writings through the mid-1980s, as denying what Frank argued was the considerable explanatory power of fairness considerations in law and economics.Footnote 55 In contrast, I gently chide Judge Posner for overlooking roughly 25 years later that, by the private ordering of contract law, some SSOs had chosen to impose an obligation of fairness so that (according to my economic interpretation) those SSOs could nudge parties into exercising the degree of moderation in their negotiation demands that is necessary to achieve contract formation reliably and expeditiously.

The irony is that my interpretation of why the word “fair” must have an independent meaning within the FRAND contract is quintessentially Posnerian: A division of surplus that is perceived by both parties to be fair maximizes the probability of contract formation over some defined time horizon, which in turn immediately benefits the parties to the contract. Thus, fairness clearly promotes static allocative efficiency. Moreover, across time the fairness constraint on the division of surplus also benefits countless consumers, whom the grand edifice of the FRAND contract is surely intended to benefit (though not necessarily by the formal machinery of conferring on those consumers legally enforceable rights of a third-party beneficiary, as the FRAND contract does confer on implementers). As Joseph Schumpeter taught us, it is the consumption of innovative products in the future that delivers radical – not marginal – gains in consumer surplus.Footnote 56 Thus, the fairness constraint promotes dynamic efficiency as well.

In this respect, Posner’s emphasis on efficiency and Frank’s emphasis on fairness are reconcilable. A lopsided division of surplus is a cost imposed on efficient transactions to the extent that it prevents some otherwise promising negotiations from achieving successful contract formation; if that cost can be eliminated or mitigated, a larger number of efficient transactions will occur. Therefore, regardless of whether one prefers to call it a quest for fairness or a quest for efficiency, an SSO’s constraint on the SEP holder that a royalty for its SEPs be fair is a privately ordered feature of contract – a self-imposed cattle prod – that contributes to a result that proponents of fairness and proponents of efficiency can both applaud.

B. Fairness and Contract Formation

One can formalize a simple theory of fairness and contract formation. Imagine a decision tree depicting the expected surplus of a contract negotiation as the sum of the expected values of two mutually alternative outcomes: EV = pS + (1 – p)0, where p is the probability of contract formation and S is the surplus created by a successful transaction. The size of the surplus S is separately identified by the bargaining range, which is bounded by the reservation prices of the parties to the negotiation. But the expected value of the surplus is necessarily smaller than S because the division of the surplus might cause one of the parties to walk away. A simple and intuitive formulation of the relationship comes from defining as R the ratio of the seller’s share of the surplus (X) to the buyer’s share of the surplus (Y): R = X / Y = X / (1 – X). R is bounded below by zero and above by infinity. As R approaches zero, p approaches zero. As R approaches infinity, p again approaches zero. In either case, it becomes more likely that contract formation will fail, and consequently the parties will forfeit the surplus from the transaction.

At this point, it is instructive to consider the Ultimatum Game, a bargaining game in which a player makes a single take-it-or-leave-it offer, rather than multiple offers and counteroffers.Footnote 57 The game ends in either an agreement to the unaltered terms of the first offer or no agreement at all. If the second party rejects the offer, neither party benefits – the first party does not keep any portion of the asset but rather forfeits it all. Thus, both parties have an incentive to agree, and the division of surplus (which in this particular game is assumed to be a windfall, not a return on either party’s investment) will depend on a fair offer having been made. As I previously explained in 2013, the Ultimatum Game is interesting in analyzing the FRAND contract not because a FRAND negotiation represents an Ultimatum Game.Footnote 58 After all, in FRAND licensing, there are typically repeated rounds of offer and counteroffer, the identities of the parties are known (perhaps because the parties have previously negotiated a licensing contract), and the reputation of the players matters because they will face the prospect of repeated play in subsequent licensing over future standards. Instead, the Ultimatum Game is interesting for FRAND licensing because the results of economic experiments based on the Ultimatum Game shed light on which divisions of surplus the parties to a stylized negotiation would consider fair. Surveying the experimental economics literature as it existed in 2000, Ernst Fehr and Simon Gächter reported that “[a] robust result in [the Ultimatum Game] experiment, across hundreds of trials, is that Proposers who offer the Responder less than thirty percent of the available sum are rejected with a very high probability.”Footnote 59

If there are any positive spillovers for society as a whole from successful contract formation, as there of course would be if the contract is one for the licensing of patents essential to practice an industry standard, then those externalities are forfeited as well when the negotiation collapses. In contrast to the scenarios of negotiation impasse that I previously described, as R goes to one, p approaches one, and thus contract formation becomes increasingly certain. An impartial spectator nudging the parties to maximize the expected value of the surplus of their contemplated transaction would prescribe “maximize p with respect to R,” since S is already exogenously determined.

Although any possible division of the surplus created by voluntary exchange is mutually beneficial, that fact does not imply that every price along the bargaining range (which defines the locus of “reasonable” royalties) is equally likely to yield an agreement. How does a given split of the surplus between the SEP holder and the implementer influence the probability of their successful contract formation within a specified period of time? One interpretation of a fair royalty is that it leads more expeditiously to contract formation than some other division of the gains from trade. That is, the fairness component of the FRAND contract between the SEP holder and the SSO takes on independent meaning by giving teeth to the proposition that time is of the essence in achieving contract formation between the SEP holder and the implementer. Fairness promotes economic efficiency in the sense of hastening voluntary exchange, which is the prerequisite to the expeditious exploitation of the standard.

C. Dividing Surplus Fairly

The probability of a successful voluntary exchange increases as each party signals its willingness to accept a lesser share of the surplus that the transaction will create. Thus emerges a simple understanding of fairness, which can be expressed in comparative terms: The price corresponding to a given bilateral division of the surplus from a voluntary exchange is fairer than the price corresponding to some alternative bilateral division of that surplus if the first division is more likely than the second to lead the parties to agree to a successful transaction within some specified period of time.

My proposed definition of a fair price echoes, but is not identical to, certain themes found in the economic literature examining justice and fairness. Most notably, my definition resembles the proposition that fairness requires the approximately equal division of surplus, which Robert Frank proposed in 1988 in Passions within Reason.Footnote 60 However, my rationale for that definition differs from what I understand to be Frank’s reasoning.

1. The Established Royalty and the Bid–Ask Spread

If SEPs were bushels of wheat, one could observe a multitude of market transactions in the aggregate that would obviate the forensic attempt by expert witnesses and judges to divide the surplus between buyer and seller. The bid–ask spread would be a sliver, and that fact would be considered a virtuous indicator of market efficiency. The liquidity needs, patience, and bargaining skill of any given seller would be irrelevant to the market’s price formation. The idiosyncratic valuations of both the buyer and the seller also would be irrelevant. The conditions permitting an informed market price would obviate any inquiry into the outcome of a hypothetical bilateral negotiation between any two given parties at a given moment. Instead, we would simply consult the observed market price for the given asset on the day specified. In patent law, courts call this kind of market-determined price the “established royalty” for a patent.Footnote 61

2. Fairness in Executing Licenses to SEPs

When no established royalty is apparent, the court must determine how to divide fairly the surplus from licensing the SEPs. As I have argued earlier, a given interpretation of “fairness” for purposes of SEP royalties might actually be an efficiency rationale in disguise that nudges the parties toward a successful voluntary transaction when some emotion threatens to interfere with the maximization of economic surplus. By analogy, research on the Ultimatum Game suggests that emotions such as envy, anger, or spite might upset a negotiation and thus cause the parties to forgo the benefits of dividing the positive surplus from a successful contract formation.Footnote 62 (Recall, for example, how Hal Varian, building on work by Duncan Foley,Footnote 63 defined a given allocation of resources as fair if it is both Pareto efficient and free from envy,Footnote 64 and William Baumol defined a “superfair” allocation of resources as one free from envy.Footnote 65)

Matthew Rabin has studied how explicit consideration of fairness influences monopoly pricing.Footnote 66 An important caveat that he makes is that the players “make only mutually beneficial offers.”Footnote 67 This restriction is fortuitous for purposes of analogizing his analysis to a FRAND or RAND royalty negotiation because (in my opinion) the succinct economic meaning of the reasonableness constraint is to demand that the SEP holder’s offered price would produce a positive surplus for the offeror and for the offeree. Rabin then asks: “What is the highest price consistent with a fairness equilibrium at which this product could be sold?”Footnote 68 He finds that “the highest equilibrium price is lower than the conventional monopoly price when fairness is added to the equation.”Footnote 69 This result – which is consistent with the earlier experimental findings of Daniel Kahneman, Jack Knetsch, and Richard Thaler – implies, in Rabin’s words, that “a monopolist interested in maximizing profits ought not to set price at ‘the monopoly price,’ because it should take consumers’ attitudes toward fairness as a given.”Footnote 70

One might conjecture that the purpose of a contractual obligation to make a “fair” division of surplus is to keep on a short leash the human emotions that might upset a mutually beneficial transaction. This interpretation of “fair” seems to be an acknowledgment that some principle ostensibly rooted in fairness is in actuality a lubricant to facilitate efficient voluntary exchange. So viewed, the constraint that a price embody fairness is in truth a means to an end. Just as a reduction in transaction costs can facilitate the expeditious conclusion of a voluntary exchange, so too can the absence of certain kinds of provocative (or strategic) behavior reduce the likelihood that one party will walk away in anger or spite from a voluntary negotiation that, if completed, would create surplus in which both parties would share.Footnote 71 This possibility is consistent with the observation of Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler in 1986 that earlier arguments by Arthur Okun, George Akerlof, and Kenneth Arrow “to account for apparent deviations from the simple model of a profit-maximizing firm is that fair behavior is instrumental to maximization of long-run profits.”Footnote 72 “In these approaches,” they write, “the rules of fairness define the terms of an enforceable implicit contract: Firms that behave unfairly are punished in the long run.”Footnote 73

Fairness in executing licenses to today’s SEPs can serve as a credible commitment to one’s doing so with respect to tomorrow’s SEPs, which are currently unknown. Fairness in the execution of licenses can produce increased acceptance of the SEP holder’s technologies in future standards, increased participation by future implementers and holders of complementary SEPs, and an increased probability that the standard will achieve the scale necessary to be commercially successful. Fairness might be a commitment not to pull back the veil of ignorance, and thus fairness might discourage actions such as the IEEE’s 2015 bylaw revisions, which large implementers favored and large SEP holders opposed.Footnote 74

D. Licensing SEPs on Terms Consistent with the Fairness Constraint of the FRAND Contract between the SEP Holder and the SSO

By definition, any price within the bargaining range is mutually beneficial. But that fact does not imply that every such price is equally likely to yield an agreement. How does a given split of the surplus between the SEP holder and the implementer influence the probability of their successful contract formation within a specified period of time? Is the distinguishing characteristic of a fair royalty that it leads more expeditiously to contract formation than some other division of the same gains from trade?

To analyze this question, let us normalize the bargaining range so that it runs from 0 to 100. Normalizing the bargaining range simplifies the application of this analysis to different prospective implementers of the SEPs belonging to a given SEP holder. A license agreement struck at a normalized price of 0 gives the implementer 100% of the surplus. That is, an agreement at a normalized price of 0 is equivalent to a license bearing a royalty rate equal to the SEP holder’s minimum willingness to accept and not a penny more. In contrast, an agreement at a normalized price of 100 gives the SEP holder 100% of the surplus. That is, an agreement struck at a normalized price of 100 is equivalent to a license bearing a royalty rate equal to the implementer’s maximum willingness to pay and not a penny less.

For any license agreement struck at a normalized price between 0 and 100, each party will gain some of the surplus generated. For any possible agreement at a single given normalized price between 0 and 100, some probability exists that, within a specified period of time, the implementer will accept that price and enter into an agreement, and some different probability exists that the SEP holder will accept that same price and enter into an agreement. If both parties accept the same price, then an agreement is reached, and contract formation occurs.

The probability that the implementer will agree to terms decreases as the negotiated price moves farther from the SEP holder’s minimum willingness to accept and closer to the implementer’s maximum willingness to pay. Conversely, the probability that the SEP holder will agree to terms increases as the negotiated price moves farther from the SEP holder’s minimum willingness to accept and closer to the implementer’s maximum willingness to pay. The implementer has a “bid function” that determines the implementer’s probability of agreeing to terms (within a specified period of time) at any given price over the bargaining range. Similarly, the SEP holder has an “ask function” that determines the SEP holder’s probability of agreeing to terms (within the same specified period of time) at any given price over the bargaining range.

If the bid function and the ask function are symmetric, then the most common agreement will occur where the parties divide the gains from trade evenly. This 50–50 outcome is merely the arithmetic implication of the bid function’s being the mirror image of the ask function. It is important to emphasize that this result does not rely on the Nash bargaining solution, which predicts a 50–50 split of the surplus in a bilateral negotiation using cooperative game theory.Footnote 75 Nor does this result rely on the familiar cake-cutting principle described by Rawls and others – “You cut, I choose”Footnote 76 – which Peyton Young notes “is fair because the outcome is envy-free.”Footnote 77

However, there is no economic reason to expect that the bid function and the ask function will be symmetric. In practice, risk aversion, discount rates, or other economic factors will influence the specific shapes for the bid function and the ask function.

The point royalty within the range of reasonable royalties upon which the SEP holder and the implementer will agree – that is, how they will divide the surplus from voluntary exchange – will be determined by the parties’ relative bargaining power. The party that suffers least from delaying the agreement – that is, the party that is most patient – will typically have more bargaining power. Parties can have different levels of “patience” during a FRAND licensing negotiation while still negotiating in good faith, and it is common for SEP negotiations to take multiple years. For example, a SEP holder that lacks liquidity might need an immediate resolution of the negotiations. Or the implementer might be on the verge of releasing a standard-compliant product and therefore quickly needs a license to the SEPs before releasing a noninfringing product. Conversely, the SEP holder might not need an immediate license to the SEPs, which would increase its bargaining power. The near-absence of injunctive relief in SEP infringement litigation and the limited likelihood of enhanced damages might lead one to conclude, all other factors remaining the same, that implementers are more “patient.” It is well established in the economic literature that the cost that each party bears from a delay is measured by its respective discount rate.Footnote 78

A more precise model could use different assumptions concerning the probability of contract formation. For example, are the probabilities for the two parties independent of one another, or is each probability conditional on the expected reaction of the counterparty (and, if so, for how many future rounds of the negotiation)? These questions are appropriate to ask if an economist wants to model the probability of contract formation in precise mathematical terms – for example, along the lines of the Rubinstein bargaining model, which is based on noncooperative game theory.Footnote 79 But my goal here is more modest and more heuristic. So those particulars about the precise nature of the probabilities are unnecessary to resolve to make the larger point (which I believe a judge or jury could readily understand intuitively) – namely, that it is reasonable to expect that the speed of contract formation will depend on the relative parity or disparity of the shares by which each party to a negotiation proposes to divide the surplus from a successful licensing transaction.

One proposed division of surplus might be substantially more likely than another to yield successful contract formation within a specified period of time spent negotiating. For example, it seems intuitively clear that a 60–40 split of the surplus would more readily be accepted by both parties than would a 99–1 split. If so, we would say that the 60–40 split is fairer than the 99–1 split.

What would be the threshold for a judge or jury to make the qualitative determination that a particular division of surplus would be unfair? Perhaps the experimental results of the Ultimatum Game, which I discussed earlier, will suggest a useful line of analysis.

Footnotes

3 Cellular SEP Royalties and 5G What Should Competition Policy Be?

a These figures provide a basic perspective on these technologies’ capabilities and position to compete to do specific jobs-to-be-done. Some of these figures may be theoretical maximums, while others may be viewed as practical maximums. Many may represent estimates of varying rigor and quality. In either case, a host of assumptions may apply; for example, one might achieve a maximum rate at a minimal range. Future advances in technology, or perhaps in implementation techniques, may improve upon these figures.

b Report ITU-R M.2410-0 (11/2017), Minimum requirements related to technical performance for IMT-2020 radio interface(s), www.itu.int/dms_pub/itu-r/opb/rep/R-REP-M.2410-2017-PDF-E.pdf.

c Ronan McLaughlin, “5G low latency requirements,” Broadband Library, https://broadbandlibrary.com/5g-low-latency-requirements/.

d Jeremy Horwitz, “The definitive guide to 5G low, mid, and high band speeds” (Dec. 10, 2019), https://venturebeat.com/mobile/the-definitive-guide-to-5g-low-mid-and-high-band-speeds/.

e Ronan McLaughlin, “5G low latency requirements,” Broadband Library.

f “How fast are 4G and 5G?,” 4G.co.uk, www.4g.co.uk/how-fast-is-4g/.

g “Ericsson and Telstra extend reach on an LTE network up to 200km,” Ericsson (Feb. 27, 2020), www.ericsson.com/en/press-releases/2/2020/2/ericsson-and-telstra-extend-reach-on-an-lte-network-up-to-200km.

i “Bluetooth low energy basics: classic Bluetooth vs. Bluetooth LE,” How to Electronics (May 20, 2023), https://how2electronics.com/classic-bluetooth-vs-bluetooth-low-energy-comparison/

j Jon Gunnar Sponås, “Things You Should Know About Bluetooth Range,” Nordic Semiconductor (Jan. 25, 2023), https://blog.nordicsemi.com/getconnected/things-you-should-know-about-bluetooth-range.

k “Comparison of Wireless Technologies: LoRaWAN and Zigbee, WiFi, NB-IoT,” DFRobot (Apr. 12, 2023), www.dfrobot.com/blog-1646.html.

l Anthony Spadafora, “Starlink internet coverage, cost, speeds and the latest news,” Tom’s Guide, (June 16, 2023), www.tomsguide.com/news/starlink-internet-coverage-speed-cost-satellites-ipo-and-latest-news.

m “DOCSIS 4.0 Technology,” CableLabs (July 3, 2023), www.cablelabs.com/technologies/docsis-4-0-technology.

n Vivian Susko, “DOCSIS 4.0, Explained,” Minim (Apr. 21, 2021), www.minim.com/blog/docsis-4.0-explained.

o “DOCSIS 4.0 Technology,” CableLabs (July 3, 2023).

p Vivian Susko, “DOCSIS 4.0, Explained,” Minim (Apr. 21, 2021).

q Jeff Heynen, “50G PON moves closer to deployment,” Dell’Oro (Apr. 19, 2023), www.delloro.com/50g-pon-moves-closer-to-deployment/.

r “Consumer Drones Comparison” (July 5, 2023), DJI.com, www.dji.com/products/comparison-consumer-drones.

1 Multi-access Edge Computing (MEC) deploys cloud-computing capabilities “at the edge of the network” – that is, the equivalent of the base station – thus obtaining ultra-low latency and high bandwidth. In addition, it allows real-time access to radio network information that can be used by applications. Operators can open their Radio Access Network (RAN), enabling service providers to offer applications and services to mobile subscribers, households, and firms. Multi-access Edge Computing (MEC), ETSI, www.etsi.org/technologies/multi-access-edge-computing (last visited May 18, 2022).

2 A Ricardian rent arises from differential productivity or costs per unit among factors of production on the types of rent; see Roger G. Noll, “Buyer Power” and Economic Policy, 72 Antitrust L.J. 589, 592–94 (2005). In the business literature, this is usually called a competitive advantage or a differential firm capability.

3 Base Station Market Poised for Strong Year Thanks to 5G and China According to Omdia, Microwave J. (Dec. 7, 2020), www.microwavejournal.com/articles/35089-base-station-market-poised-for-strong-year-thanks-to-5g-and-china-according-to-omdia.

4 Press Release, Dell’Oro Grp., Open RAN on Track Comprise 15 Percent of RAN by 2026 (Jan. 21, 2022), www.delloro.com/news/open-ran-on-track-comprise-15-percent-of-ran-by-2026/.

5 Worldwide Mobile Data Pricing 2021, Cable.co.uk, www.cable.co.uk/mobiles/worldwide-data-pricing/ (last visited Apr. 9, 2021).

6 Mark A. Lemley & Carl Shapiro, Patent Holdup and Royalty Stacking, 85 Tex. L. Rev. 1991 (2007).

7 This section is based on Alexander Galetovic & Stephen Haber, SEP Royalties: What Theory of Value and Distribution Should Courts Apply?, 17 Ohio St. Tech. L.J. 189 (2021).

8 Galetovic & Haber, supra Footnote note 7, at 197.

9 To draw the intercept of the linear demand curve on the price axis, we followed Alexander Galetovic, Stephen Haber, & Lew Zaretzki, Is There an Anticommons Tragedy in the World Smartphone Industry?, 32 Berkeley Tech. L.J. 1527, 1550 (2017), who use the fact that 2G phones, which were considerably inferior devices compared with a 2016 smartphone, were introduced at $1,400 in 1992. It is likely that this underestimates consumers’ willingness to pay and hence biases our calculation toward obtaining smaller market power rents. Consumers buy different models and brands. Nevertheless, they are free to choose among models and brands, and in equilibrium, marginal consumers are indifferent among them. Consequently, one could build a quality-adjusted average phone and work with this demand curve.

10 The August 2017 update of the database, which shows the sources and calculations in detail, is available in an Excel workbook available upon request. Alexander Galetovic, Stephen Haber, & Lew Zaretzki, An Estimate of the Average Cumulative Royalty Yield in the World Mobile Phone Industry: Theory, Measurement and Results, 42 Telecomm. Pol’y 263, 266 (2018).

11 This is equal to about 1% of world GDP.

12 Indeed, the profits of patent licensors would have been of the order of 0.6 % of world GDP.

13 Lemley & Shapiro, supra Footnote note 6.

14 We use the term royalty “yield” rather than royalty “rate.” “Rate” refers to the actual royalty paid by a licensee to a licensor as a percentage of the licensee’s sales. “Yield” is the sum of patent royalty payments divided by the total value of mobile phones shipped, the latter of which might include the production of those who evade patent licenses.

15 Galetovic et al. (2018), supra Footnote note 10.

18 This means that we now omit licensors focused on non-SEP licensing as well as those focused on licensing SEPs not related to cellular technologies, for example those related to digital audio and video technologies and Wi-Fi. This results in our removing licensors such as IBM, Rambus, and Xperi from our study, as well as patent pools such as Via Licensing’s AAC program and MPEG-LA’s H.264 and MPEG-4 programs.

19 For the methodology behind this calculation and the calculations in the subsequent paragraph, see the Appendix.

20 Clayton M. Christensen, Taddy Hall, Karen Dillon, & David S. Duncan, Know Your Customer’sJobs to Be Done,” Harvard Business Review (Sept. 2016), https://hbr.org/2016/09/know-your-customers-jobs-to-be-done.

22 Cisco VNI Global Mobile Data Traffic Forecast, 2017–2022, Cisco (Feb. 2019), https://twiki.cern.ch/twiki/pub/HEPIX/TechwatchNetwork/HtwNetworkDocuments/white-paper-c11-741490.pdf.

23 New Cisco Annual Internet Report Forecasts 5G to Support More Than 10% of Global Mobile Connections by 2023, Cisco (Feb. 18, 2020), www.cisco.com/c/en/us/solutions/collateral/executive-perspectives/annual-internet-report/white-paper-c11-741490.html.

24 Starlink Statistics (Oct. 22, 2022, 11:48 PM), https://planet4589.org/space/stats/star/starstats.html.

25 Caleb Henry, SpaceX Submits Paperwork for 30,000 More Starlink Satellites, Space News (Oct. 15, 2019), https://spacenews.com/spacex-submits-paperwork-for-30000-more-starlink-satellites/.

26 Michael Kan, SpaceX Preps ‘Ruggedized’ Starlink Dish for Cars, Boats, and Planes, PC Mag (Aug. 4, 2021), www.pcmag.com/news/spacex-preps-ruggedized-starlink-dish-for-cars-boats-and-planes.

27 Helium.com, www.helium.com/ (last visited Oct. 23, 2022).

28 These figures provide a basic perspective on these technologies’ capabilities and position to compete to do specific jobs-to-be-done. Some of these figures may be theoretical maximums, while others may be viewed as practical maximums. Many may represent estimates of varying rigor and quality. In either case, a host of assumptions may apply; for example, one might achieve a maximum rate at a minimal range. Future advances in technology, or perhaps in implementation techniques, may improve upon these figures.

4 The Fair Division of Surplus from a FRAND License Negotiated in Good Faith

1 Guanyu Shenli Biaozhun Biyao Zhuanli Jiufen Anjian De Gongzuo Zhiyin (Shixing) (关于审理标准必要专利纠纷案件的工作指引 (试行)) [Working Guidelines on the Trial of Standard-Essential Patent Dispute Cases (for Trial Implementation)] (Apr. 26, 2018); Guide to Licensing Negotiations Involving Standard Essential Patents, Japan Patent Office (June 5, 2018), www.jpo.go.jp/e/support/general/sep_portal/document/index/guide-seps-en.pdf; Communication from the Com. to the Eur. Parliament, the Council, & the Eur. Econ. and Soc. Comm., COM (2017) 712 final, at 2 (Nov. 29, 2017) (“The Commission … considers that there is an urgent need to set out key principles that foster a balanced, smooth and predictable framework for SEPs.”); Andrei Iancu, Under Sec’y of Com. for Intell. Prop. & Dir. of the United States Patent and Trademark Office, Remarks Delivered at the Standard-Essential Patents Strategy Conference, Solvay Business School, Université Libre de Bruxelles (ULB) (Sept. 10, 2019), www.uspto.gov/about-us/news-updates/remarks-director-iancu-standard-essential-patents-strategy-conference (“Government policy should make clear that good faith negotiations are expected on both sides, and that the presence or absence of good faith during negotiations can be a factor in the setting of remedies for infringement of FRAND-encumbered SEPs.”).

2 US Dep’t of Just., Public Comments Welcome on Draft Policy Statement on Licensing Negotiations and Remedies for Standards-Essential Patents Subject to F/RAND Commitments (Dec. 6, 2021), www.justice.gov/opa/pr/public-comments-welcome-draft-policy-statement-licensing-negotiations-and-remedies-standards?utm_campaign%20=%20subscriptioncenter&utm_content%20=%20&utm_medium%20=%20email&utm_name%20=%20&utm_source%20=%20govdelivery&utm_term=; Standard Essential Patents and Innovation: Call for Views, Intellectual Property Office (UK) (Dec. 7, 2021), www.gov.uk/government/consultations/standard-essential-patents-and-innovation-call-for-views/standard-essential-patents-and-innovation-call-for-views; Jacob Schindler, Japanese Ministry Seeks Industry Input on SEP Negotiation Guidelines, IAM (Feb. 7, 2022), www.iam-media.com/frand/japanese-ministry-seeks-industry-input-sep-negotiation-guidelines (citing Ministry of Economy, Trade, and Industry, Study Group on the Ideal Trading Environment for Licenses for Standard Essential Patents (Dec. 15, 2021) (Japan), www.meti.go.jp/shingikai/economy/patent_license/pdf/006_gijiyoshi.pdf?_x_tr_sl%20=%20ja&_x_tr_tl%20=%20en&_x_tr_hl%20=%20ja&_x_tr_pto%20=%20wapp); European Commission, Call for Evidence for an Impact Assessment; Intellectual Property – New Framework for Standard-Essential Patents, ARES (2022) 1076263 (Feb. 14, 2022) (EU), https://ec.europa.eu/info/law/better-regulation/have-your-say/initiatives/13109-Intellectual-property-new-framework-for-standard-essential-patents_en.

3 Sisvel v. Haier, Bundesgerichtshof [BGH] [Federal Court of Justice] May 5, 2020, KZR 36/17, ¶ 83 (Ger.), www.arnold-ruess.com/fileadmin/user_upload/2020_07_07_FCJ_SisvelvHaier_English (“The obligation of the market dominant patentee to inform the infringing party about the infringement and the possibility of obtaining a licence and to make an offer of a licence to the infringer willing to take a licence is not an end in itself, but is intended to make it easier for the latter to negotiate reasonable conditions with the patentee for his use. For this reason, after the first indication of infringement, it is not sufficient for the establishment of further obligations for the market-dominant patentee if the infringer then merely shows himself willing to consider entering into a licence agreement or to enter into negotiations as to whether and under what conditions the conclusion of a contract is possible for him. Rather, the infringer, for his part, must clearly and unequivocally declare his willingness to conclude a licence agreement with the patent proprietor on reasonable and non-discriminatory terms and must also subsequently participate in the licence agreement negotiations in a target oriented manner.”) (citation omitted); Unwired Planet Int’l Ltd. v. Huawei Techs. Co. [2017] EWHC (Pat) 711 [163] (Eng.) (“The implementer must take a FRAND approach to the negotiation and accept a licence on FRAND terms if it wishes to take advantage of the constraint on the patentee’s rights imposed by the FRAND undertaking. A FRAND approach to negotiation does not mean that parties cannot negotiate in good faith and a FRAND approach will allow for starting offers which leave room for negotiation. The fact an opening offered rate is higher than the true FRAND rate does not mean of itself that a patentee has failed to take a FRAND approach any more than the converse could be said about an implementer. On the other hand, making extreme offers and taking an intransigent approach which prejudice fair, reasonable and non‑discriminatory negotiation is not a FRAND approach.”), aff’d, [2018] EWCA (Civ) 2344 (Eng.), aff’d, [2020] UKSC 37 (Eng.); id. [693] (“An alleged infringer who wishes to show they are a willing licensee would do well to make an open offer of the FRAND terms it would be prepared to accept.”); id. [708] (“[A] willing licensee must be one willing to take a FRAND licence on whatever terms are in fact FRAND.”).

4 TCL Commc’n Tech. Holdings, Ltd. v. Telefonaktiebolaget LM Ericsson, Nos. SACV 14-341 JVS, CV 15-2370 JVS, 2018 WL 4488286, at *6 (C.D. Cal. Sept. 14, 2018), vacated, reversed in part, and remanded, 943 F.3d 1360 (Fed. Cir. 2019). For my own extended discussion of the SEP holder’s and the implementer’s possible duties to negotiate a FRAND license in good faith, see J. Gregory Sidak, Judge Selna’s Errors in TCL v. Ericsson Concerning Apportionment, Nondiscrimination, and Royalties under the FRAND Contract, 4 Criterion J. Innovation 101, 102–07 (2019) [hereinafter Judge Selna’s Errors].

5 Makan Delrahim, Assistant Att’y Gen., Antitrust Div., US Dep’t of Just., Remarks as Prepared for the Licensing Executives Society (LES) 2019 Annual Meeting: “The Times They Are A’Changin’”: The Nine No-No’s in 2019, at 6 (Oct. 21, 2019), www.justice.gov/opa/speech/file/1213831/download (“[A]ctual evidence of hold-up remains scant even after a decade has passed since the theory was first introduced. The gulf between the theory and practice is especially troubling as many advocates ignore the real risk of hold‑out by potential licensees of the chosen SEP technology. ‘Hold-out,’ of course, refers to the countervailing problem to hold-up: when an implementer licensee refuses to negotiate in good faith with a patent holder for a license, and instead forces the patent holder either to undertake significant litigation costs or to give up IP enforcement efforts.”).

6 Letter from Makan Delrahim, Assistant Att’y Gen., US Dep’t of Just., to Sophia A. Muirhead, Gen. Coun. & Chief Compliance Officer, IEEE (Sept. 10, 2020), www.justice.gov/atr/page/file/1315291/download (emphasis in original).

7 DOJ Policy: Department Restores 2015 Business Review Letter Interpreted as Opposing SEP Holders Seeking Injunctive Relief, Capitol Forum (Apr. 14, 2021).

8 The economists who made major contributions to the design of those spectrum auctions include Nobel laureate Paul Milgrom of Stanford, Paul Klemperer of Oxford, and Ken Binmore of University College London. Paul Milgrom, Putting Auction Theory to Work (2004); Paul Klemperer, Auctions: Theory and Practice (2004); Ken Binmore & Paul Klemperer, The Biggest Auction Ever: The Sale of the British 3G Telecom Licenses, 112 Econ. J. C74 (2002); Paul Milgrom, Putting Auction Theory to Work: The Simultaneous Ascending Auction, 108 J. Pol. Econ. 245 (2000).

9 J. Gregory Sidak, The FRAND Contract, 3 Criterion J. Innovation 1 (2018). In at least one reported case, a RAND commitment was found to be unenforceable, thus mooting the question of contract interpretation. In an investigation before the US International Trade Commission (ITC), Chief Administrative Law Judge Charles Bullock, in the public version of his Initial Determination on Violation of Section 337 and Recommended Determination on Remedy and Bond, found that, on the basis of the specific facts of the case, and pursuant to New York law, the complainant’s RAND commitment to the Joint Electron Device Engineering Council (JEDEC) was too ambiguous to constitute an enforceable contract. Inv. No. 337-TA-1023, slip op. at 195 (USITC Nov. 14, 2017) (Initial Determination – Public Version); Sidak, The FRAND Contract, supra Footnote note 9, at 2–6.

10 Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., The Common Law (1881).

11 Richard A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (9th ed. 2014). As a new federal appellate judge, Posner relished every opportunity to cite an old common law case. Within four months of joining the Seventh Circuit, he found in a diversity case of first impression that Hadley v. Baxendale was the controlling authority for deciding a breach-of-contract claim involving a misdirected electronic funds transfer. EVRA Corp. v. Swiss Bank Corp., 673 F.2d 951, 955–59 (7th Cir. 1982).

12 For example, a discussion on contract formation under French law that predates the 2016 revisions of the Civil Code states:

French law sees a contract as an agreement, and it shares with English law (and indeed all other Western systems) the analysis of that agreement in terms of offer and acceptance. The practical results of that analysis quite often, however, diverge from those found in English law, and where this is so it is usually because French law … adopts a more subjective approach.

Barry Nicholas, The French Law of Contract 61 (2d ed. 1992). Elsewhere, Nicholas discusses – again, before the 2016 revisions of the French Civil Code – the difference between English and French contract law at a higher level of abstraction:

It is clear … that the analysis of contract in terms of a free agreement of wills (or, in English terms, a meeting of minds) is common to both the French and the English classical theories of contract and remains part of the common currency of both systems.

Where the two systems differ … is partly in the intellectual rigour with which the analysis is carried through to detailed consequences, and partly in the way that agreement is understood: as a subjective meeting of two minds or as the objective appearance of agreement. English law usually favours the latter approach, as being the more practical and the more conducive to the certainty which commercial convenience demands, whereas French law inclines to the former, though sometimes with a corrective which yields much the same practical result as the objective approach.

Footnote Id. at 35. I would argue, for the reasons that I explain in this chapter, that it is erroneous as an empirical matter to assume that “much the same practical result” will occur when contract formation for the licensing of SEPs is analyzed under a FRAND or RAND obligation controlled by French law than when American law (typically New York law) controls the interpretation of contract formation between the SEP holder and the implementer. For further analysis of offer and acceptance under French law before the 2016 revisions, see John Bell, Sophie Boyron, & Simon Whittaker, Principles of French Law 302–05 (2d ed. 2008). For analysis of contract formation under French law after the 2016 revisions, see Ruth Sefton-Green, Formation of Contract: Negotiation and the Process of Agreement, in The Code Napoléon Rewritten: French Contract Law after the 2016 Reforms 59 (John Cartwright & Simon Whittaker eds., 2017).

13 Bell et al., supra Footnote note 12, at 334 (“[S]ome [French] jurists consider that the principle of good faith is a useful way for French contract law to be or to become more ‘social’, … allowing the Cour de cassation to ‘promote a degree of good citizenship in the relationship of parties to a contract, this being preferable to the cynicism which an exclusively economic understanding of contractual relations could bring’. However, other jurists warn against the potentially subjective and uncertain nature of the concept, or deny the vision of contracts as ‘a little society where each party works for a common good’ on the basis that … ‘contracts often appear as the result of a tension between antagonistic interests, the striking of a balance between divergent interests’. So, ‘the duty of good faith does not oblige a person to protect the interests of another person to the detriment of his own interest, as some of the partisans of the unlikely notion of “contractual solidarity” contend’.”) (footnotes omitted) (first quoting Denis Mazeaud, La Politique Contractuelle de la Cour de Cassation, in Libre Propos sur les Sources du Droit, Mélanges en l’Honneur de Philippe Jestaz 371, 382 (2006); then quoting François Terré, Philippe Simler, & Yves Lequette, Droit Civil: Les Obligations 443 (2005); and then quoting Philippe Malaurie, Laurent Aynès, & Philippe Stoffel-Munck, Les Obligations 373 (2007)); Nicholas, supra Footnote note 12, at 48 (“[W]here the Common law, in the interests of commercial convenience and the security of transactions, looks to the external appearance of consent, French law, influenced no doubt by the doctrine of the autonomy of the will and more concerned for justice in the individual case than for commercial expediency, often takes account of the true state of mind of one of the parties. … [Thus,] the requirement of good faith, though explicitly mentioned by the Code [Napoléon] only in connection with the performance of contracts, is introduced into the context of their formation under cover of the requirement of a genuine consent.”); Sefton-Green, supra Footnote note 12, at 60 (“It could be said that good faith is a big empty envelope into which a lot of concrete circumstances can be folded.”); Open Sessions Volume IV at 1111:9–18, Certain LTE- and 3G-Compliant Cellular Communications Devices, Inv. No. 337-TA-1138 (USITC Sept. 17, 2019) (Testimony of Bertrand Fages) (“Q [by Counsel for INVT SPE LLC, the SEP holder and complainant]. Under French law, what does good faith require? A. Under French law it’s ultimately up to the judge to decide what French law is in the context of each case; but in concrete terms, act in good faith is making serious proposals, which are consistent with the economic value and the purpose of the contract, and generally, to adopt an active attitude to achieve successful negotiations.”).

14 Bell et al., supra Footnote note 12, at 334.

15 HTC Corp. v. Telefonaktiebolaget LM Ericsson, 12 F.4th 476, 484 (5th Cir. 2021) (“[The] FRAND commitment ‘is “governed by the laws of France,” and is “solely [] contractual [in] nature.”’”) (alterations in original) (quoting HTC Corp. v. Telefonaktiebolaget LM Ericsson, No. 6:18-CV-00243-JRG, 2019 WL 126980, at *3 (E.D. Tex. Jan. 7, 2019) (quoting European Telecommunications Standards Institute, ETSI Intellectual Property Rights Policy, Annex 6, § 12 (Apr. 3, 2019) [hereinafter ETSI IPR Policy], www.etsi.org/images/files/IPR/etsi-ipr-policy.pdf)).

16 Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers [IEEE], IEEE-SA Standards Board Bylaws § 3, at 3 (Feb. 2022), https://standards.ieee.org/content/dam/ieee-standards/standards/web/documents/other/sb_bylaws.pdf.

17 Sidak, Judge Selna’s Errors, supra Footnote note 4, at 104–07.

18 Consolidated Version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union art. 102(c), Oct. 26, 2012, 2012 O.J. (C 326) 47.

19 Huawei Techs. Co. v. ZTE Corp., Case C‑170/13, ECLI:EU:C:2015:477 (July 16, 2015).

20 Sidak, Judge Selna’s Errors, supra Footnote note 4, at 102–07.

21 In 2015, I observed:

With respect to contract performance and enforcement, the Restatement [of Contracts] says that “[e]very contract imposes upon each party a duty of good faith and fair dealing …” It is not clear why this symmetry of obligations should give way to asymmetry of obligations at the stage of contract formation, assuming that a court is inferring that the common law duty of good faith and fair dealing encompasses contractual negotiations.

J. Gregory Sidak, The Meaning of FRAND, Part II: Injunctions, 11 J. Competition L. & Econ. 201, 217 n.67 (2015) (emphasis added) (citation omitted) (quoting Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 205 (Am. Law Inst. 1981)).

22 Posner, supra Footnote note 11, at 760–62.

23 Sidak, Judge Selna’s Errors, supra Footnote note 4, at 107.

24 Code Civ. [Civ. Code] art. 1104 (Fr.), translated in John Cartwright, Bénédicte Fauvarque-Cosson, & Simon Whittaker, The Law of Contract, The General Regime of Obligations, and Proof of Obligations art. 1104 (2016). “This provision is a matter of public policy.” Id. This translation of the “provisions of the Code civil created by Ordonnance n˚ 2016-131 of 10 February 2016 … was commissioned by the Direction des affaires civiles et du sceau, Ministère de la Justice, République française.” Id. at 1.

25 Northwest, Inc. v. Ginsberg, 572 U.S. 273, 295 (2014) (“[M]ost States recognize some form of the good faith and fair dealing doctrine.”); Sidak, Judge Selna’s Errors, supra Footnote note 4, at 105–06 & nn. 23–27.

26 HTC Corp. v. Telefonaktiebolaget LM Ericsson, No. 6:18-CV-00243-JRG, 2018 WL 6617795, at *5–6 (E.D. Tex. Dec. 17, 2018).

27 It is worth questioning whether the negotiation of a license to SEPs declared essential to ETSI is beyond the scope of the performance of the SEP holder’s FRAND contract with ETSI to be “prepared to grant” a license, and thus outside the scope of ETSI’s choice-of-law provision. I leave the task of answering this question to others more familiar with French law.

28 Certain Wireless Devices with 3G Capabilities and Components Thereof, Inv. No. 337-TA-800, Initial Determination at 422 (USITC June 28, 2013) (“The parties agree that the ETSI IPR Policy is governed by French law. Under French law, the type of obligation set forth in the ETSI undertaking is best described as un accord de principe (agreement in principle). This imposes on both negotiating parties a duty to negotiate in good faith. It does not, however, impose an obligation actually to conclude a contract … In this regard, French law is consistent with U.S. contract law, under which a generalized ‘agreement to agree’ is unenforceable, but parties may enter into binding agreements to negotiate.”) (citations omitted); Certain LTE- and 3G-Compliant Cellular Communications Devices, Inv. No. 337-TA-1138, Open Sessions Volume IV at 1106:8–21 (USITC Sept. 17, 2019) (McNamara, ALJ) (Testimony of Bertrand Fages) (“Q [by Counsel for INVT SPE LLC, the SEP holder and complainant]. What is an accord de principe, or agreement in principle under French law? A. An agreement in principle is characterized by the fact that it entails no obligation to contract, but only an obligation to negotiate in good faith; and this obligation to negotiate in good faith is only an obligation of means that permits behavior, consists of having an attitude in order to achieve successful negotiations by conducting them fairly, and we have a decision from the Paris Court of Appeal that puts it very clearly by saying that there is no obligation to conclude but only a commitment to negotiate.”); Bell et al., supra Footnote note 12, at 305 (“Sometimes parties to contractual negotiations make preliminary agreements before concluding any ultimate contract. French law’s attitude to these is generally more favourable than is English law’s owing in particular to the absence of the requirement of consideration … A very important example of pre-contractual agreements which are enforced as contracts are ‘unilateral promises to contract’ (promesses unilatérales de contrat). Here, a person promises to contract on particular terms with another at the latter’s option, this promise being binding once accepted. Of more uncertain status are ‘agreements in principle’ (accords de principe) which usually involve an agreement by the parties on certain matters and that they will continue to negotiate towards final contract … Even in the absence of any preliminary agreement as to the course or conduct of negotiations, French law holds the parties to a standard of proper conduct, [which is] referred to either positively in terms of the requirements of good faith or negatively in terms of the parties having ‘abused their right’ to break off negotiations before a contract is concluded.”) (footnotes omitted).

29 Market St. Assocs. Ltd. v. Frey, 941 F.2d 588, 593–94 (7th Cir. 1991) (“In fact the law contemplates that people frequently will take advantage of the ignorance of those with whom they contract, without thereby incurring liability. The duty of honesty, of good faith even expansively conceived, is not a duty of candor. You can make a binding contract to purchase something you know your seller undervalues.”) (citations omitted); id. at 594 (“But it is one thing to say that you can exploit your superior knowledge of the market – for if you cannot, you will not be able to recoup the investment you made in obtaining that knowledge – or that you are not required to spend money bailing out a contract partner who has gotten into trouble. It is another thing to say that you can take deliberate advantage of an oversight by your contract partner concerning his rights under the contract. Such taking advantage is not the exploitation of superior knowledge or the avoidance of unbargained-for expense; it is sharp dealing. Like theft, it has no social product, and also like theft it induces costly defensive expenditures, in the form of overelaborate disclaimers or investigations into the trustworthiness of a prospective contract partner, just as the prospect of theft induces expenditures on locks.”); id. at 595–96 (“The emphasis we are placing on postcontractual versus precontractual conduct helps explain the pattern that is observed when the duty of contractual good faith is considered in all its variety, encompassing not only good faith in the performance of a contract but also good faith in its formation and in its enforcement. The formation or negotiation stage is precontractual, and here the duty is minimized. It is greater not only at the performance but also at the enforcement stage, which is also postcontractual … At the formation of the contract the parties are dealing in present realities; performance still lies in the future. As performance unfolds, circumstances change, often unforeseeably; the explicit terms of the contract become progressively less apt to the governance of the parties’ relationship; and the role of implied conditions – and with it the scope and bite of the good-faith doctrine – grows.”) (emphasis in original) (citations omitted).

30 I do not attempt to answer the question of whether the duty to negotiate in good faith under contract law (relevant to the license negotiation) is different (narrower or broader) than the contractual duty of good faith negotiation that is presumed to exist under the FRAND contract.

31 J. Gregory Sidak, Enhanced Damages for Infringement of Standard-Essential Patents, 1 Criterion J. Innovation 1101 (2016).

32 Furthermore, to the extent that a court were to find ETSI’s FRAND commitment not to be contractual, there is reason to doubt that the SEP holder’s promise could have binding effect under French contract law, which does not recognize promissory estoppel as an available claim. In 2019, Yves-Marie Laithier, a professor of French contract law at the Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne, testified in a pretrial hearing in u-blox v. InterDigital that “[t]he doctrine of promissory estoppel is unknown in French contract law. It is indeed untranslatable in French.” Declaration of Prof. Yves-Marie Laithier in Support of Motion to Dismiss at 2, u-blox AG v. InterDigital Inc., No. 19-cv-00001-CAB-BLM (S.D. Cal. Feb. 25, 2019), ECF No. 50-5. That conclusion comports with the understanding that promissory estoppel “is peculiar to common law systems.” Id. (quoting John Cartwright, Formation and Variation of Contracts § 10-01 (2d ed. 2018)).

33 That ambiguity is exemplified by the opposing expert reports of two French law scholars filed in late 2018 and early 2019 in one such case. Compare Expert Report of Dr. Philippe Stoffel-Munck ¶ 121, at 29, Koninklijke KPN N.V. v. Sierra Wireless, Inc., No. 17-090-LPS-CJB (D. Del. Nov. 20, 2018) (“[T]he Declarant must grant a license on FRAND terms and must negotiate in good faith irrespective of the outcome of their negotiations and, a fortiori, irrespective of the binding force that their future agreement will be given or not in retrospect. In any event, they must answer for any loss caused to the other party by any breach of their duty to grant a license on FRAND terms and to negotiate in good faith.”), ECF No. 205‑1, and Reply Expert Report of Dr. Philippe Stoffel-Munck ¶ 77, at 16, Sierra Wireless, No. 17-090-LPS-CJB (D. Del. Feb. 3, 2019) (“Where the negotiations form part of a binding agreement, the duty of good faith becomes more demanding, as comes into play the duty to perform in good faith.”) (emphasis in original), ECF No. 205-1, with Rebuttal Expert Report of Dr. Vernon Valentine Palmer ¶ 133, at 39–40, Sierra Wireless, No. 17-090-LPS-CJB (D. Del. Jan. 8, 2019) (“[T]o the extent any good faith obligation exists, it is simply one to avoid committing a clear abuse of the liberty to negotiate freely – an obligation that would not be understood to require that a debtor put aside its own interests in favor of another party.”).

34 Seneca, On the Shortness of Life 1 (C.D.N. Costa trans., 1997) (49 A.D.).

35 J. Gregory Sidak, What Makes FRAND Fair? The Just Price, Contract Formation, and the Division of Surplus from Voluntary Exchange, 4 Criterion J. Innovation 701, 725–27 (2019) [hereinafter What Makes FRAND Fair?]; Sidak, The FRAND Contract, supra Footnote note 9, at 13–14 & n.47 (citing J. Gregory Sidak, Irreparable Harm from Patent Infringement, 2 Criterion J. Innovation 1 (2017); J. Gregory Sidak, Is Harm Ever Irreparable?, 2 Criterion J. Innovation 7, 10 (2017) (Inaugural Address for the Ronald Coase Professorship in Law and Economics, Tilburg University, Tilburg, The Netherlands (Sept. 16, 2011)).

36 Sidak, The Meaning of FRAND, Part II: Injunctions, supra Footnote note 21, at 218.

37 Klemperer, supra Footnote note 8, at 181–82; Milgrom 2004, supra Footnote note 8, at 5–6, 14 (discussing the activity rule used in US spectrum auctions in 1994).

38 Sidak, The FRAND Contract, supra Footnote note 9, at 15–19.

39 Evan Kwerel, Foreword, in Milgrom 2004, supra Footnote note 8, at xvii.

40 Footnote Id.; Milgrom 2004, supra Footnote note 8, at 267 (“The auction closing rule is especially important: the [simultaneous ascending] auction ends only after a round in which there are no new bids on any license.”) (emphasis in original).

41 J. Gregory Sidak, Fair and Unfair Discrimination in Royalties for Standard-Essential Patents Encumbered by a FRAND or RAND Commitment, 2 Criterion J. Innovation 301, 333–34 (2017); J. Gregory Sidak, Bargaining Power and Patent Damages, 19 Stan. Tech. L. Rev. 1, 20–22 (2015).

42 Jack Hirshleifer, Amihai Glazer, & David Hirshleifer, Price Theory and Applications: Decisions, Markets, and Information 203 (7th ed. 2005).

43 Footnote Id. at 203–04.

44 Footnote Id. at 204 n.4 (emphasis in original); Armen A. Alchian & William R. Allen, Exchange and Production: Competition, Coordination, and Control 48–49 (3d ed. 1983) (demonstrating that the total surplus in a negotiation is the sum of the seller’s gain from trade and the buyer’s gain from trade).

45 Ian Steedman, Reservation Price and Reservation Demand, in 4 The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics 158 (John Eatwell, Murray Milgate, & Peter Newman eds., 1987); Klemperer, Auctions: Theory and Practice, supra Footnote note 8, at 18, 109, 112; Milgrom 2004, supra Footnote note 8, at 9–11; Robert L. Phillips, Pricing and Revenue Optimization 46 (Stanford University Press 2005); Robert S. Pindyck & Daniel L. Rubinfeld, Microeconomics 393, 510–11 (9th ed. 2018); John G. Riley, Essential Microeconomics 451–56 (2012); Garrett J. van Ryzin, Models of Demand, in The Oxford Handbook of Pricing Management 340, 342–43 (Özalp Özer & Robert Phillips eds., 2012).

46 Two handbooks published by the Cambridge University Press concerning SEPs do not explain how fairness constrains the calculation of a FRAND royalty. Patent Remedies and Complex Products: Toward a Global Consensus (C. Bradford Biddle et al. eds., 2019); The Cambridge Handbook of Technical Standardization Law: Competition, Antitrust, and Patents (Jorge L. Contreras ed., 2017).

47 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 11 (rev. ed. 1999) (1971); John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (Erin Kelly ed. 2001); John Rawls, Justice as Fairness: Political Not Metaphysical, 14 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 223 (1985). Rawls’ biographer, Thomas Pogge, reminds us that Rawls began A Theory of Justice with this proposition: “Justice is the first virtue of social institutions.” Thomas Pogge, John Rawls: His Life and Theory of Justice 28 (Michelle Kosch trans., 2007) (quoting Rawls, A Theory of Justice, supra Footnote note 47, at 3). Pogge then explains how this proposition relates to the making and keeping of promises. By referring to “social institutions,”

Rawls means to refer to the practices and rules that structure relationships and interactions among agents. This sense [of Rawls’ use of “social institutions”] is exemplified by a social institution of promising. Its rules lay down what interactions between two agents count as creating a promise, what promisee conduct (if any) counts as releasing the promisor from the promise, what circumstances (if any) can be invoked as justification or excuse for nonperformance, and so on.

Footnote Id. By Pogge’s account, Rawls’ Theory of Justice has greater relevance to contract interpretation than might immediately appear to be the case for a book on political philosophy.

48 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, supra Footnote note 47, at 14; id. at 14–15 (“The merit of the contract terminology is that it conveys the idea that principles of justice may be conceived as principles that would be chosen by rational persons, and that in this way conceptions of justice may be explained and justified.”).

49 Footnote Id. at 15 (emphasis added). I have elsewhere traced my theory of fairness to the writings on the just price by Saint Thomas Aquinas. Sidak, What Makes FRAND Fair?, supra Footnote note 35, at 701–02, 710–21.

50 869 F. Supp. 2d 901, 912 (N.D. Ill. 2012), rev’d in part on other grounds, 757 F.3d 1286 (Fed. Cir. 2014). Judge Marsha Berzon previously wrote for the Ninth Circuit that a FRAND obligation was “legally equivalent” to a RAND obligation. Microsoft Corp. v. Motorola, Inc., 696 F.3d 872, 877 n.2 (9th Cir. 2012).

51 Sidak, Fair and Unfair Discrimination in Royalties for Standard-Essential Patents Encumbered by a FRAND or RAND Commitment, supra Footnote note 41, at 308.

52 Footnote Id. at 308–11.

53 Robert H. Frank, Passions within Reason: The Strategic Role of the Emotions 165 (1988) (emphasis in original).

54 Footnote Id. at 167 (emphasis suppressed).

55 Frank argues that in “the self-interest model,” which he identifies with Judge Posner,

the division of the surplus simply plays no role in determining whether a transaction will take place. It will occur provided each party gets some positive share of the surplus, no matter how small. When Posner says fairness “has no content,” this feature of the traditional model must be at least in part what he has in mind. Yet, as we will presently see, concerns about fairness repeatedly cause people to reject transactions with positive surplus.

Footnote Id. (attributing Judge Posner’s quotation to Paul Barrett, Influential Ideas: A Movement Called “Law and Economics” Sways Legal Circles, Wall St. J. 1, 16 (Aug. 4, 1986). Frank argues that Judge “Posner and other rationalists would hardly deny that people say they care about fairness[,] [b]ut hardheaded economists treat such statements as mere verbiage, devoid of any power to predict behavior.” Id. (emphasis in original).

56 J. Gregory Sidak & David J. Teece, Dynamic Competition in Antitrust Law, 5 J. Competition L. & Econ. 581, 602 (2009) (“Dynamic competition is powered by the creation and commercialization of new products, new processes, and new business models. As [Joseph] Schumpeter said, competition fueled by the introduction of new products and processes is the more powerful form of competition: ‘competition from the new commodity, the new technology, the new source of supply, the new type of organization – competition which commands a decisive cost or quality advantage and which strikes not at the margins of the profits and the output of existing firms, but at their foundations and their very lives.’ Advocates of strong competition policy must surely favor dynamic competition, for static competition is anemic in comparison.”) (quoting Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy 8 (1942)).

57 Richard H. Thaler, Anomalies: The Ultimatum Game, 2 J. Econ. Persp. 195 (1988).

58 J. Gregory Sidak, The Meaning of FRAND, Part I: Royalties, 9 J. Competition L. & Econ. 931, 1047 (2013). In 2013, I said that the Ultimatum Game sheds light on the reasonableness of an offer as well. Id. I no longer believe that proposition to be correct. I have concluded instead that the reasonableness component of the FRAND (or RAND) obligation concerns the identification of the size of the surplus, not the question of how the parties will find it mutually acceptable to divide the surplus. Sidak, What Makes FRAND Fair?, supra Footnote note 35, at 708 n.30.

59 Ernst Fehr & Simon Gächter, Fairness and Retaliation: The Economics of Reciprocity Source, 14 J. Econ. Persp. 159, 161 (2000) (citing Werner Güth, Rolf Schmittberger, & Bernd Schwarze, An Experimental Analysis of Ultimatum Bargaining, 3 J. Econ. Behavior & Org. 367 (1982); Colin Camerer & Richard Thaler, Anomalies: Ultimatums, Dictators and Manners, 9 J. Econ. Persp. 209 (1995); Alvin Roth, Bargaining Experiments, in 1 The Handbook of Experimental Economics 253 (Alvin E. Roth & John H. Kagel eds., 1995)). A 29–71 split of the surplus would correspond to a value of R equal to 0.41.

60 Frank, Passions within Reason, supra Footnote note 53, at 165. For a (now somewhat dated) survey of that literature, see James Konow, Which Is the Fairest One of All? A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories, 41 J. Econ. Literature 1188 (2003). “Justice arguments are now widely invoked to improve theoretical and empirical analysis in nearly every field of economics,” wrote Konow in 2003, a development that “contrasts with the traditional belief of many economists that justice is chimerical or amorphous.” Id. at 1188. “Despite the emerging consensus in economics over the relevance of fairness, though, no … agreement yet exists among economists or, for that matter, among psychologists, political scientists, sociologists, or philosophers, about the proper theory of justice.” Id. at 1189. Ernst Fehr & Klaus M. Schmidt, A Theory of Fairness, Competition and Cooperation, 114 Q.J. Econ. 817 (1999). Earlier surveys on the economics of fairness appear in Edward Zajac’s two books. Edward E. Zajac, Political Economy of Fairness (1995); Edward E. Zajac, Fairness or Efficiency: An Introduction to Public Utility Pricing (1978).

61 Georgia-Pacific Corp. v. U.S. Plywood Corp., 318 F. Supp. 1116, 1120 (S.D.N.Y. 1970), modified and aff’d, 446 F.2d 295 (2d Cir. 1971).

62 One large-scale experiment of the Ultimatum Game found support for the prediction that “informed, knowledgeable respondents may react to small ultimatum offers by perceiving them as unfair, feeling anger, and acting spitefully.” Madan M. Pillutla & J. Keith Murnighan, Unfairness, Anger, and Spite: Emotional Rejections of Ultimatum Offers, 68 Org. Behav. & Human Decision Processes 208, 208 (1996). Silicon Valley has had its titans who have expressed anger and spite toward their commercial adversaries. See, for example, Walter Isaacson, Steve Jobs (2011). Relatedly, in the business context, negotiators might be adverse to an “unfair” (that is, extremely skewed) split of the surplus based on the purely unemotional reason that it would set an unfavorable precedent for future negotiations or (in the event of information leakage) concurrent negotiations with other parties. The lopsided division of surplus might be used as comparable royalty evidence in future litigations.

63 Duncan K. Foley, Resource Allocation and the Public Sector, 7 Yale Econ. Essays 45 (1967).

64 Hal Varian wrote: “Consider the problem of dividing a fixed amount of goods among a fixed number of agents. If, in a given allocation, agent i prefers the bundle of agent j to his own, we will say i envies j. If there are no envious agents at allocation x, we will say x is equitable. If x is both pareto efficient and equitable, we will say x is fair.” Hal R. Varian, Equity, Envy, and Efficiency, 9 J. Econ. Theory 63, 63 (1974) (emphasis in original); Konow, supra Footnote note 60, at 1204 (“The theory of fairness with the purest economic pedigree, and the usual definition of equity in welfare economics, is the absence of envy criterion.”). But see id. at 1205 (“Absence of envy is questionable not only as a description of justice but also of what is meant by envy in common parlance: it seems quite possible that I would like to have another person’s allocation, but that I do not experience the resentful feeling about his advantage that the word envy typically connotes.”).

65 William J. Baumol, Superfairness: Applications and Theory 15 (1986).

66 Matthew Rabin, Incorporating Fairness into Game Theory and Economics, 83 Am. Econ. Rev. 1281, 1292 (1993).

69 Footnote Id. at 1293.

70 Footnote Id. (citing Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch, & Richard H. Thaler, Fairness as a Constraint on Profit Seeking: Entitlements in the Market, 76 Am. Econ. Rev. 728 (1986); Daniel Kahneman, Jack L. Knetsch, & Richard H. Thaler, Fairness and the Assumptions of Economics, 59 J. Bus. S285 (1986)).

71 A negotiation might reach an impasse because of “the tendency for parties to arrive at judgments that reflect a self-serving bias – to conflate what is fair with what benefits oneself.” Linda Babcock & George Loewenstein, Explaining Bargaining Impasse: The Role of Self-Serving Biases, 11 J. Econ. Persp. 109, 110 (1997). “Such self-serving assessments of fairness,” Babcock and Loewenstein warn, “can impede negotiations and promote impasse in at least three ways.” Id. The first way that they describe actually results from the incorrect identification of the bargaining range owing to a false understanding of one’s true outside option: “if negotiators estimate the value of the alternatives to negotiated settlements in self‑serving ways, this could rule out any chance of settlement by eliminating the contract zone (the set of agreements that both sides prefer to their reservation values).” Id. In contrast, the next two ways concern biases affecting the division of a positive surplus whose size is commonly understood:

Second, if disputants believe that their notion of fairness is impartial and shared by both sides, then they will interpret the other party’s aggressive bargaining not as an attempt to get what they perceive of as fair, but as a cynical and exploitative attempt to gain an unfair strategic advantage. Research in psychology and economics has shown that bargainers care not only about what the other party offers, but also about the other party’s motives. Third, negotiators are strongly averse to settling even slightly below the point they view as fair. If disputants are willing to make economic sacrifices to avoid a settlement perceived as unfair and their ideas of fairness are biased in directions that favor themselves, then bargainers who are “only trying to get what is fair” may not be able to settle their dispute.

Footnote Id. (citation omitted).

72 Kahneman et al., Fairness as a Constraint on Profit Seeking: Entitlements in the Market, supra Footnote note 70, at 728.

73 Footnote Id. at 728–29.

74 J. Gregory Sidak, The Antitrust Division’s Devaluation of Standard-Essential Patents, 104 Geo. L. J. Online 48 (2015); J. Gregory Sidak, Testing for Bias to Suppress Royalties for Standard-Essential Patents, 1 Criterion J. Innovation 301 (2016).

75 John F. Nash, Jr., The Bargaining Problem, 18 Econometrica 155 (1950). In his 1950 article, John Nash proposed a solution to what he called the “bargaining situation” – an economic game in which two parties “have the opportunity to collaborate for mutual benefit in more than one way.” Id. at 155. A solution to that game maximizes “the amount of satisfaction each [party] should expect to get from the situation.” Id. According to Nash’s model, an increase in the value of a party’s position absent an agreement improves the party’s bargaining position and therefore results in an improvement in that party’s value of the bargain.

Before deriving his solution, Nash made certain assumptions about the game’s participants: that each bargaining party is “highly rational,” “can accurately compare [its] desires for various things,” is “equal [to the other] in bargaining skill,” “has full knowledge of the tastes and preferences of the other,” and “wishes to maximize the utility to [itself] of the ultimate bargain.” Id. at 155, 159. Nash further assumed the independence of irrelevant alternatives – that is, if a bargainer faces a choice between A and B and prefers A to B, then that bargainer must also prefer A to B if faced with a choice between A, B, and C. Id. at 156. In 1953, Nash extended his 1950 article in a manner that “tells the players what threats they should use in negotiating.” John Nash, Two-Person Cooperative Games, 21 Econometrica 128, 130 (1953). He summarized: “Supposing A and B to be rational beings, it is essential for the success of the threat that A be compelled to carry out his threat T if B fails to comply. Otherwise it will have little meaning.” Id. (emphasis in original).

American courts have been skeptical of the real-world applicability of the Nash bargaining solution as expert economic testimony and thus bristle at its invocation as a basis for predicting a 50–50 division of surplus in a bilateral negotiation. As the Federal Circuit explained in the context of measuring reasonable royalty damages for patent infringement, “[t]he Nash [bargaining] theorem arrives at a result that follows from a certain set of premises” but “itself asserts nothing” about the real-world reliability of those premises. VirnetX, Inc. v. Cisco Sys., Inc., 767 F.3d 1308, 1332 (Fed. Cir. 2014) (analyzing Nash, The Bargaining Problem, supra Footnote note 75).

76 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, supra Footnote note 47, at 74; Ken Binmore, Game Theory and the Social Contract: Just Playing 382–83 (1998); H. Peyton Young, Equity in Theory and Practice 135 (1994); H. Peyton Young, Dividing the Indivisible, 38 Am. Behavioral Scientist 904, 911–12 (1995); Hugo Steinhaus, The Problem of Fair Division, 16 Econometrica 101 (1948).

77 Young, Equity in Theory and Practice, supra Footnote note 76, at 135.

78 Pindyck & Rubinfeld, supra Footnote note 45, at 562; Robert Gibbons, Game Theory for Applied Economists 68–71 (1992).

79 Ariel Rubinstein, Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model, 50 Econometrica 97 (1982).

Figure 0

Table 3.1. New 5G technologies and capabilities

Figure 1

Table 3.2. Potential beneficiary suppliers

Figure 2

Figure 3.1. RAN market revenue by OEM

Source: Base Station Market Poised for Strong Year Thanks to 5G and China According to Omdia, Microwave J. (Dec. 7, 2020)
Figure 3

Figure 3.2. Comparison of RAN architecture options

Figure 4

Table 3.3. Firms that potentially can participate as decentralized providers

Figure 5

Figure 3.3. Value and distribution in the smartphone value chain

Figure 6

Figure 3.4. Monopoly licensor sets the royalty rate

Figure 7

Figure 3.5. Patents and Ricardian rents

Figure 8

Figure 3.6. Value and distribution in the smartphone value chain with a single Monopoly Patent Holder (2016)

Figure 9

Figure 3.7. Patent royalties as percentage of the value of mobile (smart and feature) phones shipped (2007–2016)

Figure 10

Figure 3.8. WW mobile subscriptions by cellular generation

Source: Ericsson Mobility Visualizer, Sept. 16, 2023
Figure 11

Table 3.4. Leading cellular SEP licensing businesses (2015–2022)

Sources: IDC, Mobile Phone, Tablet, and Wearables, 2015–2022; Ericsson, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Interdigital, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Nokia, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Qualcomm, Investor Relations materials, 2015–2022; Qualcomm QTL Licensee Search; CNBC, “Huawei to start charging royalties to smartphone makers using its patented 5G tech,” Arjun Kharpal, Mar. 16, 2021, “Huawei announces royalty rates for its patent license programs,” Huawei, July 13, 2023
Figure 12

Table 3.5. Comparison of 5G and substitutes, alternatives, and complementsa

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×