Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xm8r8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-04T20:12:13.610Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Diversion to Treatment when Treatment is Scarce: Bioethical Implications of the U.S. Resource Gap for Criminal Diversion Programs

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 May 2024

Deniz Aritürk
Affiliation:
YALE UNIVERSITY, NEW HAVEN, CONNECTICUT, USA
Michele M. Easter
Affiliation:
DUKE UNIVERSITY, DURHAM, NORTH CAROLINA, USA.
Jeffrey W. Swanson
Affiliation:
DUKE UNIVERSITY, DURHAM, NORTH CAROLINA, USA.
Marvin S. Swartz
Affiliation:
DUKE UNIVERSITY, DURHAM, NORTH CAROLINA, USA.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Précis

Despite significant scholarship, research, and funding dedicated to implementing criminal diversion programs over the past two decades, persons with serious mental illness and substance use disorders remain substantially overrepresented in United States jails and prisons. Why are so many U.S. adults with behavioral health problems incarcerated instead of receiving treatment and other support to recover in the community? In this paper, we explore this persistent problem within the context of “relentless unmet need” in U.S. behavioral health (Alegría et al., 2021).

Type
Independent Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of American Society of Law, Medicine & Ethics

Despite significant scholarship, research, and funding dedicated to implementing criminal diversion programs, persons with serious behavioral health conditions, including substance use disorders (SUD) and serious mental illnesses (SMI), remain substantially overrepresented in United States jails and prisons. An estimated 58% of adults in state prisons and 63% of those sentenced to jail have an SUD, compared to about 5% of the general adult population.Reference Bronson, Zimmer and Berzofsky1 About 14% of adults in prison and 26% of those in jail meet criteria for “serious psychological distress,” compared to about 5% in the general population.2 An estimated 75% of those in state prison and jail who had any recent mental health problem also have SUD.Reference James and Glaze3 Why are so many U.S. adults with behavioral health problems incarcerated instead of receiving treatment and other support to recover in the community? In this paper, we explore this persistent problem within the broader context of “relentless unmet need” in U.S. behavioral health.Reference Alegría4 We use a common bioethics frameworkReference Beauchamp and Childress5 to examine concerns that this unmet need raises for diversion-to-treatment programs, which are designed to help justice-involved adults with behavioral health conditions access appropriate resources in the community as an alternative to incarceration. We consider whether diversion programs that are implemented in resource-constrained service environments can fulfill their ambitious promise to reduce justice involvement, improve clinical outcomes, promote self-determination, and enhance overall quality of life for their target populations. What are the implications for diversion programs if persistent resource gaps make it unlikely that they will achieve these worthy goals for a significant proportion of participants?

The Problem: Unavailable, Inappropriate, and Inaccessible Resources

In 2022, merely 13.1 million out of an estimated 54.6 million people in the U.S. aged 12 or older who needed substance use disorder (SUD) treatment received it, and about half of the estimated 15.4 million U.S. adults with serious mental illness (SMI) perceived an unmet need for mental health services.6 Marginalized communities disproportionately bear the burden of this unmet need: among adults with any substance use or mental health disorder, those who are poor, uninsured, or persons of color are consistently less likely to receive behavioral health services.Reference Haeny7

A deep resource gap in treatment and human services is the backdrop for this unmet need. In many communities, treatment and related service options are practically nonexistent. For example, some prescribers decline to offer buprenorphine, making this key SUD treatment resource unavailable. In other cases, available treatment is inappropriate and may cause more harm than good. Many treatment options are not evidence-based, patient-centered, or culturally sensitive. Individuals who need social support, housing, or help identifying their drug use triggers may instead be forced into abstinence-based treatment programs because of a limited resource landscape or the constraints of court-sanctioned programs. Finally, available and desired treatment options may remain inaccessible for community members who lack the time or resources to travel to a clinic, pay for treatment, or follow intensive and long-term requirements. Without steady income, housing, childcare, transportation, or other key resources, engagement in treatment may be nearly impossible. We will refer to these three barriers — unavailable, inappropriate, and inaccessible resources — collectively as the “resource problem.” The “resource problem” thus encompasses any gap in the supply of accessible, evidence-based treatment, as well as other resource gaps that prevent people from effectively participating in a treatment program. The underlying causes of the resource problem and their ethical implications are not within the scope of this analysis, but we note that specific public policies (e.g., drug control policies that shape access to methadone) and contextual factors (e.g., lack of training for clinical professionals working within the criminal legal system, healthcare workforce shortages (particularly in rural areas), and limited political will to fund behavioral services) likely contribute to these gaps.

The resource gap may help explain the apparent lack of willingness among people with SUD to pursue treatment. In 2022, a national survey estimated that 96 percent of individuals with SUD who did not receive treatment at any specialty facility perceived no need for such treatment.8 In many cases, lack of perceived need may reflect a person’s rational decision not to engage with treatment that is stigmatizing, unregulated, unproven (e.g., abstinence-based approaches for opioid use disorder (OUD)), or overly burdensome (e.g., mandatory daily in-person appearances at methadone clinics). Inadequate knowledge of treatment options and low public awareness and recognition of problematic substance useReference Hasin and Grant9 likely also play a role. Moreover, some people with SUD may not be ready to enter treatment because their other needs, such as housing, are not met.Reference Blank Wilson10

For these reasons, addressing the resource gap requires responsiveness to individuals’ complex web of needs. Programs that “meet people where they are” (rather than, for instance, requiring abstinence) and address their basic needs for shelter, food, and medical and mental health care can help those who are not yet ready or able to attend treatment.Reference Padgett11 Building a more diverse behavioral healthcare workforce can help provide culturally-sensitive services, address stigmatizing attitudes towards mental illness and addiction, and ensure that treatment resources appropriately address patients’ needs.12 Together, such interventions could encourage participation and help alleviate the racial and socioeconomic disparities in addiction treatment completion.Reference Saloner and Lê Cook13

In the context of criminal diversion, the resource problem implicates not only the health but also the liberty and safety of individuals. Criminal diversion programs offer defendants alternatives to traditional criminal prosecution, often with the goal of avoiding a criminal record and its many collateral consequences. Many diversion programs target individuals with SUD or SMI by incorporating treatment and other resources to prevent unnecessary justice involvement.14 Examples include pre-arrest diversion such as Law Enforcement Assisted Diversion (LEAD), in which a police officer links individuals to case management instead of arresting them;Reference Collins, Lonczak and Clifasefi15 drug treatment court, in which a judge mandates participation in supervised treatment instead of conviction or incarceration; and post-conviction behavioral health probation, in which a person who has pleaded guilty to an offense receives a probation sentence that may have specific conditions, such as court-ordered drug testing or therapy.Reference Skeem, Manchak and Montoya16

One important distinction is between programs that involve supervision by the criminal legal system, such as drug court and mental health probation, and those that do not, such as LEAD. Most programs in the former category, which we call supervised diversion, require the defendant to plead guilty, although some, like drug courts in certain jurisdictions, allow participants to avoid a criminal record if they successfully complete program requirements. Programs in the latter category, which we call community-based diversion, connect individuals to appropriate treatment, social, or human services without imposing requirements or sanctions through the criminal legal system. As we will discuss, the presence of criminal supervision often raises distinct ethical issues for diversion programs.

Diversion programs focused on behavioral health, which are the topic of this paper, aim to reduce criminal justice contact by intervening at various points or “intercepts” along the continuum of justice involvement, as depicted in the Sequential Intercept Model (SIM).17 The original model identifies five intercepts, each one of which presents an opportunity for diversion to treatment: law enforcement and emergency services; initial hearings and initial detention; jails and courts; reentry from jails, prisons, and forensic hospitals; community corrections and community support services.

The resource problem has already been recognized as a roadblock to diversion. Researchers evaluating a variety of diversion programs have identified the resource problem as a factor limiting programs’ effectiveness, and advocates have posed the question, “diversion to what?” Here, we examine the bioethical implications of this longstanding problem for diversion programs and those who participate in them.

A key principle of the SIM is that diversion should occur as early as possible, and ideally prevent justice involvement altogether. An “accessible, comprehensive, effective” behavioral health treatment system would serve as the “ultimate intercept” by preventing the criminalization of behavioral health disorders in the first place.18 In theory, this would mean that people with these disorders would never become involved with the justice system as an indirect consequence of untreated SUD or SMI (these individuals might nonetheless become involved with the justice system as a result of individual or social risk factors, just like the broader population; the ultimate intercept does not promise to prevent all justice involvement). Recently, scholars have incorporated this “ultimate intercept” into the SIM as “Intercept 0.” Intercept 0 includes the full range of emergency services that respond to behavioral health crises, such as mobile crisis outreach teams, crisis respite services, and first responders,Reference Abreu19 as well as the entire integrated community behavioral health system.Reference Bonfine, Blank Wilson and Munetz20 Under this conception, substance use, mental health, primary medical, criminogenic, and social needs of individuals would be “addressed in a coordinated and timely manner to achieve the desired goals of improved health, prevention of institutionalization (hospitalization and incarceration), and overall recovery.”21 An integrated community behavioral health system is essential to the ethical planning and operation of diversion programs. Thus, we include Intercept 0 in our analysis.

The resource problem has already been recognized as a roadblock to diversion. Researchers evaluating a variety of diversion programs have identified the resource problem as a factor limiting programs’ effectiveness,Reference Scott22 and advocates have posed the question, “diversion to what?”23 Here, we examine the bioethical implications of this longstanding problem for diversion programs and those who participate in them.

Analytical Framework: The Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics

We explore the resource problem through a bioethics framework for three reasons: First, the principles of non-maleficence, beneficence, autonomy, and justice reflect a shared set of values among clinicians and are directly related to the treatment of behavioral health patients. Diversion efforts are healthcare efforts, not only because they help direct people to treatment, but also because the avoidance of justice involvement is a health-promoting measure.Reference Cloud, Parsons and Delany-Brumsey24

Second, the principles of bioethics were formulated to protect patients and research participants from abuse due to the mismatch of power and information between them and researchers and clinicians.25 Individuals considering whether to enter diversion programs are in a particularly vulnerable position not only because of the sanctions and other liberty restrictions that may consequently be imposed on them, but also because justice-involved individuals are disproportionately from socially marginalized communities.Reference Kurlychek and Johnson26

Third, and finally, bioethics must be responsive to the social and political context in which it operates. The field has been criticized for failing to address the effects of racism and other structural inequities on clinical and research outcomes. Scholars have argued that bioethics can and should contribute to addressing racismReference Danis, Wilson and White27 and have conceptualized a “bioethics of the oppressed.”Reference Guta, Voronka and Gagnon28 Here, we apply this conceptual framework to behavioral health diversion programs, which operate against significant racial and economic disparities that shape the U.S. criminal legal system.Reference Alexander29 While we focus on a systemic resource problem, our analysis largely addresses how that problem impacts individual patients’ experiences in diversion. Other ethical frameworks, while beyond the scope of this commentary, could provide valuable insight to this issue as well.

In the next four sections, we outline how each bioethical principle relates to criminal diversion, and the series of complications created by the lack of an accessible, comprehensive network of evidence-based and person-centered treatment, support programs, and human services. We focus on decision-making for individuals who do not pose an imminent threat of danger to themselves or others, as safety considerations may be overriding in other cases. Crucially, while we address only the ethical challenges raised by the resource gap, we acknowledge that other, serious ethical issues implicate certain supervised diversion programs like drug courts (for instance, public hearings can compromise private medical information, program-wide bans on effective and needed forms of medication can compromise participant wellbeing, and the therapeutic jurisprudence philosophy underlying drug courts is inherently coercive and perhaps irreconcilable with the principle of autonomy).Reference Csete30 While we touch on how these issues relate to the resource problem, they are not our focus and would require internal reforms to those diversion programs rather than external reforms aimed at the resource gap. In sum, responding to the issues we outline in this commentary will be necessary yet not sufficient for many diversion programs to align their practices with the principles of bioethics.

1. Autonomy

The principle of autonomy requires respecting the rights of patients to make their own treatment decisions, including by providing sufficient information to enable reasoned and informed choices.31 Autonomy is particularly implicated in the context of diversion from incarceration, a near-complete loss of autonomy. However, diversion programs often involve limitations on autonomy as well. For example, participants in prosecutor-led diversion, treatment court, and mental health-related probation are supervised by a prosecutor, judge, or probation officer. Moreover, participants can face sanctions including fees, a criminal record, or incarceration if they do not comply with program requirements. As we describe in the introduction, we refer to this family of programs as “supervised diversion,” which we differentiate from “community-based diversion.” The latter allows health providers and patients to chart out a treatment plan without criminal sanctions, threats, or supervision.

Ideally, diversion programs should avoid all unnecessary restrictions of autonomy (i.e., those that are not warranted by public or individual safety concerns) in both the criminal and clinical setting. The resource problem can be a barrier to this ideal if treatment is more easily accessible to people enrolled in a diversion program. We discuss the implications of this issue in the context of coercion and patient-centered care.

Autonomy requires that individuals participate in treatment voluntarily, typically by providing informed consent. A reasoned and informed choice to participate entails “more than a simple declaration by the defendant.”32 It requires briefing people on the potential positive and negative consequences of and alternatives to participation in the program. It also requires providing special care for individuals who have difficulty understanding the premises of diversion, including the voluntariness of the offer or the inherent lack of guarantee of success of the treatment.

Before entering a diversion program, participants are typically presented with a choice between diversion and continuing along the standard criminal prosecution pathway. These choices may be treatment court rather than jail time or conviction; community services under probation supervision rather than jail time; referral to community services rather than arrest. Transfer to a diversion program in some instances may be the only opportunity for immediate release from jail to the community. In each of these instances, individuals are “free” to refuse diversion and to choose, for instance, to spend six months in jail rather than 18 months in a court-supervised treatment program or on probation. However, these choices come under the pressure of criminal sanctions and are notably different from the choices patients typically make when giving informed consent.

Presenting criminal sanctions as the alternative to treatment unavoidably adds a degree of coercion to individuals’ decision to participate in diversion, making the decision less and less “free” as the criminal alternative becomes more and more restrictive. Treatment programs that do not threaten criminal consequences or supervision as the consequence of nonparticipation, such as those operating at Intercept 0 prior to arrest or conviction, can avoid the coercive aspect inherent in supervised diversion programs. Such community-based programs are thus preferable for promoting patient autonomy, unless a clear public safety concern warrants greater supervision or confinement.

However, coercion may become unavoidable under conditions of resource scarcity, where diversion offers the only chance for treatment. For people who live in resource-constrained areas or are uninsured, treatment may only be available through a supervised diversion program. Well-meaning justice professionals may coerce people into diversion programs to secure treatment, just as well-meaning health providers may involuntarily commit a psychiatric patient because that is the only way to secure an inpatient bed (which is arguably an unconstitutional abridgement of rightsReference Lawrence Fitch and Swanson33). In some instances, such as arrests for trespassing, overnight camping, panhandling, and other laws that essentially criminalize homelessness, supervised diversion may impose greater restrictions on autonomy than the criminal charges would warrant.

Such coercive interventions to enroll participants in diversion, no matter how well-intentioned, require a “strong justification.”34 In the context of involuntary commitment, some have argued that “there may be no ethical case” for commitment if “the problem is merely one of addressing removable barriers to treatment—that is, providing access to services that the person would be willing and able to accept voluntarily, if available.” Similarly, if supervised diversion functions solely as a means of addressing removable barriers to treatment or other human services for individuals who are not a threat to themselves or others, there will be no ethical case for its use over community-based alternatives.

In addition to avoiding unjustified instances of coercion, diversion programs can promote autonomy through patient-centered care that responds to the complex needs, goals, and preferences of patients related to co-occurring disorders; trauma history; gender, race, and sexual identity; social support; basic needs; and more. Ideally, this would mean allowing individuals with SUD to choose the services that they need to recover, including by pursuing social and mental health supports that help them identify and avoid triggers, rather than being forced into a dichotomy between abstinence-based treatment and criminal sanctions. The experience of autonomy in patient-centered care is not only ethically desirable but also likely to improve treatment outcomes by allowing patients to feel empowered and invested in their recovery.

Unfortunately, choice of care specifically and patient-centered care generally are difficult to achieve in the context of mandated treatment, a common component of supervised diversion programs. People who have been diverted are often seen as “beggars, not choosers;” this attitude prevents clear-eyed consideration of whether treatment requirements actually meet participants’ needs. For example, for many individuals with SUD, recovery may require only social support and counseling to help identify triggers of drug use, rather than a stay at an inpatient residential facility. For those with OUD, medications are often a crucial component of recovery. However, some forms of medication-assisted treatment (MAT) are barred by supervised diversion programs that require abstinence and equate MAT with illegal drugs, often due to misinformation on the part of diversion program administrators.35 Some drug courts allow one form of MAT—naltrexone—because it is an opioid antagonist and therefore more in line with an abstinence philosophy. However, patients and their doctors might prefer an alternative type of MAT, such as buprenorphine, because it is less expensive, easier to start because it does not require detoxification,Reference Lee36 and less likely to lead to overdose.Reference Ajazi37 It is not only ethical but also feasible and more effective for supervised diversion programs to implement a person-centered approach that includes any form of MAT that is medically indicated. Indeed, practitioners have outlined specific strategies to help programs make the transition.Reference Garcia and Lucas38

Patient-centered care and autonomy might be compromised by other program components too, especially in supervised diversion. For example, some judges require women to participate in anger management classes as a condition of program completion. In such programs, women with trauma histories of male-perpetrated violent victimization, which make up the majority of justice-involved women,Reference Moloney, van den Bergh and Moller39 can be mandated to attend a group with men.Reference Robertson40 Given a free choice, a woman in this situation might reasonably reject participating in group therapy with men, and a trauma-informed clinician would likely not recommend it.

The above examples illustrate how the resource problem, in addition to being an external barrier to ethical program implementation, can itself be exacerbated by internal program policies. Diversion participants may not have access to MAT if affordable and appropriate options are not available in their rural setting.Reference Joudrey41 Others might be denied access to available treatment because program administrators disallow it. In the former scenario, diversion programs suffer the consequences of longstanding and vast resource problems in the American behavioral health infrastructure. In the latter, diversion participants suffer the consequences of program policies that insufficiently accommodate participants’ autonomy. For women who are mandated to participate in mixed-gender anger management, finite resources and program requirements combine to constrain treatment options. While the necessary policy solutions will vary widely in each case, patient-centered care becomes elusive in all as individuals get forced to meet requirements that fail to meet their needs and even make things worse.

Under conditions of resource abundance and scarcity alike, community-based diversion programs that are not supervised by criminal legal system actors are best positioned to promote participant autonomy, both by ensuring that the decision to participate is not coerced by the threat of criminal sanctions and by allowing participants to access the resources that best align with their needs and goals. Supervised programs are appropriate only for individuals who pose a significant threat to public safety. Realistically, when community-based programs are unavailable or inaccessible, supervision is likely to expand to include individuals who do not pose such a threat, leading to restrictions of autonomy that are difficult to justify.

Inappropriate treatment poses a greater risk of harm in programs that mandate treatment. When programs require compliance with treatment that turns out to be unavailable, inappropriate, or inaccessible, participants can be left to suffer not only the consequences of untreated SUD and SMI but also the financial, physical, and mental burdens of attempting to meet program requirements and the adverse consequences of failing to do so. Participants may consequently suffer long-lasting health effects if, due to feelings of alienation and discouragement, they become less likely to pursue treatment in the future.

2. Non-Maleficence

The principle of non-maleficence states that health professionals should avoid causing harm in treatment.42 In criminal diversion, unlike in typical clinical settings, this duty is two-fold: Diversion programs, operating at the intersection of the criminal legal and health systems, must avoid causing harms through either system.

Although diversion programs are intended to prevent the many harms related to contact with the criminal legal system,Reference Lett43 they may inadvertently increase criminal involvement in the context of the resource gap. This can happen in at least two ways.

First, diversion programs may contribute to net-widening, which refers to the expansion of the “criminal net” via the surveillance, control, and punishment of a broader group of people.44 Law enforcement officers and prosecutors have significant discretion, and some may choose to arrest or prosecute individuals for whom they believe diversion offers the best or only access to treatment and social resources. When resources are scarce, criminal involvement can become the first point of access to care, particularly for uninsured, unhoused, and otherwise marginalized individuals who have no meaningful alternative.

Second, diversion programs might increase criminal contact among their participants. Many supervised diversion programs involve requirements of successful completion and/or sanctions for noncompliance. Some of these requirements and sanctions cause the very harms that diversion seeks to avoid, such as burdensome court fines, frequent interactions with criminal legal officials, and even jail time. Non-adherent drug court participants may receive longer periods of incarceration than they would have through traditional sentencing.Reference Sevigny, Fuleihan and Ferdik45 Mental health probation participants without sufficient time or money to meet program requirements may receive technical violations and return to jail or prison.Reference Van Deinse46

Non-maleficence requires that diversion programs avoid causing harm, in particular the kinds of adverse health effects that often result from standard criminal prosecution and incarceration. Restrictive conditions might become necessary if an individual poses a significant public safety risk. In all other cases, programs must avoid conditions and sanctions that mimic the very harms diversion is meant to prevent (e.g., jail days as a program response to relapse47).

The second set of potential harms that criminal diversion must seek to avoid relates to contact (or lack thereof) with the healthcare system. Diversion might harm participants’ health by diverting them to treatment that is unavailable, inaccessible, or inappropriate, without enabling access to supports required to meaningfully participate, and imposing consequences if the person does not succeed. Individuals may be unable to complete a diversion program because there are no affordable or appropriate resources in their community, or because they are unable to follow treatment due to other problems like being unhoused. Alternatively, resources that do not appropriately address individuals’ needs might delay recovery or even cause harm, such as the aforementioned examples of abstinence requirements for individuals with OUD 48 and mandatory mixed-gender anger management classes for women with sexual trauma histories.49 As mentioned, diversion programs sometimes mandate inappropriate treatments even when better alternatives are available due to the biases or lack of clinical expertise among judges or diversion program staff.

Inappropriate treatment poses a greater risk of harm in programs that mandate treatment. When programs require compliance with treatment that turns out to be unavailable, inappropriate, or inaccessible, participants can be left to suffer not only the consequences of untreated SUD and SMI but also the financial, physical, and mental burdens of attempting to meet program requirements and the adverse consequences of failing to do so. Participants may consequently suffer long-lasting health effects if, due to feelings of alienation and discouragement, they become less likely to pursue treatment in the future.

3. Beneficence

The principle of beneficence states that treatment must aim to maximize possible benefits and minimize possible harms.50 Diversion programs can do this by minimizing contact with the criminal legal system and by maximizing positive treatment outcomes — in other words, by using the least intrusive intervention that has a chance of success.

The goal of providing a benefit while removing or minimizing potential harms, as required by the principle of beneficence, is subtly different than the goal of simply “doing no harm,” as required by non-maleficence. To promote beneficence, diversion programs ideally must facilitate participants’ access to treatment and human services that improve their wellbeing — in ways that are meaningful to them — in part by avoiding the harms of criminal prosecution, but also by minimizing any adverse consequences of the treatment program itself. In this way, beneficence demands a more ambitious and imaginative understanding of what diversion can and ought to be.

Following the guidepost of the “least intrusive intervention that has a chance of success,” justice officials can employ their considerable discretionary powers to help people avoid criminal sanctions as much as possible. Prosecutors can drop the charges against individuals arrested for low-level crimes and refer them to voluntary treatment, rather than proceeding with prosecution or imposing court-supervised programs.51 Similarly, judges can decide to dismiss cases, and police officers can choose not to arrest individuals in the first place. If supervision is necessary for public safety reasons, prosecutors and judges can select the least demanding requirements possible, working, for instance, to prioritize connections to treatment and human services over frequent check-ins with court personnel. Doing so would help maximize benefits for individuals by sparing them the harms of criminal supervision and potentially increasing their engagement with treatment in the absence of looming criminal or civil sanctions; participants might feel more comfortable with honest disclosure of their symptoms and struggles in a therapeutic context where “failure” in treatment will not be met with sanctions as severe as jail time or loss of child custody. Discretion used in this way can minimize the potential harms of diversion. Of course, for such discretion to be effective, services meeting the needs of individuals need to be available in the community, outside of supervised diversion settings.

Similarly, the principle of maximizing potential benefits requires not only that programs offer a better alternative to traditional criminal prosecution, but also that they maximize treatment outcomes to the extent possible. To do so, programs would ideally offer a range of evidence-based, person-centered, culturally sensitive treatments that address participants’ various needs and help them achieve long-term recovery. These might include trauma-informed counseling, appropriate medications, assertive community treatment (if intensive team-based case management services are warranted), treatment for co-occurring disorders, individual psychotherapy, harm reduction, and program features to meet social and economic needs like housing and transportation.

Including knowledgeable and enlightened clinicians in the design of diversion programs could help to align treatment philosophy and policies with the most effective and evidence-based treatment approaches, modalities, and interventions to promote patient-centered recovery. Thoroughgoing involvement of behavioral healthcare professionals in diversion at the programmatic level could foster productive collaboration with system actors in the criminal legal realm — sheriffs, judges, prosecutors — who might otherwise structure and implement diversion programs with constraints to prioritize their concerns with risk management and crime control, deemphasizing the beneficence principle with respect to participants’ own life chances and wellbeing.Reference Blank Wilson and Draine52 Allowing behavioral health experts to make behavioral health-related decisions in diversion would promote health outcomes and may be welcomed by criminal justice professionals who lament having been “placed in the position of taking on the responsibility of justice-involved people with serious mental illness.”53 Yet, the resource problem poses a challenge to implementing this change. An acute national shortage of behavioral health providers is “compounded by the lack of racial, ethnic, and language diversity in the behavioral health workforce.”54 Efforts to improve diversion must thus include recruitment, training, and employment of behavioral health providers at higher rates, particularly those who are traditionally underrepresented in the workforce. They must also include internal reforms to diversion programs which so often exclude healthcare professionals from their staff and program design.

To promote beneficence, diversion must aim to maximize, rather than merely improve, benefits, and minimize, rather than merely reduce, harms. Programs that avoid criminal supervision whenever possible and that include, following the expertise of healthcare professionals, an integrated system of evidence-based behavioral health services alongside social and human services can be expected to maximize beneficence.

4. Justice

The principle of justice states that the benefits and risks of an intervention should be equitably distributed among the population.55 Each of the three principles we have addressed — autonomy, non-maleficence, and beneficence — implicate justice in the context of the resource problem. This is because the resource problem is a justice problem that disproportionately affects racially and economically marginalized individuals. Unsurprisingly, the resource problem is also a barrier to the equitable distribution of resources within diversion programs.

Ideally, diversion programs following the justice principle would help alleviate existing disparities in the criminal legal system. They would do so by reducing the overrepresentation of individuals with behavioral health conditions as well as those from racially and economically marginalized communities across all stages of criminal prosecution. Diversion programs would provide all participants equal access to treatment, regardless of insurance status or ability to pay, and address people’s unmet needs for housing, transportation, employment, etc., that prevent their access to treatment.

Unfortunately, justice remains elusive in many diversion programs. Black and Hispanic people are increasingly overrepresented at each level of criminal supervision, i.e. among arrestee, probation, and incarcerated populations.56 Yet, Black and Hispanic people are consistently underrepresented in diversion program participation and completion rates.Reference Marlowe, Hardin and Fox57 This reversal from over- to underrepresentation may be explained by factors like resource disparities between White participants and participants of color, shortage of culturally-sensitive programs, limited racial diversity in the behavioral health workforce, and racist perceptions of people of color as more dangerous and less appropriate candidates for diversion.Reference Bennett and Plaut58 The full extent of racial disparities in diversion and the factors driving them are difficult to gauge since many programs do not measure and report outcomes by race. This lack of data is another, significant barrier to racial justice in diversion.

Ironically, the severity of individuals’ behavioral health conditions can lead to disparities as well, especially when resources are limited. This is because individuals with milder symptoms may require fewer resources and thus be considered “easier” to divert. According to one recent study, individuals with SMI experience not only longer stays in jail but also lower rates of treatment engagement and enrollment in specialty courts as well as poorer diversion outcomes compared to individuals without SMI.Reference Kubiak59 Since diversion programs often measure their success by successful completion rates, program operators may be incentivized to enroll individuals who have less severe symptoms or more resources to help them complete program requirements, including individuals who may not have SMI or SUD. Under resource scarcity, diversion programs may leave out the very people they were designed for.60

Diversion programs can exacerbate economic disparities as well, shutting out participants who cannot afford participation fees, which can be as high as $5,000 for a single offense.Reference Dewan and Lehren61 Program and treatment fees create a “pay to play” system wherein diversion offers a way out of the criminal continuum solely for individuals with the ability to pay. Primary caregivers to children who cannot afford childcare, full-time employees who cannot afford to stop working, and individuals who are uninsured or otherwise unable to meet program requirements due to financial limitations are similarly denied the opportunity to exit the criminal continuum and receive the treatment and services that they need.

Individuals who face criminal conviction are often uninsured, underinsured, or indigent. When diversion programs disproportionately allow the advantaged to avoid or end contact with the criminal system while disproportionately leaving in the individuals who have been the most marginalized by it, the principle of justice remains woefully unmet.

Conclusion

To assess diversion programs, we must address the question, diversion to what? For many U.S. communities, the answer continues to be “not enough.” We have analyzed diversion programs using a bioethical framework in the context of a persistent resource problem in behavioral health and other human services. We find that programs operating under such circumstances are faced with difficult ethical dilemmas and may at times cause more harm than good, especially when they involve criminal legal supervision.

It is possible to design and implement diversion programs that effectively promote health and reduce harms while preserving the dignity and autonomy of justice-involved individuals with behavioral health needs. However, doing so requires addressing the background resource problem that permeates the behavioral health and human services infrastructure. Without public investments to increase treatment capacity, choice of treatment options, and the representativeness of the health and human services workforce, diversion programs cannot provide ethical care to participants, especially to those from marginalized communities. Crucially, doing so also requires significant internal reforms to many programs’ staffing, eligibility criteria, conditions of participation, and success metrics, so that diversion itself does not become an additional barrier to accessing an already scarce supply of resources. If diversion programs are to live up to their goals of reducing justice involvement and improving clinical outcomes, including in communities that have been most deeply underserved by the justice and healthcare systems, we must all become more responsive to the resource problem. The bioethics framework offers a helpful tool to begin that work.

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the Wilson Center for Science & Justice at Duke University School of Law.

References

Bronson, J., Zimmer, S., and Berzofsky, M., “Drug Use, Dependence, and Abuse Among State Prisoners and Jail Inmates, 2007-2009” (Bureau of Justice Statistics, 2017), available at <https://bjs.ojp.gov/content/pub/pdf/dudaspji0709.pdf> (last visited February 29, 2024).+(last+visited+February+29,+2024).>Google Scholar
James, D. J. and Glaze, L. E., “Mental Health Problems of Prison and Jail Inmates,” Bureau of Justice Statistics Special Report, 2006, 1–12, US Department of Justice, Office of Justice Programs, NCJ Number 213600, September 2006, available at <https://bjs.ojp.gov/library/publications/mental-health-problems-prison-and-jail-inmates> (last visited April 10, 2024).+(last+visited+April+10,+2024).>Google Scholar
Alegría, M. et al., “Transforming Mental Health and Addiction Services,” Health Affairs 40, no. 2 (2021): 226–34, https://doi.org/10.1377/hlthaff.2020.01472.Google ScholarPubMed
Beauchamp, T. L. and Childress, J. F., Principles of Biomedical Ethics (Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration (SAMSHA), “Key Substance Use and Mental Health Indicators in the United States: Results from the 2022 National Survey on Drug Use and Health” (Rockville, MD: Center for Behavioral Health Statistics and Quality, U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, 2023).Google Scholar
Haeny, A. M. et al., “Drug and Alcohol Treatment Utilization and Barriers among Black, American Indian/Alaskan Native, Latine, Asian/Pacific Islander/Native Hawaiian, and White Adults: Findings from NESARC-III,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment, July 21, 2021, 108569, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jsat.2021.108569; R. M. Entress, “The Intersection of Race and Opioid Use Disorder Treatment: A Quantitative Analysis,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment, August 19, 2021, 108589, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jsat.2021.108589; Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality, September 2019); M. Alegría et al., “Removing Obstacles To Eliminating Racial And Ethnic Disparities In Behavioral Health Care,” Health Affairs 35, no. 6 (2016): 991–99, https://doi.org/10.1377/hlthaff.2016.0029; T. G. McGuire et al., “Implementing the Institute of Medicine Definition of Disparities: An Application to Mental Health Care,” Health Services Research 41, no. 5 (2006): 1979–2005, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-6773.2006.00583.x; J. A. Chen et al., “Racial/Ethnic and Gender Differences in Receipt of Brief Intervention among Patients with Unhealthy Alcohol Use in the U.S. Veterans Health Administration,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment 119 (2020): 108078, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jsat.2020.108078.Google Scholar
See SAMSHA, supra note 6.Google Scholar
Hasin, D. S. and Grant, B. F., “The National Epidemiologic Survey on Alcohol and Related Conditions (NESARC) Waves 1 and 2: Review and Summary of Findings,” Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology 50, no. 11 (2015): 1609–40, https://doi.org/10.1007/s00127-015-1088-0; B. Han, E. I. Lopez, and E. F. McCance-Katz, “Commentary on Harris et al. (2019): Increasing Perceived Need for Substance Use Treatment among People with Substance Use Disorders,” Addiction 114, no. 8 (2019): 1460–61, https://doi.org/10.1111/add.14658.Google ScholarPubMed
Blank Wilson, A., “How People With Serious Mental Illness Seek Help After Leaving Jail,” Qualitative Health Research 23, no. 12 (2013): 1575–90, https://doi.org/10.1177/1049732313508476; S. Tsemberis, L. Gulcur, and M. Nakae, “Housing First, Consumer Choice, and Harm Reduction for Homeless Individuals With a Dual Diagnosis,” American Journal of Public Health 94, no. 4 (.2004): 651–56, https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.94.4.651.Google ScholarPubMed
Padgett, D. K. et al., “Substance Use Outcomes Among Homeless Clients with Serious Mental Illness: Comparing Housing First with Treatment First Programs,” Community Mental Health Journal 47, no. 2 (2011): 227–32, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10597-009-9283-7.Google ScholarPubMed
See Alegría et al., supra note 4; D. M. Anglin, B. G. Link, and J. C. Phelan, “Racial Differences in Stigmatizing Attitudes Toward People With Mental Illness,” Psychiatric Services 57, no. 6 (2006): 857–62, https://doi.org/10.1176/ps.2006.57.6.857.Google Scholar
Saloner, B. and Lê Cook, B., “Blacks and Hispanics Are Less Likely Than Whites To Complete Addiction Treatment, Largely Due To Socioeconomic Factors,” Health Affairs (Project Hope) 32, no. 1 (2013): 135145, https://doi.org/10.1377/hlthaff.2011.0983.Google ScholarPubMed
Center for Health and Justice at TASC, “No Entry: A National Survey of Criminal Justice Diversion Programs and Initiatives” (Chicago: Center for Health and Justice at TASC, December 2013); S. J. Prins, “Prevalence of Mental Illnesses in U.S. State Prisons: A Systematic Review,” Psychiatric Services 65, no. 7 (2014): 862–72, https://doi.org/10.1176/appi.ps.201300166.Google Scholar
Collins, S. E., Lonczak, H. S., and Clifasefi, S. L., “Seattle’s Law Enforcement Assisted Diversion (LEAD): Program Effects on Recidivism Outcomes,” Evaluation and Program Planning 64 (2017): 4956, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.evalprogplan.2017.05.008.Google ScholarPubMed
Skeem, J. L., Manchak, S., and Montoya, L., “Comparing Public Safety Outcomes for Traditional Probation vs Specialty Mental Health Probation,” JAMA Psychiatry 74, no. 9 (2017): 942–48, https://doi.org/10.1001/jamapsychiatry.2017.1384.Google ScholarPubMed
Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration, “The Sequential Intercept Model (SIM),” Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration, June 24, 2021, available at <https://www.samhsa.gov/criminal-juvenile-justice/sim-overview> (last visited February 29, 2024); M. R. Munetz and P. A. Griffin, “Use of the Sequential Intercept Model as an Approach to Decriminalization of People With Serious Mental Illness,” Psychiatric Services 57, no. 4 (2006): 544–49, https://doi.org/10.1176/ps.2006.57.4.544.+(last+visited+February+29,+2024);+M.+R.+Munetz+and+P.+A.+Griffin,+“Use+of+the+Sequential+Intercept+Model+as+an+Approach+to+Decriminalization+of+People+With+Serious+Mental+Illness,”+Psychiatric+Services+57,+no.+4+(2006):+544–49,+https://doi.org/10.1176/ps.2006.57.4.544.>Google Scholar
See Munetz and Griffin, id.Google Scholar
Abreu, D. et al., “Revising the Paradigm for Jail Diversion for People with Mental and Substance Use Disorders: Intercept 0,” Behavioral Sciences & the Law 35, no. 5–6 (2017): 380–95, https://doi.org/10.1002/bsl.2300.Google ScholarPubMed
Bonfine, N., Blank Wilson, A., and Munetz, M. R., “Meeting the Needs of Justice-Involved People with Serious Mental Illness Within Community Behavioral Health Systems,” Psychiatric Services 71, no. 4 (2020): 355–63, https://doi.org/10.1176/appi.ps.201900453.Google ScholarPubMed
Scott, D. A. et al., “Effectiveness of Criminal Justice Liaison and Diversion Services for Offenders With Mental Disorders: A Review,” Psychiatric Services 64, no. 9 (2013): 843–49, https://doi.org/10.1176/appi.ps.201200144; T. Seltzer, “Mental Health Courts: A Misguided Attempt to Address the Criminal Justice System’s Unfair Treatment of People with Mental Illnesses,” Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 11, no. 4 (2005): 570–86, https://doi.org/10.1037/1076-8971.11.4.570; T. B. Van Deinse et al., “Using the Consolidated Framework for Implementation Research to Examine Implementation Determinants of Specialty Mental Health Probation,” Health & Justice 7, no. 1 (December 5, 2019): 17, https://doi.org/10.1186/s40352-019-0098-5; D. S. Morse et al., “Finding the Loopholes: A Cross-Sectional Qualitative Study of Systemic Barriers to Treatment Access for Women Drug Court Participants,” Health & Justice 3, no. 1 (2015): 12, https://doi.org/10.1186/s40352-015-0026-2; M. M. Easter et al., “North Carolina Specialty Courts, Treatment Access, and the Substance Use Crisis: A Promising but Underfunded Model,” Psychiatric Services, June 18, 2021, appi.ps.202000868, https://doi.org/10.1176/appi.ps.202000868; J. Bowers, “Contraindicated Drug Courts,” UCLA Law Review 55, no. 4 (2008 2007): 783–836.Google ScholarPubMed
National Alliance on Mental Illness, “Divert to What? Community Services That Enhance Diversion” (National Alliance on Mental Illness, 2020), available at <https://www.nami.org/Support-Education/Publications-Reports/Public-Policy-Reports/Divert-to-What-Community-Services-that-Enhance-Diversion/DiverttoWhat.pdf> (last visited February 29, 2024); Bazelon Center for Mental Health Law, “Diversion to What?” (Bazelon Center for Mental Health Law: Bazelon Center for Mental Health Law, September 2019), available at <http://www.bazelon.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/09/Bazelon-Diversion-to-What-Essential-Services-Publication_September-2019.pdf> (last visited February 29, 2024).+(last+visited+February+29,+2024);+Bazelon+Center+for+Mental+Health+Law,+“Diversion+to+What?”+(Bazelon+Center+for+Mental+Health+Law:+Bazelon+Center+for+Mental+Health+Law,+September+2019),+available+at++(last+visited+February+29,+2024).>Google Scholar
Cloud, D. H., Parsons, J., and Delany-Brumsey, A., “Addressing Mass Incarceration: A Clarion Call for Public Health,” American Journal of Public Health 104, no. 3 (2014): 389–91, https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.2013.301741.Google ScholarPubMed
See Beauchamp and Childress, supra note 5.Google Scholar
Kurlychek, M. and Johnson, B., “Cumulative Disadvantage in the American Criminal Justice System,” Annual Review of Criminology 2 (2019): 291319, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-criminol-011518-024815.Google Scholar
Danis, M., Wilson, Y., and White, A., “Bioethicists Can and Should Contribute to Addressing Racism,” The American Journal of Bioethics 16, no. 4 (2016): 312, https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2016.1145283.Google ScholarPubMed
Guta, A., Voronka, J., and Gagnon, M., “Resisting the Digital Medicine Panopticon: Toward a Bioethics of the Oppressed,” The American Journal of Bioethics 18, no. 9 (2018): 6264, https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2018.1498936.Google Scholar
Alexander, M., The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of Colorblindness (New York: The New Press, 2010); H. Ann Thompson, “The Racial History of Criminal Justice in America,” Du Bois Review: Social Science Research on Race 16, no. 1 (2019): 221–41, https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X19000183; M. C. Campbell and H. Schoenfeld, “The Transformation of America’s Penal Order: A Historicized Political Sociology of Punishment,” American Journal of Sociology 118, no. 5 (2013): 1375–1423, https://doi.org/10.1086/669506.Google Scholar
Csete, J., “Criminal Justice Barriers to Treatment of Opioid Use Disorders in the United States: The Need for Public Health Advocacy,” American Journal of Public Health 109, no. 3 (2019): 419–22, https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.2018.304852; H. Matusow et al., “Medication Assisted Treatment in US Drug Courts: Results from a Nationwide Survey of Availability, Barriers and Attitudes,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment 44, no. 5 (2013): 473–80, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jsat.2012.10.004; E.J. Miller, “Embracing Addiction: Drug Courts and the False Promise of Judicial Interventionism,” Ohio State Law Journal 65 (2004): 1479; M. Hoffman, “Therapeutic Jurisprudence, Neo-Rehabilitationism, and Judicial Collectivism: The Least Dangerous Branch Becomes The Most Dangerous,” Fordham Urban Law Journal 29 (2001); A. M. McLeod, “Decarceration Courts: Possibilities and Perils of a Shifting Criminal Law,” Georgetown Law Journal 100 (2011): 1587.Google ScholarPubMed
See Beauchamp and Childress, supra note 5.Google Scholar
See Seltzer, supra note 22.Google Scholar
Lawrence Fitch, W. and Swanson, J. W., “Civil Commitment and the Mental Health Continuum” (Rockville, MD: Office of the Chief Medical Officer, Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration: Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration (SAMSHA), U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (HHS), 2019), available at <https://www.samhsa.gov/sites/default/files/civil-commitment-continuum-of-care.pdf> (last visited February 29, 2024).+(last+visited+February+29,+2024).>Google Scholar
See Fitch and Swanson, id.Google Scholar
See Matusow et al., supra note 30; see Csete, supra note 30.Google Scholar
Lee, J. D et al., “Comparative Effectiveness of Extended-Release Naltrexone versus Buprenorphine-Naloxone for Opioid Relapse Prevention (X:BOT): A Multicentre, Open-Label, Randomised Controlled Trial,” Lancet 391, no. 10118 (2018): 309–18, https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(17)32812-X.Google Scholar
Ajazi, E. M. et al., “Revisiting the X: BOT Naltrexone Clinical Trial Using a Comprehensive Survival Analysis,” Journal of Addiction Medicine, March 11, 2022, https://doi.org/10.1097/ADM.0000000000000931.Google Scholar
Garcia, A. and Lucas, D., “Bridging the Gap: A Practitioner’s Guide to Harm Reduction in Drug Courts” (Center for Court Innovation, 2021), available at <https://www.courtinnovation.org/sites/default/files/media/document/2021/Guide_TA_BridgingtheGap_08102021.pdf> (last visited February 29, 2024).+(last+visited+February+29,+2024).>Google Scholar
Moloney, K. P., van den Bergh, B. J., and Moller, L. F., “Women in Prison: The Central Issues of Gender Characteristics and Trauma History,” Public Health 123, no. 6 (2009): 426–30, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.puhe.2009.04.002; N. Messina and C. Grella, “Childhood Trauma and Women’s Health Outcomes in a California Prison Population,” American Journal of Public Health 96, no. 10 (2006): 1842–48, https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.2005.082016.Google ScholarPubMed
Robertson, A. G. et al., “Gender-Specific Participation and Outcomes among Jail Diversion Clients with Co-Occurring Substance Use and Mental Health Disorders,” Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment 115 (2020): 108035, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jsat.2020.108035.Google ScholarPubMed
Joudrey, P. J. et al., “Pharmacy-Based Methadone Dispensing and Drive Time to Methadone Treatment in Five States within the United States: A Cross-Sectional Study,” Drug and Alcohol Dependence 211 (2020): 107968, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.drugalcdep.2020.107968.Google ScholarPubMed
See Beauchamp and Childress, supra note 5.Google Scholar
Lett, E. et al., “Racial Inequity in Fatal US Police Shootings, 2015–2020,” Journal of Epidemiological Community Health 75, no. 4 (2021): 394–97, https://doi.org/10.1136/jech-2020-215097; M. Massoglia and B. Remster, “Linkages Between Incarceration and Health,” Public Health Reports 134, no. 1_suppl (2019): 8S-14S, https://doi.org/10.1177/0033354919826563; M. Massoglia and W. Alex Pridemore, “Incarceration and Health,” Annual Review of Sociology 41, no. 1 (2015): 291–310, https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-soc-073014-112326; N. F. Sugie and K. Turney, “Beyond Incarceration: Criminal Justice Contact and Mental Health,” American Sociological Review 82, no. 4 (2017): 719–43, https://doi.org/10.1177/0003122417713188; R. T. Trotter et al., “A Survey of Health Disparities, Social Determinants of Health, and Converging Morbidities in a County Jail: A Cultural-Ecological Assessment of Health Conditions in Jail Populations,” International Journal of Environmental Research and Public Health 15, no. 11 (2018): 2500, https://doi.org/10.3390/ijerph15112500.Google Scholar
See McLeod, supra note 30; J. Gross, “The Effects of Net-Widening on Minority and Indigent Drug Offenders: A Critique of Drug Courts,” University of Maryland Law Journal of Race, Religion, Gender and Class 10 (2010): 161; see Miller, supra note 30; E. Sevigny, H. Pollack, and P. Reuter, “Can Drug Courts Help to Reduce Prison and Jail Populations?” The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 647, no. 1 (2013): 190–212.Google Scholar
Sevigny, E., Fuleihan, B., and Ferdik, F., “Do Drug Courts Reduce the Use of Incarceration? A Meta-Analysis,” Journal of Criminal Justice 41 (2013): 416–25, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jcrimjus.2013.06.005; M. M. O’Hear, “Rethinking Drug Courts: Restorative Justice as a Response to Racial Injustice,” Stanford Law & Policy Review 20 (2009): 463; R. Fluellen and J. Trone, “Do Drug Courts Save Jail and Prison Beds?,” Issues in Brief Series (New York, NY: Vera Institute of Justice, 2000), available at <https://www.ojp.gov/ncjrs/virtual-library/abstracts/do-drug-courts-save-jail-and-prison-beds> (last visited February 29, 2024).Google Scholar
Van Deinse, T. B. et al., “Probation Officers’ Perceptions of Supervising Probationers with Mental Illness in Rural and Urban Settings,” American Journal of Criminal Justice 43, no. 2 (2018): 267–77, https://doi.org/10.1007/s12103-017-9392-8.Google Scholar
National Association of Drug Court Professionals, “Adult Drug Court Best Practice Standards Volume II” (Alexandria, VA, 2015).Google Scholar
See Csete, supra note 30.Google Scholar
See Robertson et al., supra note 40.Google Scholar
See Beauchamp and Childress, supra note 5.Google Scholar
See McLeod, supra note 30.Google Scholar
Blank Wilson, A. and Draine, J., “Collaborations Between Criminal Justice and Mental Health Systems for Prisoner Reentry,” Psychiatric Services 57, no. 6 (2006): 875–78, https://doi.org/10.1176/ps.2006.57.6.875; K. C. Johnson et al., “An Overview of Prosecutor-Led Diversion Programs: A New Incarnation of an Old Idea,” Justice System Journal 41, no. 1 (2020): 63–78, https://doi.org/10.1080/0098261X.2019.1707136; J. Csete and H. Catania, “Methadone Treatment Providers’ Views of Drug Court Policy and Practice: A Case Study of New York State,” Harm Reduction Journal 10, no. 1 (2013): 35, https://doi.org/10.1186/1477-7517-10-35.Google Scholar
See Bonfine, Wilson, and Munetz, supra note 20.Google Scholar
See Alegría et al., supra note 4.Google Scholar
See Beauchamp and Childress, supra note 5.Google Scholar
See Alexander, supra note 29; see Thompson, supra note 29; see Campbell and Schoenfeld, supra note 29.Google Scholar
Marlowe, D. B., Hardin, C. D., and Fox, C. L., “Painting the Current Picture: A National Report Card on Drug Courts and Other Problem Solving Court Programs in the United States, Vol. I, No. 2” (Alexandria, VA: National Association of Drug Court Professionals, 2016); B. Joy Hedden et al., “Racial Disparities in Access to and Utilization of Jail- and Community-Based Mental Health Treatment in 8 US Midwestern Jails in 2017,” American Journal of Public Health 111, no. 2 (2021): 277–85, https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.2020.305992.Google Scholar
Bennett, M. W. and Plaut, V. C., “Looking Criminal and the Presumption of Dangerousness: Afrocentric Facial Features, Skin Tone, and Criminal Justice,” U.C. Davis Law Review 51 (2017): 745.Google Scholar
Kubiak, Sh. et al., “Identification, Referral, and Services for Individuals with Serious Mental Illness Across Multiple Jails,” Journal of Correctional Health Care 26, no. 2 (2020): 168–82, https://doi.org/10.1177/1078345820920703.Google ScholarPubMed
See Bowers, supra note 22.Google Scholar
Dewan, S. and Lehren, A. W., “After a Crime, the Price of a Second Chance,” The New York Times, December 12, 2016, available at <https://www.nytimes.com/2016/12/12/us/crime-criminal-justice-reform-diversion.html> (last visited February 29, 2024).+(last+visited+February+29,+2024).>Google Scholar