Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-mwx4w Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-19T19:43:54.879Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Advancing Value Pluralist Approaches to Social Policy Controversies: A Case Study of Welfare Conditionality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 March 2023

Beth Watts-Cobbe*
Affiliation:
Heriot-Watt University, Scotland, United Kingdom
Suzanne Fitzpatrick
Affiliation:
Heriot-Watt University, Scotland, United Kingdom
*
*Corresponding author: Email: b.watts-cobbe@hw.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

‘Value pluralism’ is a strand of analytical philosophy that posits the plurality of morally significant values. By enabling systematic mapping of the diversity of moral registers within which social policy concerns might legitimately be considered, we contend that value pluralist-inspired analysis can aid constructive policy dialogue. Our argument is founded on four claims: first, as a matter of normative principle, value pluralism represents a defensible ethical standpoint; second, as a matter of fact, people are attracted to a plurality of moral values; third, as a matter of democratic legitimacy, pluralism offers a means of (partially) reconciling rival moral claims; fourth, as a matter of political strategy, pluralism offers a pragmatic approach that can engage protagonists on their own terms. To demonstrate its efficacy, we apply this pluralist approach to the vexed question of welfare conditionality, which we interrogate via six normative perspectives (rights, utilitarianism, contractualism, communitarianism, paternalism and social justice).

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

Introduction

Many if not most social policy challenges pose not only technical questions (about the best means to agreed ends) and political questions (about which coalition of interests can gain sufficient power to implement their policy agenda), but also fundamental ethical issues, pertaining to deeper concerns about the rightness or wrongness, or goodness or badness, of societal arrangements. These ethical questions often tap into our most deep-seated personal views about how society ought to be organised, meaning that debates can sometime seem stuck at an impasse between profoundly opposed factions. This paper seeks to signal a philosophically-informed route to more constructive dialogue in areas of profound tension in social policy, reflecting our view that political and moral philosophy provide effective yet underused tools to address ethical questions within social policy.Footnote 1

Our central aim is to explicate the attractions of ‘value pluralism’ as a substantive moral orientation, and the empirical, democratic and pragmatic reasons to deploy it in social policy analysis, as laid out in the next section. To demonstrate the power of this pluralist ethical framework, we then consider the vexed question of welfare conditionality via the lens of six key normative perspectives (rights, utilitarianism, contractualism, communitarianism, paternalism and social justice). The remainder of the paper applies this pluralistic perspective to what we view as the main morally-relevant questions in determining the justifiability or otherwise of welfare conditionality. We conclude by reflecting on the potential of value pluralism in social policy analysis, focusing on the importance of clarifying normative and non-normative sources of disagreement, triangulating multiple moral perspectives to build robust support for particular policies, and understanding diverse value orientations to clarify the basis of polarisation in policy debate.

Value pluralism and social policy

Value pluralists endorse a view of ethics that recognises that there are a “plurality of morally significant values” (Wolf, Reference Wolf1992, p.785). It is important to note that value pluralism does not entail moral relativism – that is, the view that there are no universal moral truths (Wolf, Reference Wolf1992; Galston, Reference Galston2002), far less ‘subjectivism’, the notion that morality represents merely the expression of emotional attitudes (Wolf, Reference Wolf1992). On the contrary, it represents a commitment to the objectivity of a multiple, but finite, set of morally relevant fundamental values (Berlin, Reference Berlin2002). Crucially for our purposes here, value pluralism stands in contradistinction to ‘monist’ theories that see all forms of goodness or rightness as reducible to a singular measure or meta-value (Galston, Reference Galston2002, p.4). Utilitarians, for instance, view ethics as fully explained by attention to the level of collective wellbeing different courses of action achieve. A rights-based deontological perspective, on the other hand, interprets the source of fundamental ethical value as lying in people’s basic rights and “morally protected sphere of individual autonomy” being respected at all times (Nagel, Reference Nagel2021, p.5).

Pluralists hold that these and other monist approaches can only ever hope to capture part of the ‘moral truth’ (Wolf, Reference Wolf1992; Wolff, Reference Wolff2015). This proposition is linked, at the social policy level, to the insight that the ‘good society’ has to be judged on multiple criteria, not by a single standard, with a balance struck between a range of (often competing) social objectives, such as the protection of personal liberty, the advancement of social justice, the nurturing of social cohesion, the pursuit of economic prosperity, and the establishment and institutionalisation of democracy (Miller, Reference Miller1999; Wolff, Reference Wolff2015). Reductionist, monist approaches can thus be obfuscatory as well as partial in their intellectual impact, as was famously argued by Isaiah Berlin:

“… the belief that some single formula can in principle be found whereby all the diverse ends of men can be harmoniously realised is demonstrably false. If as I believe the ends of men are many, and not all of them are in principle compatible with each other, the possibility of conflict - and of tragedy - can never wholly be eliminated from human life, either personal or social. The necessity of choosing between absolute claims is then an inescapable characteristic of the human condition.” (Reference Berlin2002, p.214)

It is surprising, in this light, that rights-based perspectives have come to carry such sway within social policy scholarship as the predominant normative lens via which to defend the welfare state (see below and e.g. Dwyer, Reference Dwyer2000; Dean, Reference Dean2015), and part of our goal in this paper is to explicate alternative perspectives to it.

While value pluralism is a philosophical concept, psychologists have bolstered its empirical foundations by mapping the ‘moral foundations’ that people draw upon when thinking about ethics in practice. Haidt and Graham (Reference Haidt and Graham2007), for example, have highlighted that people’s moral foundations extend beyond philosophers’ – and we would add social policy scholars’ – traditional concerns with justice, rights and fairness, to “group-level moral concerns” such as authority, loyalty and tradition (Graham et al., Reference Graham, Nosek, Haidt, Iyer, Koleva and Ditto2011, p. 367).

This evidence that, as a matter of political and psychological fact, people are attracted to a plurality of moral values, bolsters the democratic argument for social policy underpinned by value pluralist-style analysis (Miller, Reference Miller1999). Berlin was pessimistic regarding the incommensurability of such divergent values in policy and practice (see above). However, our pluralist approach is also inspired by Nagel (Reference Nagel1979), who more optimistically argued that “Radical disagreement about the basis of ethics is compatible with substantial agreement about what the important factors are in real life” (p.141). Galston (Reference Galston2002) also saw potential for reasonable and constructive debate about policy dilemmas in the face of plural values. “Deliberative argument”, he argued “can provide reasons for choices among qualitatively different claims even when no common measure of value is available” (Galston, Reference Galston2002, p.35). In other words, people may agree on what is ethically permissible, or required, in concrete cases, even though they arrive at this judgement for quite different reasons. One pertinent example is Deacon’s (Reference Deacon2004) analysis of the then UK Labour Government’s policies on anti-social behaviour targeting social tenants. Deacon found that three distinct normative frameworks – contractualist, paternalist and mutualist – could be engaged to justify these policies, despite many in the academic social policy community viewing them as oppressive interventions.

By systematically examining contentious matters of social policy via multiple ethical lenses, such analysis lends weight to the pluralist case by illuminating the powerful moral intuitions that each perspective taps into (Nagel, Reference Nagel2021). Moreover, in demonstrating that similar moral conclusions on specific matters of policy can be reached via very different ethical routes, they reinforce the pragmatic value of the pluralist approach. Even for monists, convinced of the reducibility of all normative considerations to one fundamental value, there may therefore be good strategic reasons to ‘reach across the aisle’ beyond their preferred ethical repertoire, in order to engage those with different normative orientations but with whom common ground may be found in particular cases.

Consistent with Berlin (Reference Berlin2002), and other key pluralist thinkers including Miller (Reference Miller1999) and Ignatieff (Reference Ignatieff2000), our proposed approach to social policy analysis lays strong emphasis on the interdependence of moral reflection, logical deduction, and empirical evidence in progressing contentious social policy debates. In particular, some apparent ethical disagreements reflect errors of logic, which can be corrected, or conflicting factual assumptions, which are apt for empirical testing. Close attention to these non-normative matters as part of more systematic ethical analysis of social policy allows us to identify the narrowed territory where genuine values-based trade-offs, or ‘tragic choices’ (Berlin, Reference Berlin2002), might be required. In the sections that follow, we seek to pull apart these strands of the highly polarised debate on welfare conditionality, foregrounding the presence (or absence) of fundamental value-disagreements that undermine effective policy debate in this area.

Welfare conditionality: the view through distinctive ethical lenses

Welfare conditionality, which links access to welfare goods and services to behavioural requirements, has become a mainstream policy tool globally. A central component of social security policy across advanced welfare states, from the so-called ‘liberal’ regimes of the UK, Australia and the US, to the social democratic welfare regimes of the Nordic countries (Immervoll et al, Reference Immervoll, Knotz and Otmani2020), conditionality also plays a core role in the evolving social protection systems of the Global South, most often in the form of Conditional Cash Transfers (CCTs) (Fiszbein et al., Reference Fiszbein, Schady, Ferreira, Grosh, Keleher, Olinto and Skoufias2009). While conditionality attached to cash benefits usually requires recipients to seek work, CCTs, and some conditional policies in Australia, focus instead on health or education-related behaviours, such as ensuring that children are appropriately immunised or attending school (Bastagli, Reference Bastagli2009; Taylor et al., Reference Taylor, Gray and Stanton2016).

Though all conditional welfare approaches share a core logic – involving the imposition of behavioural requirements, the monitoring and verification of required actions, and the use of sanctions in instances of non-compliance (or sometimes incentives for compliance) – there is wide variation in the design and specification of these components in practice. Some conditional welfare programmes have stringent behavioural requirements (e.g. 35 hours a week job search activity, learning a new language, overcoming an addiction), harsh sanctions (e.g. permanent ‘full family’ sanctions in parts of the US), and quite intrusive levels of surveillance (e.g. compulsory daily visits by a support worker) (Watts and Fitzpatrick, Reference Watts and Fitzpatrick2018). In many other instances, however, conduct requirements are much more modest (two job search activities per month in Korea, for example), and sanctions relatively mild (a first warning followed by a loss of five days benefit in Sweden) (Immervoll and Knotz, Reference Immervoll and Knotz2018).

Despite the ubiquity of, and immense variation in, programmes captured under the banner of welfare conditionality, debates in this field tend to be highly polarised, even inflammatory, in style and content. Proponents see conditionality as self-evidently justified: as an “integral” component of welfare systems (Miscampbell, Reference Miscampbell2014, p.6), and as a “key element of the mutual obligation that underpins both the effectiveness and fairness of the social security system” (Oakley, Reference Oakley2014, p.4). Opponents, on the other hand, have characterised conditionality as “institutional barbarity against the most vulnerable people in the system” (Corbyn, Reference Corbyn2016), and even described the underlying logic as reflective of “a government of the grotesque” (Ryan, Reference Ryan2014).

Academic perspectives are also divided, with a small number of scholars robustly defending the essential role of welfare conditionality (Mead, Reference Mead1986; Dunn, Reference Dunn2014), while others feel it can only be justified once onerous background ‘conditions of fair reciprocity’ (White, Reference White2003) are met. The majority view in the social policy community, however, is firmly set against welfare conditionality, which has been variously described as “neither effective nor ethical… [and] unfit for purpose” (Wright et al., Reference Wright, Dwyer, Jones, McNeill, Scullion and Stewart2018, p.10), “morally dubious” (Standing, Reference Standing2011, p.33), “illiberal” (Curchin, Reference Curchin2019, p.2) and “superfluous, pernicious, atrocious and abominable” (Freeland, Reference Freeland2007, p.75). Recent contributions have interpreted sanction-based reforms through the lenses of ‘social abuse’, ‘institutional violence’ and even ‘social murder’ (see Wright et al., Reference Wright, Fletcher and Stewart2020), and characterised sanctions as primarily a “weapon” (Redman, Reference Redman2020, p.84) deployed to “degrade” (McNeill, Reference McNeill2020, p.295) welfare recipients.

Stepping back from these impassioned and antagonistic, positions, and inspired by Deacon’s (Reference Deacon2004) normative analysis of anti-social behaviour interventions, we now map the contours of six key perspectives which our review of the international evidence indicates are the primary ethical lenses through which welfare conditionality has been debated to date (Watts and Fitzpatrick, Reference Watts and Fitzpatrick2018; see also Curchin et al., Reference Curchin, Weight and Ritter2021). While some of these perspectives have historical roots and specific points of substance in common, they are distinct in foregrounding particular rationales via which to defend or object to conditionality. In keeping with our pluralist analysis, we seek to draw out the most compelling aspects of each of these moral frameworks (‘steel-personning’ rather than ‘straw-manning’ them), while also noting the key objections they face. Crucially, we explicate their implications with regard to the moral permissibility of, or even requirement for, conditions to be attached to receipt of welfare provisions. Our desire to ‘steel-person’ people’s positions also informs our choice of normative frameworks. We focus upon established normative traditions that a reasonable person of “general goodwill and human sympathy” (Harsanyi, Reference Harsanyi, Sen and Williams1982, p.56) could plausibly endorse, rather than assume malign intentions on the part of any stakeholders.

Rights

Rights-based perspectives are a dominant normative framing of welfare conditionality within social policy scholarship in the UK, as noted above. Such perspectives draw (implicitly) on a deontological Kantian logic that ethical value inheres in ‘universalisable’ duties about how we treat each other being acted upon, such that “we must regard each person… as immune from subjection to others” (Nagel, Reference Nagel2021, p.5), with all human beings presenting “the same stubborn and impenetrable moral surface” (ibid., p.8). The focus may be on social citizenship rights (Dwyer, Reference Dwyer2000; Reeves and Loopstra, Reference Reeves and Loopstra2017; and Fitzpatrick et al, Reference Fitzpatrick, McKeever and Simpson2019) or human rights (Nevile, Reference Nevile2008; Veit-Wilson, Reference Veit-Wilson2009), but in both cases, rights to welfare goods and services are typically seen as non-negotiable.

For Dwyer (Reference Dwyer2004), for example, the “very idea of ‘welfare rights’ is systematically undermined” by the “creeping conditionality” initially seen in the late 1990s, and the ubiquitous conditionality that now characterizes UK social security policy (p.265; see also Dwyer & Wright, Reference Dwyer and Wright2014). This ‘rights logic’ is also evident in Viet-Wilson’s critique of CCTs in which he emphasises “the categorical implications of human rights to the means for social inclusion” (Veit-Wilson, Reference Veit-Wilson2009, p.172) arguing that “poor people… have a categorical human right both to an adequate income and to education and health care” (p.173) and questioning the grounds on which governments can make access to these things conditional. Freeland, similarly, highlights the inconsistency between human rights discourses, often emphasised in the development context, and the conditionality inherent within CCTs:

“it is morally highly questionable whether a government (often encouraged by donors) can, on the one hand, proudly tell its citizens that social protection is their basic ‘human right’; and then, on the other hand, threaten to deprive the neediest among them of that very ‘right’ if they fail to meet certain ‘conditions’.” (Freeland, Reference Freeland2007, p.77)

From this perspective welfare conditionality is seen as unethical as a matter of a priori logic. Withholding something people have a right to is, necessarily, an unacceptable rights violation. Any positive consequences (e.g. higher employment or immunisation rates) associated with such an incentive structure are irrelevant: rights are side-constraints or ‘trumps’ and can’t be traded against other goals, including the collective good (Dworkin, Reference Dworkin1977).

There is something undeniably compelling about rights advocates’ insistence upon the dignity of persons, the ‘non fungibility’ of human beings, and the need to treat all of us as ends in ourselves, rather than simply the means to other people’s ends. However, while this rights-orientated framework clearly carries a lot of weight within the social policy community, its absolutist and non-negotiable tenor (Waldron, Reference Waldron1993) can alienate wider society (including the frontline workers implementing these policies, see Sadeghi and Terum, Reference Sadeghi and Terum2020) where a more pluralist set of values prevails (Graham et al., Reference Graham, Nosek, Haidt, Iyer, Koleva and Ditto2011). Abstract human rights are also subject to objections regarding their philosophical foundations, and have a range of unintended negative consequences when they take a juridified, enforceable form (Fitzpatrick et al, Reference Fitzpatrick, Bengtsson and Watts2014).

Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism offers the main opposition to rights-based theories, conceiving of ethical choices – and policies – as those which maximise utility, welfare or wellbeing (Goodin, Reference Goodin and Singer1993; Kymlicka, Reference Kymlicka2002). Its intuitive appeal rests on the central proposition that the only intrinsically morally significant phenomenon is the conscious experiences of sentient beings (Goodin, Reference Goodin and Singer1993): any other values that appear to have moral currency are ultimately only meaningful in the instrumental service they pay to these experiences.

For utilitarians, the ethical legitimacy of conditional welfare interventions depends on their aggregate impact on overall societal welfare. The ‘utilitarian calculus’ must weigh in the balance welfare impacts on the full range of relevant actors, including those directly targeted by the intervention, where an assessment must be made about whether it enhances their wellbeing (e.g. by encouraging them into work that helps lift them out of poverty, or to engage with health services) or diminishes it (e.g. via the material hardship imposed by benefit sanctions). The impact of conditionality on other members of the benefit recipient’s household, including any children, is also relevant, as is the impact on the wider public, including whether welfare conditionality has any general deterrent effect on unemployment and/or welfare claims (Paz-Fuchs, Reference Paz-Fuchs2008), and whether the public gain or lose utility by seeing welfare goods distributed in accordance with behavioural conditions.

Utilitarianism’s unpopularity with many on the political Left arises from its aggregative quality and association with economistic reasoning (see, for example, Titmuss, Reference Titmuss2018[1970]), but few can doubt that the maximisation of welfare ought to be a core objective of social policy. Moreover, what is often overlooked is that utilitarianism properly understood has strong egalitarian implications in at least two senses: equal weight must be given to each person’s interests in the utilitarian calculus (Kymlicka, Reference Kymlicka2002); and the gains (and losses) of those who have least count for most under the law of ‘diminishing marginal utility’ (Gabriel, Reference Gabriel2017). On the other hand, utilitarianism’s disregard for the distribution of the sum total of utility and the moral equivalence attached to different sources of utility limits the appeal of the theory as a complete moral code. Another objection to monist utilitarian approaches highly relevant to our argument is that:

“…impartial benevolence, the motive that is supposed to ground utilitarianism, is far too weak in most human beings to support obedience to its demanding moral requirements, which makes it unsuitable as the sole basis for human morality.” (Nagel, Reference Nagel2021, p.6)

Contractualism

The contractualist normative lens foregrounds the value of reciprocity (Miscampbell, Reference Miscampbell2014), as opposed to utility or a one-sided emphasis on rights (Deacon, Reference Deacon2004), with the metaphor of the contract capturing the idea that a good or right state of affairs consists in two parties meeting their mutual obligations to one another in a fair exchange. Much policy discourse and reform associated with the development of welfare conditionality, especially in the UK, US and Australia, has emphasised a rebalancing of this hypothetical welfare contract away from the state’s obligations to provide welfare services, and towards citizens’ obligations to be contributing and responsible members of society (Crisp and Fletcher, Reference Crisp and Fletcher2008).

However, some philosophically-grounded contractualist accounts, not least those of John Rawls (Reference Rawls1999[1971]), emphasise the conditions that must be met in order for expectations of reciprocity on welfare recipients to hold. In this Rawlsian tradition, White (Reference White2003)Footnote 2 has argued that a series of background conditions of ‘fair reciprocity’ must pertain, including the minimisation of brute luck poverty, equality of opportunity, protection against discrimination, and income adequacy in exchange for productive participation (which extends beyond paid employment). On this view, the ethical legitimacy of conditional forms of welfare will depend upon the fairness of the imagined contract, and realities of the social arrangements in a particular context.

The contractualist impulse echoes the documented ubiquity of ideas of reciprocity and mutuality as constituents of morality across cultures and political divides (Graham et al., Reference Graham, Nosek, Haidt, Iyer, Koleva and Ditto2011). This ‘something for something’ ethical framing has a strong intuitive appeal amongst those coming from very different ideological standpoints (Miller, Reference Miller1999; Deacon, Reference Deacon2004), but the sort of exacting background conditions specified by White (Reference White2003) are seldom met in practice. Furthermore, Paz-Fuchs (Reference Paz-Fuchs2008) observes that the contractualist view seems to rest on an implausible assumption that those on either side of welfare contract – individuals on one side, the state on the other – have equal bargaining power. Contractualist thinking thus risks obfuscating very substantial power imbalances.

Communitaranism

Communitarians share contractualists’ emphasis on people’s obligations to one another, but reject the individualism of welfare contractualism in favour of an emphasis on community solidarity and cohesion (see Mulhall and Swift, Reference Mulhall and Swift1996; Etzioni, Reference Etzioni1997). Crucially, these mutual obligations are seen to arise independently of any background social conditions or required role of the state in setting a fair context. Instead, they are rooted in people’s pre-existing “personal responsibility for the common good” (Selznick, Reference Selznick and Etzioni1998, p.63). While communitarianism refers to a broad set of perspectives spanning the political Left and Right, they share a strong emphasis on the common good over concerns with individual freedom, rights or wellbeing.

Such communitarian-orientated analyses entail a pro-active role for the state and social policy in promoting (through sanctions, incentives, or other social control mechanisms) ways of life that are deemed to be in line with communally shared values (Mulhall and Swift, Reference Mulhall and Swift1996). The perspective therefore provides an obvious normative framework within which conditional approaches to welfare are justified as a means of enforcing key social rules, with regard, for example, to refraining from anti-social behaviour, undertaking paid work, ensuring that one’s children attend school, accepting relevant healthcare interventions, and so on. Communitarians tend not to see inequality in itself as a social problem (Selznick, Reference Selznick and Etzioni1998), though are sometimes concerned to minimise ‘social exclusion’ that threatens the community cohesion they value (Gray, Reference Gray, Askonas and Stewart2000). While this may put a limit on the severity of the sanctions employed in conditional forms of welfare, communitarian perspectives provide a uniquely strong logic for endorsing conditional approaches in societies that value reciprocity and mutuality.

Haidt (Reference Haidt2012) has argued that we neglect the community bonds that enable human beings to peaceably co-exist, at least for the most part, at our peril, capturing the core of the enduring appeal of communitarian ethics. As a moral code, however, some forms of communitarianism can lend themselves to authoritarian styles of governance that constrain individual liberty and entrench existing power imbalances, rendering them unattractive to those who value freedom and equality as cornerstones of a decent society.

Paternalism

Paternalism, like communitarianism, places a relatively lower value on individual liberty than some of the other normative perspectives reviewed, but drawing on the metaphor of the parent/child relationship, it foregrounds the pursuit of the best interests of welfare recipients, who are seen to be acting in ways that may subvert their own wellbeing (Deacon, Reference Deacon2004). A distinction can be drawn between hard paternalism, which employs forceful or coercive methods to induce people to act in ways considered to be in their own interests (Scoccia, Reference Scoccia2008), and libertarian paternalism that seeks to non-coercively ‘nudge’ people towards such behaviours (Thaler and Sunstein, Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008). Trading short-term pain for future gain is a key aspect of justifications for hard paternalist interventions especially, which seek to ‘save people from themselves’.

From the political Right, American political theorist Mead (Reference Mead1997) has sought to justify welfare conditionality on paternalist grounds. He views welfare claimants as ‘dutiful but defeated’ (Mead, Reference Mead1992) – that is, accepting of society’s mainstream work ethic but, in Paz-Fuchs rendering of this perspective “simply lack[ing] the will power to choose the better life” (Reference Paz-Fuchs2008, p.438). As such, they require ‘help and hassle’, i.e. to receive state support. Others coming from a very different perspective have argued that paternalistic interventions may be justified for vulnerable groups with high levels of identifiable support needs – for instance, people with serious addiction issues (Gregory, Reference Gregory2015; Watts et al, Reference Watts, Fitzpatrick and Johnsen2018).

Paternalism often provokes extreme ire in progressive circles, because it offends against the liberal principle that people are best placed to judge their own interests. Moreover, when applied via welfare provisions, it leaves the idle rich undisturbed by the attentions of the ‘tutelary state’. However, it is difficult to conceive of any ethical welfare system that would exclude paternalistic concern for vulnerable groups such as young children, but also adults with severely limited capacity. The relevant question is not, then, whether paternalism is justifiable, but what are its appropriate limits (Parsell and Marston, Reference Parsell and Marston2016) and how do these map on to the diverse groups targeted by specific conditional welfare policies.

Social Justice

The final normative lens considered here is that of social justice, best conceived as a place-holder for a diverse set of theories that hold in common the idea that ethical courses of action or policies must achieve an appropriate balance between a range of distributive criteria. Miller (Reference Miller1999) offers one compelling, multi-dimensional theory of social justice, arguing that a just distribution of societal resources requires that: first, need-meeting resources must be distributed according to need (with space for democratic deliberation on what these needs are in a given context); second, in their capacity as citizens, people must be treated as equals, including being given equal access to a range of legal, political and social rights; and third, beyond these (fairly onerous) parameters, many other social resources may be allocated on the basis of desert – for instance, rewarding people for working hard.

From this perspective, conditional forms of welfare can be ethically justified if they are introduced against a background of equality of opportunity that promotes meritocracy and dampens the effects of luck, and as long as they do not lead to people’s fundamental needs going unmet. This perspective thus constructs an ethically high bar for the just use of welfare conditionality, but does not imply an outright moral bar on such approaches. In fact, Miller’s theory could be argued to ethically require forms of conditionality that ensure that legitimate forms of deservingness are recognized, if the specified background conditions are met.

Miller’s social justice framework holds particular appeal from our overarching value pluralist perspective, as it pulls into one coherent whole key dimensions of some of the other normative perspectives outlined above. Specifically, it recognizes the powerful ethical appeal of the norms of reciprocity, desert and merit, often neglected in the context of the rights-dominance of mainstream social policy (see above), while at the same time acknowledging the importance of the core progressive principles of needs, rights and equality. Yet, as Miller himself acknowledges, even this multi-dimensional concept of justice is only one amongst several values that a good society must protect, and it may on occasion have to be traded-off in the name of other core values, including “democracy, individuality, or social harmony” (Reference Miller1999, p.17)

A pluralist assessment of the ethics of conditional welfare

The normative lenses highlighted above foreground different ethical priorities, and in many cases propose alternative decision-making procedures. How persuasive one finds each of these specific ethical perspectives, and particular combinations of them, will depend on one’s own personal underpinning ‘moral foundations’ (Haidt and Graham, Reference Haidt and Graham2007).

However, looping back to our introductory comments inspired by Galston (Reference Galston2002) and other value pluralists, we would contend that there is more scope for working across these competing normative outlooks in dealing with real-world policy dilemmas than is sometimes assumed, with people often agreeing on what is ethically justified in specific cases via very different (even opposing) processes of moral reasoning. We would make the case that policy choices are most defensible where their aims and consequences can be considered as legitimate from multiple normative perspectives (Carens, Reference Carens1987; Deacon, Reference Deacon2004). For value pluralists, such an ‘overlapping consensus’ (Rawls, Reference Rawls1999[1971]) strengthens the ethical weight of any given normative conclusions as a matter of philosophical principle (Galston, Reference Galston2002). But even for non-pluralists, such ‘moral triangulation’, or ‘incompletely theorized agreement’ (Sunstein, Reference Sunstein1995), has profound democratic and strategic benefits.

Nonetheless, there will be occasions where ethical perspectives clash rather than triangulate on concrete cases of concern, pointing in different directions with regard to the justifiability or otherwise of underlying policy aims and impacts. A value pluralist conceptual analysis will not always reveal ‘hidden consensus’ on relevant matters, but will also surface irreconcilable divergence. Even in these more difficult cases, however, pluralist approaches have something important to offer in the way of constructive tools for moving debate forward.

Critical here is the pluralist readiness to engage protagonists on their own terms, testing the logical and empirical foundations of their arguments, rather than getting mired in irresolvable disagreements about fundamental values. For example, opponents of conditional welfare are on indisputably firm ground challenging utilitarian advocates to evidence that these measures do in fact maximise societal utility, while a sincere paternalist can fairly be held to account on whether conditional policies do in reality benefit those targeted. Similar empirical claims or contingencies can be identified within all plausible normative frames, and establishing an agreed evidence base on these is a key first step in moving past an unproductive debate.

Proponents of conditional welfare approaches, from whatever normative perspective, must also demonstrate a logical connection between the policy aims they seek and the use of behavioural conditions as a means to these ends. In other words, are there good grounds for believing that the behaviour change sought (e.g. more job search activity) is genuinely a solution to the social problem that the intervention seeks to address (e.g. unemployment)? They must have a convincing answer to the criticism made by many, for example, that an emphasis on welfare conditionality in out-of-work benefits implies a misdiagnosis of a fundamental structural problem (weak labour demand) for a behavioural problem (unwillingness to work) (Beatty and Fothergill, Reference Beatty and Fothergill2016).

If the social problem at issue can be empirically defended as in significant part behavioural, the ethical justifiability of welfare conditionality is also dependent on there being plausible grounds for thinking that sanction-backed requirements will in fact lead to the behaviour change desired. Relevant here is the challenge laid down by behavioural economists who have highlighted the cognitive biases and boundaries that limit expected rational responses to behavioural cues such as sanctions (Darnton, Reference Darnton2008). These social-psychological complexities require policy designers to take seriously the worldview, context and actual decision-making processes of the individuals whose behaviour they seek to influence (Curchin, Reference Curchin2017). At the very least, it requires concerted efforts to ensure that welfare recipients understand the relevant behavioural demands, and have the resources and capacity to fulfil them, and evidence that they have fulfilled them. It also requires recognising, for instance, the impact of trauma, addiction and mental health conditions on people’s ability to respond predictably when exposed to stressors or triggers. Existing evidence suggests that conditional welfare interventions, in the UK at least, often fail these basic tests of efficacy (Griggs and Evans, Reference Griggs and Evans2010; Oakley, Reference Oakley2014; Wright and Stewart, Reference Wright and Stewart2016).

The international evidence base on the impacts of welfare conditionality is limited in important respects, and is also mixed. For example, it is clear from the US case that harsh forms of conditionality attached to out-of-work benefits can effectively drive down the claimant count (Ray et al., Reference Ray, Sissons, Jones and Vegeris2014). But if no regard is had to the destination or well-being of those ‘hassled off’ welfare programmes, this is difficult to justify within most normative perspectives, except perhaps those versions of communitarianism which give overriding priority to the enforcement of key social rules regardless of the consequences for social exclusion, or in a utilitarian calculus that weighs public approval of such rules much more heavily than their impacts on those subject to them. With regard to programme goals that might be considered respectable from a wider range of moral standpoints, such as improved labour market outcomes and poverty reduction, the evidence base is highly variable. Some studies across the US and Europe point to positive impacts of conditionality on levels of work search, employment entry and earnings, while others identify no or negative impacts (Griggs and Evans, Reference Griggs and Evans2010; Ray et al., Reference Ray, Sissons, Jones and Vegeris2014), or only short-term positive effects (Hofmann, Reference Hofmann2008; Müller and Steiner, Reference Müller and Steiner2008; Arni et al., Reference Arni, Lalive and van Ours2009).

In the case of CCTs in the Global South, a stronger evidence base, often involving randomised control trials, suggests that well designed CCTs can be effective in achieving programme goals – around, for example, school enrolment and attendance, and reductions in child labour (Bastagli, Reference Bastagli2009; Fiszbein et al., Reference Fiszbein, Schady, Ferreira, Grosh, Keleher, Olinto and Skoufias2009; Kabeer et al., Reference Kabeer, Piza and Taylor2012; Pellerano and Barca, Reference Pellerano and Barca2014). Even here, however, there is ongoing debate regarding whether the conditionality of the cash transfers is key to these positive impacts, or whether they could be achieved by alternative less coercive means, including the provision of ‘unconditional’ benefits (Baird et al., Reference Baird, Ferreira, Özler and Woolcock2014; Kidd, Reference Kidd2016).

Any evidence demonstrating the effectiveness of conditional interventions in achieving their intended aims must be placed in the context of wider unintended impacts (both positive and negative). Here it is apt to note that, in both the US and UK, harsh forms of benefit sanctions have been associated with material hardships including food poverty, debt, rent arrears, homelessness, and destitution (Lindhorst and Mancoske, Reference Lindhorst and Mancoske2006; Loopstra et al., Reference Loopstra, Reeves, Taylor-Robinson, Barr, McKee and Stuckler2015; Wright and Stewart, Reference Wright and Stewart2016; Reeve, Reference Reeve2017; Fitzpatrick et al., Reference Fitzpatrick, Bramley, Sosenko, Blenkinsopp, Wood, Johnsen, Littlewood and Watts2018), and negative physical and mental health outcomes (Griggs and Evans, Reference Griggs and Evans2010; Dwyer, Reference Dwyer2018). Such findings seriously challenge the utilitarian and paternalistic case for these strong sanctions, and probably the contractualist case too, at least as regards those theorists concerned with the fairness of the imagined social contract (White, Reference White2003). These negative impacts may even be seen to undermine the potential communitarian argument for strict sanctioning regimes, given their exclusionary consequences (Gray, Reference Gray, Askonas and Stewart2000); they certainly seem fatal to any plausible social justice-based defence of these measures.

Concluding remarks

The core aim of this paper has been to advocate for the application of a value pluralist perspective to ethical questions in social policy. By offering a means to map systematically the diversity of moral registers within which social policy concerns might legitimately be considered, we would argue that this pragmatic pluralist approach can aid constructive policy dialogue and decision making. There are practical, democratic and strategic grounds to adopt a value pluralist analytical approach, even if in philosophical terms one remains a ‘monist’ wedded to a singular ethical measure or meta-value. A pluralist approach helps provide tools for the development of robust policies that are ethically permissible from multiple normative perspectives. Such moral triangulation, where possible, offers the surest means to pursue policy options that gain the widest public endorsement. Moreover, serious attempts at moral triangulation, even where not fully realised, shine a bright analytical light on genuine areas of irreconcilable difference, as well as on areas of (hidden) agreement, in order to maximise clarity and mutual comprehension on both. Confronting relevant matters from multiple plausible moral perspectives increases the rigour, thoroughness and scope of the ethical evaluation task.

For case study purposes, we have explored the potential contribution of six key normative lenses – rights, utilitarianism, contractualism, communitarianism, paternalism and social justice – in considering the ethical legitimacy of welfare conditionality. We have elucidated the implications of each of these perspectives for assessing the ethics of conditional welfare approaches, and sought to pull out the empirical claims and logical assumptions on which their support for or critique of such approaches depends. Rigorous testing of these non-normative elements is an invaluable first step in bringing diverse starting positions closer together when applied to concrete policy choices.

One key conclusion of our substantive case study analysis is that there is unlikely to be a single, consistent answer to the question of whether welfare conditionality is ethically ‘justified’. Much turns on the context, focus, rationale and, most crucially, impacts of the specific instance of conditionality under discussion. As argued above, the harshest forms of benefit sanctions found in the US and UK are difficult to justify under most (though not necessarily all) plausible normative frameworks. However, this is far from ruling out the possibility of a broader ‘overlapping consensus’ of support for milder forms of conditionality that can be empirically demonstrated to benefit welfare recipients and/or wider society. Some of the CCT programmes in the Global South reviewed above may come into this category, for example, and one can envisage utilitarian, contractualist, communitiarian, paternalist and social justice arguments triangulating in support of at least some such programmes. Only those rights-based theorists, currently so dominant in UK social policy, that reject conditional welfare approaches as a matter of principle, regardless of their practical consequences, may stand outside such an overlapping consensus.

We hope to have demonstrated the utility of the value pluralist approach in contentious areas of social policy, and also that a great deal of the consensus-building work in a field like welfare conditionality can take a non-normative form, by establishing the relevant factual basis for decision making and expounding the logical consequences that flow from particular value commitments. In many cases, protagonists coming from very different moral orientations may find themselves drawing similar substantive conclusions on concrete policy questions. It is true that “pockets of indeterminacy” (Wolf, Reference Wolf1992, p.788) will remain even after all these avenues for reasoned debate have been exhausted. Berlin’s ‘tragic choices’ thus cannot be avoided altogether but they can be greatly narrowed in scope.

Competing interests

The author(s) declare none

Footnotes

1 Beem and Mead (Reference Beem, Mead, Mead and Beem2005) and Wolff (Reference Wolff2015) have argued from the other side that political and moral philosophers have not engaged sufficiently or in the right ways with questions of public policy.

2 We consider White here as an example of a contractualist perspective given the core relevance of the idea of a welfare contract to his work. We also recognise the influence of communitarianism, and Etzioni specifically, on White’s thinking. Within our categorisation, and given his concern with equality and reciprocity, White could also be considered as a social justice theorist.

References

Arni, P., Lalive, R. and van Ours, J. (2009), How effective are unemployment benefit sanctions? Looking Beyond Unemployment Exit. IZA Discussion Paper No. 4509. Bonn: The Institute for the Study of Labor (IZA).Google Scholar
Baird, S., Ferreira, F., Özler, B. and Woolcock, M. (2014), Conditional, unconditional and everything in between: a systematic review of the effects of cash transfer programmes on schooling outcomes. Journal of Development Effectiveness, 6(1), 143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bastagli, F. (2009), Conditionality in public policy targeted to the poor: promoting resilience? Social Policy and Society, 8(1), 127140.10.1017/S1474746408004648CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatty, C. and Fothergill, S. (2016), Jobs, Welfare and Austerity: How the destruction of industrial Britain casts a shadow over present-day public finances. Sheffield: CRESR, Sheffield Hallam University.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beem, C. and Mead, L. (2005), Introduction. In Mead, L. and Beem, C. (Eds.), Welfare Reform and Political Theory (pp. 19), New York: Russell Sage.Google Scholar
Berlin, I. (2002). Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.1093/019924989X.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carens, J. H. (1987), Aliens and citizens: the case for open borders. The review of politics, 49(2), 251273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, R. and Fletcher, D. R. (2008), A comparative review of workfare programmes in the United States, Canada and Australia (No. 533). London: Department for Work and Pensions.Google Scholar
Curchin, K. (2017), Using behavioural insights to argue for a stronger social safety net: Beyond libertarian paternalism. Journal of Social Policy, 46(2), 231249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curchin, K. (2019), The Illiberalism of Behavioural Conditionality: A Critique of Australia’s ‘No Jab, No Pay’Policy. Journal of Social Policy, 48(4), 789805.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curchin, K., Weight, T., & Ritter, A. (2021), Moral framings in the Australian parliamentary debate on drug testing of welfare recipients. Social Policy & Administration. https://doi.org/10.1111/spol.12774 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darnton, A. (2008), GSR Behaviour Change Knowledge Review - Reference Report: An overview of behaviour change models and their uses. Government Social Research.Google Scholar
Deacon, A. (2004), Justifying conditionality: the case of anti-social tenants, Housing Studies, 19(6), 911926.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dean, H. (2015), Social rights and human welfare. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunn, A. (2014), Rethinking unemployment and the work ethic: beyond the ‘quasi-Titmuss’ paradigm. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan.10.1057/9781137032119CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, R. (1977), Taking Rights Seriously. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
Dwyer, P. (2000). Welfare Rights and Responsibilities: Contesting Social Citizenship. Bristol, Policy Press.Google Scholar
Dwyer, P. (2004), Creeping conditionality in the UK: from welfare rights to conditional entitlements, Canadian Journal or Sociology, 29(2), 265287.Google Scholar
Dwyer, P. (2018), Final findings report: Welfare Conditionality 2013-2018. York: University of York.Google Scholar
Dwyer, P. and Wright, S. (2014), Universal credit, ubiquitous conditionality and its implications for social citizenship. Journal of Poverty and Social Justice, 22(1), 2735.10.1332/175982714X13875305151043CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Etzioni, A. (1997) The New Golden Rule. London: Profile Books.Google Scholar
Fiszbein, A. and Schady, N. R. with Ferreira, F., Grosh, M., Keleher, N, Olinto, P. and Skoufias, E. (2009), Conditional cash transfers: reducing present and future poverty. Washington: The World Bank.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, C., McKeever, G. and Simpson, M. (2019), Conditionality, discretion and TH Marshall’s ‘right to welfare’, Journal of Social Welfare and Family Law, 41(4), 445462, DOI: 10.1080/09649069.2019.1663016 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, S., Bengtsson, B. and Watts, B. (2014), Rights to housing: reviewing the terrain and exploring a way forward. Housing, theory and society, 31(4), 447463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitzpatrick, S., Bramley, G., Sosenko, F., Blenkinsopp, J., Wood, J., Johnsen, S., Littlewood, M. and Watts, B. (2018), Destitution in the UK 2018. York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation.Google Scholar
Freeland, N. (2007), Superfluous, pernicious, atrocious and abominable? The case against conditional cash transfers. IDS Bulletin, 38(3), 7578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabriel, I. (2017), Effective altruism and its critics. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 34(4), 457473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Galston, W. A. (2002), Liberal pluralism: The implications of value pluralism for political theory and practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, R. E. (1993), Utility and the good. In Singer, P. (Ed.), A Companion to Ethics (pp. 241–48), Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Koleva, S. and Ditto, P. H. (2011), Mapping the moral domain. Journal of personality and social psychology, 101(2), 366.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, J. (2000), Inclusion: a radical critique. In Askonas, P. and Stewart, A. (Eds.) Social Inclusion: Possibilities and Tensions, (pp. 1936), Basingstoke: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Gregory, J. (2015), Engineering compassion: the institutional structure of virtue. Journal of Social Policy, 44(2), 339356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griggs, J. and Evans, M. (2010), Sanctions within conditional benefit systems: A review of evidence. York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. (2012), The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Haidt, J. and Graham, J. (2007), When morality opposes justice: Conservatives have moral intuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social Justice Research, 20(1), 98116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. C. (1982), Morality and the theory of rational behaviour. In Sen, A. and Williams, B. (Eds,), Utilitarianism and beyond (pp.3962), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hofmann, B. (2008), Work Incentives? Ex-post Effects of Unemployment Sanctions: Evidence from West Germany. IAB Discussion Paper 43/2008. Nuremburg: IAB.Google Scholar
Ignatieff, M. (2000), I. Human Rights as Politics; II. Human Rights as Idolatry. Paper Presented at the Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University.Google Scholar
Immervoll, H. and Knotz, C. (2018), “How demanding are activation requirements for jobseekers”, OECD Social, Employment and Migration Working Papers, No. 215, OECD Publishing, Paris, https://doi.org/10.1787/2bdfecca-en.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Immervoll, H., Knotz, C. and Otmani, I. (2020), “Activity-related Eligibility Conditions For Receiving Unemployment Benenfits”, OECD, https://www.oecd.org/els/soc/Activity-related%20eligibility%20conditions_2020.pdf.Google Scholar
Kabeer, N., Piza, C. and Taylor, L. (2012), What are the economic impacts of conditional cash transfer programmes? A systematic review of the evidence. Technical report. London: EPPI-Centre, Social Science Research Unit, Institute of Education, University of London.Google Scholar
Kidd, S. (2016), To Condition or Not to Condition: What is the Evidence? Pathways’ perspectives on social policy in international development, Issue 20. http://www.developmentpathways.co.uk/resources/to-condition-or-not-to-condition-what-is-the-evidence/ Google Scholar
Kymlicka, W. (2002), Contemporary Political Philosophy: an Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lindhorst, T. and Mancoske, R. J. (2006), The social and economic impact of sanctions and time limits on recipients of temporary assistance to needy families. Journal of sociology and social welfare, 33(1), 93114.Google ScholarPubMed
Loopstra, R., Reeves, A., Taylor-Robinson, D., Barr, B., McKee, M. and Stuckler, D. (2015), Austerity, sanctions, and the rise of food banks in the UK. BMJ (Clinical research ed), 350, h1775.Google ScholarPubMed
McNeill, F. (2020), Penal and welfare conditionality: Discipline or degradation?. Social Policy & Administration, 54(2), 295310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mead, L. (1986), Beyond Entitlement: The Social Obligations of Citizenship. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Mead, L. (1992), The new politics of poverty: The nonworking poor in America. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Mead, L. (1997), The New Paternalism. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.Google Scholar
Miller, D. (1999), Principles of Social Justice. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Miscampbell, G. (2014), Smarter sanctions: Sorting out the system. London: Policy Exchange.Google Scholar
Mulhall, S. and Swift, A. (1996), Liberals and communitarians. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Müller, K-U. and Steiner, V. (2008), Imposed Benefit Sanctions and the Unemployment to Employment Transition: The German Experience. IZA Discussion Paper No. 3483. Bonn: The institute for the Study of Labor (IZA).Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (1979), ‘The fragmentation of value’, pp.128141 in Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. (2021), ‘Types of intuition’, London Review of Books, June, pp. 3–8.Google Scholar
Nevile, A. (2008), Human rights, power and welfare conditionality. Australian Journal of Human Rights, 14(1), 120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oakley, M. (2014), Independent Review of the Operation of Jobseeker’s Allowance Sanctions Validated by the Jobseekers Act 2013. London: Her Majesty’s Stationery Office.Google Scholar
Parsell, C. and Marston, G. (2016), Supportive housing: justifiable paternalism? Housing, Theory and Society, 33(2), 195216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paz-Fuchs, A. (2008), Behind the contract for welfare reform: Antecedent themes in welfare to work programs. Berkeley Journal of Employment and Labour Law, 29(2), 405454.Google Scholar
Pellerano, L. and Barca, V. (2014), Does one size fit all? The Conditions for Conditionality in Cash Transfers. Oxford Policy Management Working Paper. Oxford: OPM.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. (1999[1971]), A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ray, K., Sissons, P., Jones, K. and Vegeris, S. (2014), Employment, Pay and Poverty: evidence and policy review. York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation.Google Scholar
Redman, J. (2020), The benefit sanction: a correctional device or a weapon of disgust?. Sociological Research Online, 25(1), 84100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeve, K. (2017), Welfare conditionality, benefit sanctions and homelessness in the UK: ending the ‘something for nothing culture’ or punishing the poor? Journal of Poverty and Social Justice, 25(1), 6578.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeves, A. and Loopstra, R. (2017). ‘Set up to fail’? How welfare conditionality undermines citizenship for vulnerable groups. Social Policy and Society, 16(2), 327338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryan, F. (2014), ‘David Clapson’s awful death was the result of grotesque government policies’, Guardian, 9th September: https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/sep/09/david-clapson-benefit-sanctions-death-government-policies Google Scholar
Sadeghi, T. and Terum, L. I. (2020), Frontline managers’ perceptions and justifications of behavioural conditionality. Social Policy & Administration, 54(2), 219235.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scoccia, D. (2008), In defense of hard paternalism. Law and Philosophy, 27(4), 351381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selznick, P. (1998), Social justice: a communitarian perspective, in Etzioni, A. (ed) The Essential Communitarian Reader, 6172. Oxford: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
Standing, G. (2011), Behavioural conditionality: why the nudges must be stopped–an opinion piece. Journal of Poverty and Social Justice, 19(1)., 2738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. (1995), Incompletely theorized agreements. Harvard law review, 108(7), 17331772.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, D. R., Gray, M. and Stanton, D. (2016), New conditionality in Australian social security policy. Australian Journal of Social Issues, 51(1), 326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thaler, R. and Sunstein, C. (2008), Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth and happiness. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Titmuss, R. (2018[1970]), The gift relationship (reissue): From human blood to social policy. Bristol: Policy Press.Google Scholar
Veit-Wilson, J. (2009), Who sets the conditions? Conditionality, reciprocity, human rights and inclusion in society. Global Social Policy, 9(2), 171174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, J. (1993), Liberal Rights: Collected Papers. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Watts, B. and Fitzpatrick, S. (2018), Welfare conditionality. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watts, B., Fitzpatrick, S. and Johnsen, S. (2018), Controlling homeless people? Power, interventionism and legitimacy. Journal of Social Policy, 47(2), 235252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, S. (2003), The Civic Minimum: On the Rights and Obligations of Economic Citizenship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolf, S. (1992), Two levels of pluralism. Ethics, 102(4), 785798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, J. (2015), Political philosophy and the real world of the welfare state. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 32(4), 360372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, S., Dwyer, P., Jones, K., McNeill, J., Scullion, L., & Stewart, A. B. (2018), Final findings: Universal credit. Project Report. Welfare Conditionality. York: University of York.Google Scholar
Wright, S., Fletcher, D. R. and Stewart, A. B. (2020), Punitive benefit sanctions, welfare conditionality, and the social abuse of unemployed people in Britain: Transforming claimants into offenders?. Social Policy & Administration, 54(2), 278294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, S. and Stewart, A. (2016), First Wave Findings: Jobseekers. Project Report. Welfare Conditionality. York: University of York.Google Scholar