Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-pftt2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-02T02:11:24.932Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Part I - The Case for Wellbeing

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 May 2023

Richard Layard
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
Jan-Emmanuel De Neve
Affiliation:
University of Oxford

Summary

Type
Chapter
Information
Wellbeing
Science and Policy
, pp. 15 - 52
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2023
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BYCreative Common License - NCCreative Common License - ND
This content is Open Access and distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0 https://creativecommons.org/cclicenses/

1 What Subjective Wellbeing Is and Why It Matters

The gross national product measures everything except that which makes life worthwhile.

Robert Kennedy
Subjective Wellbeing as the Overarching Good

The idea of wellbeing as the ultimate good is not new. But now it is coming to the fore, for many reasons. One is the new science of wellbeing. But another is the growing disbelief that higher incomes alone will solve all our problems.

The movement in favour of going ‘beyond GDP’ has taken many forms. For the last fifty years, there has been a strong movement of scholars producing ‘social indicators’ in addition to GDP. In parallel with this, the Nobel-prize-winning economist Amartya Sen has set out the many ‘capabilities’ that a person needs to function well.Footnote 1 Following this, the OECD has developed a range of ‘wellbeing indicators’ for member countries, which include not only standard measures of education, health and so on but also psychological measures.Footnote 2 This work has inspired the New Zealand government to adopt wellbeing as its goal and to join a multi-country alliance known as Wellbeing Economy Governments.Footnote 3

At the same time, the world has been shocked by the climate emergency, which has underlined the short-sightedness of maximising current GDP, without regard to the more distant future. To deal with this problem, the UN’s 17 Sustainable Development Goals for 2030 look firmly to the future but they also enshrine a much broader view than the purely economic of what it is to be human.

There is, however, one central problem that still faces every policymaker. If you have multiple goals, how do you choose between alternative policies? Policy A may be better than Policy B in terms of one objective and worse in terms of another. How are you to choose?

Coherent choice is only possible if you have a single objective, in terms of which all alternative policies can be ranked. We need a ‘common currency’ for decision-making. One way to have one is to construct an index that is a weighted average of all the different objectives. But you still have to choose the weights. They can only be found by having a single objective that can determine the weights.

What might that single objective be? The most obvious answer is ‘how people feel about their lives’. This is what we mean when we talk about ‘subjective wellbeing’ (sometimes called SWB).

However, say some critics, feelings can’t be that important because they are ‘only subjective’. Are they right? There are of course many other things that are good, including health, income, freedom, respect and peace. For each of these things, you can ask people what makes it good, and people can generally give answers. For example, health matters because people feel awful when they are sick. Similarly, most other goods are good because of how they affect our felt experience. But why does it matter how people feel? No reason can be given – it self-evidently does. So when people advocate wellbeing, they are thinking of it as the ultimate good, with other things being good if they are instrumental in contributing to wellbeing. This basic idea was illustrated in Figure I.1 in the Introduction.

So the wellbeing approach builds upon the approaches where people specify multiple objectives – the ‘dashboard’ approach.Footnote 4 But it goes a lot further. It offers a vision of a society where the ultimate touchstone is the quality of people’s lives as they themselves experience them. It says that the wellbeing of the people should be the goal for a society, for its policymakers and for us as individuals. If you find this idea problematic, you might try to think of a better alternative goal.

One further point. In the wellbeing approach, what matters is the overall wellbeing of everyone. So this approach is not saying that people should pursue only their own wellbeing. On the contrary, it is saying that each individual and each organisation should do what it can to produce the greatest overall wellbeing in society.

How Should We Measure It?

But how should wellbeing be measured? There are three main conceptions of wellbeing that have been measured:Footnote 5

  • Evaluative (life satisfaction),

  • Hedonic, and

  • Eudaimonic.

Evaluative measures: The life satisfaction approach

In the first of these, people are asked how they feel about their life these days. The most common question is ‘Overall, how satisfied are you with your life nowadays?’Footnote 6 To answer it, individuals have to choose a score between 0 and 10, where 0 means ‘Not as all satisfied’ and 10 means ‘Very satisfied’. This is a question on life satisfaction. Alternatively (which gives very similar answers), people are offered a continuous line with the same answers at either end, and they are asked to mark where their answer lies in between. The results of using a ‘visual analogue scale’ like this are very similar to those from whole-number answers between 0 and 10 – both in terms of the score recorded and the factors that explain it.Footnote 7 The results are also similar when, the phrase ‘satisfied with your life’ is replaced by the phrase ‘happy with your life’.Footnote 8

In another variant, people are asked the following question, known as the Cantril ladder question:

Please imagine a ladder, with steps numbered from 0 at the bottom to 10 at the top. The top of the ladder represents the best possible life for you and the bottom of the ladder represents the worst possible life for you. On which step of the ladder would you say you personally feel you stand at this time?

The World Happiness Report uses the answers to the Cantril ladder question given when people reply in the Gallup World Poll.Footnote 9 This poll covers over a thousand people a year per country, in nearly every country. In surveys where people were asked both about life satisfaction and the Cantril ladder they were very highly correlated.Footnote 10 So for ease of language we shall describe the results of the Cantril ladder as ‘life satisfaction’.

The Gallup World Poll shows the huge spread of life satisfaction both within countries and between countries. For illustration, Figure 1.1 gives the spread in the United States and in India. Some key facts emerge:

  • In each country there is a very wide spread of life satisfaction. This corresponds to our own experience, across the range of people we meet.

  • The average of life satisfaction is much higher in the United States than in India.

There is indeed a huge variation of life satisfaction within any country, and this within-country variation actually accounts for 78% of the overall variance in life satisfaction across the world’s population.Footnote 11 Exploring the within-country variation provides key information about the personal factors that matter most in human life (see Chapter 8). For example, as we shall see, income differences explain some 2% of the variance of life satisfaction within countries – much less than the 20% explained by mental health, physical health and human relationships. (Somewhat surprisingly, average life satisfaction in most countries is very similar for men and women.)

Figure 1.1 Percentage at each level of life satisfaction (0–10): United States and India

Source: Gallup World Poll 2016–2018, Cantril ladder

There are, however, also huge differences in average life satisfaction across countries. This is shown in Table 1.1,Footnote 12 which reveals the extraordinary variation in the human condition around the world. Average wellbeing is evaluated at 7.5 or above in four Scandinavian countries and at 3.5 or below in war-torn countries like Syria, Yemen, Afghanistan, the Central African Republic and South Sudan. Explaining this variation provides many clues to the social factors that matter most in human life (see also Chapter 8).

Table 1.1 Ranking of countries by their average life satisfaction (0–10)

1Finland7.8Philippines6.0Niger4.9
Denmark7.6Hungary6.0Laos4.9
Switzerland7.6Thailand6.0Albania4.9
Iceland7.5Argentina6.0Cambodia4.8
Norway7.5Honduras6.0Bangladesh4.8
Netherlands7.4Latvia5.9Gabon4.8
Sweden7.4Ecuador5.9South Africa4.8
New Zealand7.3Portugal5.9110Iraq4.8
Austria7.360Jamaica5.9Lebanon4.8
10Luxembourg7.2South Korea5.9Burkina Faso4.8
Canada7.2Japan5.9Gambia4.8
Australia7.2Peru5.8Mali4.7
United Kingdom7.2Serbia5.8Nigeria4.7
Israel7.1Bolivia5.7Armenia4.7
Costa Rica7.1Pakistan5.7Georgia4.7
Ireland7.1Paraguay5.7Iran4.7
Germany7.1Dominican Republic5.7Jordan4.6
United States6.9Bosnia and Herzegovina5.7120Mozambique4.6
Czech Republic6.970Moldova5.6Kenya4.6
20Belgium6.9Tajikistan5.6Namibia4.6
United Arab Emirates6.8Montenegro5.5Ukraine4.6
Malta6.8Russia5.5Liberia4.6
France6.7Kyrgyzstan5.5Palestinian Territories4.6
Mexico6.5Belarus5.5Uganda4.4
Taiwan Province of China6.5North Cyprus5.5Chad4.4
Uruguay6.4Greece5.5Tunisia4.4
Saudi Arabia6.4Hong Kong S.A.R. of China5.5Mauritania4.4
Spain6.4Croatia5.5130Sri Lanka4.3
Guatemala6.480Libya5.5Congo (Kinshasa)4.3
30Italy6.4Mongolia5.5Swaziland4.3
Singapore6.4Malaysia5.4Myanmar4.3
Brazil6.4Vietnam5.4Comoros4.3
Slovenia6.4Indonesia5.3Togo4.2
El Salvador6.3Ivory Coast5.2Ethiopia4.2
Kosovo6.3Benin5.2Madagascar4.2
Panama6.3Maldives5.2Egypt4.2
Slovakia6.3Congo (Brazzaville)5.2Sierra Leone3.9
Uzbekistan6.3Azerbaijan5.2140Burundi3.8
Chile6.290Macedonia5.2Zambia3.8
40Bahrain6.2Ghana5.1Haiti3.7
Lithuania6.2Nepal5.1Lesotho3.7
Trinidad and Tobago6.2Turkey5.1India3.6
Poland6.2China5.1Malawi3.5
Colombia6.2Turkmenistan5.1Yemen3.5
Cyprus6.2Bulgaria5.1Botswana3.5
Nicaragua6.1Morocco5.1Tanzania3.5
Romania6.1Cameroon5.1Central African Republic3.5
Kuwait6.1Venezuela5.1150Rwanda3.3
Mauritius6.1100Algeria5.0Zimbabwe3.3
50Kazakhstan6.1Senegal5.0South Sudan2.8
Estonia6.0Guinea4.9Afghanistan2.6
Source: Helliwell et al (Reference Helliwell, Layard and Sachs2020) Gallup World Poll 2017–2019, Cantril ladder

One obvious question is, ‘Has wellbeing increased over time, as living standards have risen?’ The answer is in some cases yes and in others no. For the world as a whole, average wellbeing rose between the 1970s and 2007.Footnote 13 Since then, however, it has stagnated.Footnote 14 And in some countries wellbeing has not risen since research began. This is true of the United States (since the 1950s), West Germany (since the 1970s) and China (since 1990).Footnote 15 Figure 1.2 shows the figures for the United States.

If only we knew more about trends in wellbeing in earlier periods.Footnote 16 There is certainly strong evidence that most of the external conditions of life are now better than in most of human history. As Stephen Pinker has shown,Footnote 17 there is less violence, better human rights and so on. So in most parts of the world, life is probably as good now as it has ever been.

Figure 1.2 Average happiness in the United States (on a scale of 1–3)

Source: AIPO (1956–1970); NORC (1963–1976); GSS (1972–2018) grafted together onto the GSS scale based on overlapping years (see online Annex 1.1)
Hedonic measures based on ‘affect’

Our findings so far are based on people’s replies to a single question about how respondents evaluate their life ‘nowadays’.Footnote 18 But some people prefer a different approach to the study of human wellbeing – where we study more directly how people feel at the time. By comparison with this, the evaluative measures cover a longer unspecified period of time and involve an element of judgment (although they are generally completed within a few seconds).Footnote 19

The alternative measures are known as hedonic measures (from the Greek word hedone meaning pleasure). Psychologists use the word ‘affect’ to describe feelings of different sorts. Some types of affect are positive (happiness, enjoyment, laughter) and some are negative (worry, sadness, anger and stress). There are three main ways to capture these feelings. One is in real time by beeping people and asking how they are feeling just now (Ecological Momentary Assessment). The second is to sit people down a day later and have them record how they felt on the previous day hour by hour – and what they were doing and who they were with (the Day Reconstruction Method). The third, also used by the Gallup World Poll, is to ask them to summarise their different feelings over the previous day by asking Yes/No questions like ‘Yesterday did you experience a lot of happiness?’

How people feel when they are doing different things is hugely interesting. A team led by Daniel Kahneman used the Day Reconstruction Method to investigate the feelings of around 900 Texan women during the course of the previous day.Footnote 20 Table 1.2 shows what they enjoyed most and what they enjoyed least.

Table 1.2 Happiness in different activities

ActivityAverage happinessAverage hours a day
Sex4.70.2
Socialising4.02.3
Relaxing3.92.2
Praying/worshipping/meditating3.80.4
Eating3.82.2
Exercising3.80.2
Watching TV3.62.2
Shopping3.20.4
Preparing food3.21.1
Talking on the phone3.12.5
Taking care of my children3.01.1
Computer/email/internet3.01.9
Housework3.01.1
Working2.76.9
Commuting2.61.6
Source: Kahneman et al. (Reference Kahneman, Krueger, Schkade, Schwarz and Stone2004) Table 1. 900 Texan women

Note: Day Reconstruction Method. Average happiness is measured by the difference between positive affect (0–6) and negative affect (0–6). For similar studies on the United States, see Krueger (Reference Krueger2009) and on the United Kingdom, see Bryson and McKerron (Reference Bryson and MacKerron2017). For further evidence of the effects of sex on happiness, see Blanchflower and Oswald (Reference Blanchflower and Oswald2004).

Such information is highly relevant to how each of us can improve our daily life.Footnote 21 And, in principle, hedonic measures could be used to produce a single measure of wellbeing over a period of time. You could either pick a single question (such as How happy are you right now, or yesterday) or you can calculate an ‘affect balance’ by adding up all the positive scores and subtracting all the negative ones.Footnote 22 Or, altogether novel, you can analyse people’s social media activity (especially Twitter) and calculate the balance between positive and negative words or remarks.Footnote 23 Or you can analyse Google searches.

Comparison of evaluative and hedonic measures

So which of the two preceding criteria is best for use as a guide to the choice of policies? As we argued at the beginning of the chapter, it self-evidently matters how people feel. This is extremely obvious when it comes to pain versus contentment/enjoyment (the ‘hedonic’ dimension of experience). But it also applies to how people ‘feel about their life’ (the ‘evaluative’ dimension).

As a measure of wellbeing, life satisfaction has many good features. First, it covers more than a day or two.Footnote 24 Second, researchers and policymakers know what it means – it is based on a single question that they themselves could answer. Third, it is democratic – it does not require analysts to compile a list of indicators and then use their own arbitrary weights to produce an overall index.Footnote 25 Instead, each citizen applies her own weights and tells us the result – how she feels about her life. And fourth, policymakers are used to asking people how satisfied they are with their services, so why not ask people how satisfied they are with their lives?

Hedonic measures are an even more direct measure of experience, but they are much more difficult to collect over a long enough period to be relevant to many basic social issues. They are, however, essential in analysing brief experiences – like a country walk or a game of tennis or a gig. And, as science develops, they will become easier and easier to measure (including via the use of biomarkers – see Chapter 5). So, in this book, we use both life satisfaction and hedonic measures but mainly life satisfaction. When possible, we report where the two approaches yield different results.Footnote 26

Eudaimonic measures

The third wellbeing measure in common use is usually called ‘eudaimonic’ after the word ‘eudaimonia’ used by the Greek philosopher Aristotle. Eudaimonia is difficult to translate but it means literally having a ‘good demon’, which Aristotle understood, roughly, as having a rounded and virtuous character.Footnote 27 So it includes the idea that virtue ought to be included in any measure of wellbeing. A typical question is ‘Do you feel that the things you do in your life are worthwhile?’

There are, however, two objections to this approach. First, virtue is difficult to measure. If you want to know whether someone is virtuous, you cannot find out by asking that person – the Nazis felt that what they did was positive and worthwhile. Second, in the wellbeing approach, virtue is a means to an end.

We want people to be virtuous for two reasons: it will raise the wellbeing of others, and it will often (though not always) raise the wellbeing of the virtuous person. So, for example, in Figure I.1, my wellbeing is higher if

  1. (i) the people I meet – my ‘social connections’ – are virtuous, and

  2. (ii) I myself have good altruistic ‘values’.

But these are just some of the many things that determine wellbeing – they are not part of the wellbeing outcome itself. To include virtue in the outcome is to confuse means with ends. We should study virtue deeply, but we should not include it in the measure of wellbeing.Footnote 28 So, in this book, we do not use the eudaimonic concept of wellbeing.Footnote 29 We rely mainly on evaluative and hedonic measures of wellbeing, which we also sometimes call happiness. As an aide memoir, Box 1.1 summarises the preceding discussion.

Box 1.1 Different concepts of wellbeing

Type of wellbeingTypical question(s)
EvaluativeOverall, how satisfied are you with your life nowadays? (0–10)
HedonicHow happy were you yesterday?
Or
An hour by hour reconstruction of yesterday recording how you felt (the Day Reconstruction Method)
Or
Regular real-time bleeping to record your feelings (Ecological Momentary Assessment)
EudaimonicDo you feel that the things you do in your life are worthwhile? (0–10)
Can we believe self-reports?

As time passes, we shall undoubtedly get better at measuring wellbeing. Neuroscience will improve, and we shall also use more and more big data from sources like Twitter and Google. But do the questionnaires we currently use really supply any useful information? When we ask people these questions, are their answers accurate? Do they really mean anything, or do different people interpret the question and the scales so differently that their answers cannot really be compared? In other words, are the measures ‘reliable’ and ‘valid’ evidence on the thing they purport to measure.

On reliability, the question is ‘Do people give consistent answers when retested?’ In one study, the correlation between the two sets of answers two weeks apart was 0.55 for life satisfaction and 0.64 for net affect.Footnote 30 This is not bad, but it shows that there is some noise in the data.

A quite different issue is whether the scale is a ‘valid’ representation of what we want it to represent, including whether different people use the scale in the same wayFootnote 31 There are at least four reasons to believe that people’s answers provide significant objective information about how their subjective wellbeing compared with that of other people in the same country.

Correlation with brain activity

First, how people score their subjective wellbeing is correlated with objective measures of electrical activity in certain parts of the brain (see Chapter 5). The same is true of their reporting of physical pain. In a fascinating experiment, researchers applied an equally hot pad to the legs of all the people being studied. People were asked to rate the pain, and the resulting scores were then correlated across people with the electrical activity in the relevant part of the pre-frontal cortex. The correlation was good.Footnote 32 In addition, over time within the same individual over time, there is a good correlation between the wellbeing she reports and objective measurement of her brain waves.Footnote 33

Correlation with third-party reports

Second, we can ask the friends or colleagues of the individual to rate the person’s happiness. These ratings are quite well-correlated with the individual’s own self-reports.Footnote 34 Another study investigated the relationship between smiling and life satisfaction. Researchers rated the positive affect displayed in the most recent Facebook profile photo of those being studied, and this was quite well correlated with their self-reported life satisfaction.Footnote 35

Predictive power

Next, these self-reports are good predictors of many aspects of future behaviour, like quitting a job, divorce or voting behaviour. They are even a good predictor of individual life expectancy. These findings are so important that we describe them in more detail at the end of the chapter.

Explicability

And, finally, we can explain a good part of the variation in these measures by precisely the kind of things one would expect to matter. That is what makes the study of wellbeing so exciting.

So we have good evidence that different people in the same country report their feelings in a similar way. We also have evidence that the same person reports her feelings in a similar way over time. However, do people in different countries report their feelings in the same way or are international comparisons highly unreliable? After all, people are reporting in different languages and many words do not have exact equivalents in other languages. There are, however, three reasons to believe that the country rankings do indeed correspond to real differences out there.Footnote 36

  • The rankings are similar across a whole range of words – like happiness in life, satisfaction with life and position on the Cantril ladder.

  • Within a country, people speaking different languages (e.g., in Switzerland) give very similar answers, and these differ from the average of other countries using the language (e.g., the French compared with French-speaking Swiss).

  • Which language-group a country belongs to adds little to a standard explanation of the wellbeing in that country.

The reporting scale

A different issue is exactly how people use the reporting scale they are offered (0,1, … ,9,10). Do they treat it like a metre rule, where the difference between 3 and 4 centimetres is the same size as the difference between 8 and 9 centimetres? This practice would make the scale an ‘interval scale’ (or what economists call a ‘cardinal scale’). Or do the points on the scale simply reflect a ranking of different mental states (making it an ‘ordinal scale’)?

So what would it mean to say the scale is cardinal? If we want to measure differences in the level of a sensation, the standard basic unit of difference is one that is just noticeable by the person experiencing it. In other words, the natural unit for sensations is the just-noticeable difference (JND).Footnote 37 So we would call a scale an interval scale (or cardinal) if the number of JNDs between the answer 3 and the answer 4 were the same as the number of JNDs between 8 and 9.

Are they? There is a simple empirical test of whether the scale is cardinal: when people are asked and then re-asked to record their life satisfaction (0–10), the average absolute difference in replies should be similar at all points on the scale. It is.Footnote 38 So there is good reason to suppose that people use the scale in a cardinal way, as we have defined it – apparently, respondents naturally reply as though the difference between 3 and 4 is as noticeable as the difference between 8 and 9.

We have already mentioned another relevant fact. Sometimes people are asked to score a variable not by selecting an integer but by selecting a point on a continuous scale (the ‘visual analogue’ method). Studies of the kind give very similar regression results to those using integer scales.Footnote 39

So, when psychologists study sensations, they generally assume people treat the scale as cardinal (see Box 1.2 for further details). By contrast, it is difficult to see how respondents could use the scale (0–10) in an ordinal fashion. There would have to be a ranking of all their possible states of wellbeing, and they would then somehow divide this up into eleven ranges (0–10). However, since there is no concept of distance between one state and another, it is extremely difficult to see how they would undertake this process in any way that is consistent over time or across people.Footnote 41

Box 1.2 ‘Reporting functions’ in psychology

The study of sensations assumes that humans report their sensations in a cardinal fashion. It then addresses the question: How does their sensation relate to the intensity of external phenomena – like brightness? In other words, what is the ‘reporting function’ that relates the reported sensation to the external stimulus (measured in its own units)? For example, how does the reported brightness of light relate to its actual brightness measured in lumens per square metre of receiving surface?

In this case, the just-noticeable difference (JND) in brightness corresponds to a given proportional change in actual brightness (measured in lumens per square metre). Thus the ‘reporting function’ for brightness is

Sensation=alogBrightness

This is known as the Weber–Fechner effect. Similar ‘reporting functions’ have been found for the intensity of sound and indeed for many other things that can vary over a huge range from 0 upwards. But when the range of variation is narrow relative to the average (as with human height), the reporting function becomes roughly linear.Footnote 40

These reporting functions are telling us how people report on an external phenomenon. When it comes to wellbeing, we are talking about something quite different – how people record an inner state. There is no obvious reason why they would not do this in the cardinal way we have described, and the science of psycho-physics assumes they do so.

So we shall assume throughout this book that different individuals use the scale in the same way, that the scale used is stable from period to period and that the scale is a normal one (like a metre rule).

What causes wellbeing?

So what determines their wellbeing? If we want to improve wellbeing (for ourselves or others), we have to know what affects it and by how much. To find this out we have two main sources of evidence. The first is surveys in which people are asked about their wellbeing – but also about many other aspects of their life. The relationship between wellbeing and these other things tell us how much different things matter to people. But precise causality is always difficult to establish from such surveys, nor do they tell us in any detail what we can do to make things better. For this, we need evidence from experiments where some people have received a particular treatment and their change in wellbeing can then be compared with that of a control group. In the last 40 years, evidence of both types has developed at such a rate that we now have the new science of wellbeing, whose findings are the subject of this book.

What Use Is This Knowledge?

This knowledge gives us the power to produce huge improvements in human wellbeing. It helps us as individuals to manage our external life and our own inner experience. It gives new purpose to organisations like schools and businesses. And it provides a whole new framework for the conduct of government.

In each case it works in two stages. First, it helps to set priorities by providing an overall goal against which to test out various options. This goal is the greatest wellbeing possible in ourselves and those around us. Secondly, the evidence provides detailed information about which specific actions work best in terms of wellbeing.

  1. (i) For individuals it offers a perspective on what matters most. Though individuals differ, it shows how we all make systematic mistakes based on the excessive reliance on some issues (like money). It shows how we all suffer from excessive comparisons with others and how we can educate our own mind-sets to generate more compassion for ourselves and for others. Armed with these tools, we can contribute more to the lives of others both in our private lives and through our work. For we now have a moral compass and knowledge about how to use it.

  2. (ii) For organisations like schools and businesses, it provides a test of whether they are performing the functions that justify their existence. For example, it shows how most schools need to give more attention to the wellbeing of the children relative to their exam results – and provides experimental evidence on how to produce happier children. For business, more and more CEOs now consider that business exists to promote the wellbeing not only of shareholders but also of workers, customers and suppliers.Footnote 42 There is now good experimental evidence on how to do this.

  3. (iii) For governments, it provides for the first time a coherent objective. For too long, countries have talked as though economic growth was their overriding objective, though in truth they had multiple objectives that they could not compare. Now for the first time there is a coherent and measurable overall objective – the wellbeing of the people. This is not a new idea. As Thomas Jefferson said, ‘human life and happiness is the only legitimate object of government’.Footnote 43 But until recently, the information to apply this principle was not available. Now it is, and as we shall see, countries are increasingly applying it. And there are now more and more experiments to test which policies are the most cost-effective in terms of their impact on wellbeing. For those who believe that wellbeing is the ultimate objective, this is an exciting prospect, bringing hope to millions and new and worthwhile career opportunities.

Wellbeing helps us achieve other valuable objectives

There are, however, many people who question the idea of wellbeing as the objective. We shall discuss this issue in Chapter 2. But even people who do not value wellbeing for its own sake should value wellbeing because it is an important means to many other objectives that they do value. Here are some striking examples.

  • Education. Making children happier makes them learn better.Footnote 44

  • Health. Your wellbeing has a powerful effect on your longevity.Footnote 45

  • Productivity. Greater wellbeing increases productivity and helps with problem-solving.Footnote 46

  • Family/Social cohesion. Happy people create more stable families, and happy people are more pro-social.Footnote 47

  • Political stability. Wellbeing affects election outcomes more than the economy does. And unhappy people tend to support populist parties.Footnote 48

  • Charitable giving. Happy people give more to others.Footnote 49

These consequences of wellbeing are of major importance. So throughout this book we shall discuss the two-way relation between wellbeing and the different aspects of human life.

To re-cap, the two relations are these:

  • One relation is the effect of each aspect of life on overall wellbeing. This was displayed in Figure I.1, with the arrows pointing towards wellbeing.

  • The other relation is the effect of wellbeing on each aspect of life. This involves a diagram just like Figure I.1 but with the arrows pointing in the opposite direction.

In this book, we look at both sets of effects, but our strongest interest is in the first relation: how wellbeing itself is determined.

Human needs

So let’s examine some basics about how wellbeing is determined and use this to explain the structure of the book. There is evidence that all human beings have similar fundamental needsFootnote 50 and that their wellbeing can be (at least partly) explained by how well these needs are met.

A typical list of these needs includes:

  • Food and shelter,

  • Safety from attack,

  • Love and support,

  • Respect and pride,

  • Mastery of what you do,

  • Autonomy in what you choose to do.

Since 2005, the Gallup World Poll has surveyed representative samples of people in every country in each year. It asks about their life satisfaction and also whether their different needs are met.Footnote 51 The analysis confirms that satisfaction with life increases when more of these needs are met – and people are more satisfied both when their own needs are met and those of their fellow citizens. This confirms a common finding that wellbeing is contagious.Footnote 52

But are some of these needs prior in importance to others? For example, if your life is physically hard, how important is it to experience respect and pride? According to Maslow,Footnote 53 there is a hierarchy of needs (proceeding upwards from Physiological to Safety, Love and Belonging, Esteem and ultimately Self-actualisation): and the best strategy is to satisfy the needs by progressing up the sequence. Thus ‘respect is a disposable luxury when compared with food or safety’. Though hugely famous, there is little supporting evidence for Maslow’s hierarchy. The evidence from the Gallup World Poll is that when each need is satisfied, wellbeing improves. But having one need satisfied has little effect on the value of satisfying another need.Footnote 54

How people interact with their environment

This book is about what determines how far our needs are satisfied. A first answer to that question is that it depends on the interaction between our genes (with which we enter the world) and our external environment – meaning by external environment the whole social and physical world outside ourselves. This is illustrated in Figure 1.3.

Figure 1.3 How genes and external environment determine wellbeing

But this gives the impression that the individual herself is a passive player in the drama, with the environment simply interacting with the person’s genes to produce the outcome. Yet in fact every human being has some degree of agency. We influence our own wellbeing in two key ways:

  • By our behaviour, we significantly influence the situations we experience and the behaviour of others towards us.

  • By our thoughts, we influence how these experiences affect us – both through our attitudes and how we think about our life.

Figure 1.4 tries to capture some of this. Outside us there is a given social environment, but how we experience it is hugely affected by what we bring to it. So the individual’s behaviour interacts with the environment to produce the individual’s experience. This experience then affects the individual’s wellbeing – but how much depends also on how she thinks. This process is repeated over and over again. At each phase, the person’s wellbeing feeds back into her character and behaviour in the next phase of her life (as shown in the dotted lines).

Figure 1.4 How the individual and the external environment interact to produce wellbeing

From this analysis it is clear that our wellbeing does not only depend on our social environment. It also depends on what we bring to the table, in particular

  • our behaviour,

  • our thinking and

  • our genes.

In Chapters 35, we discuss each of these processes, before we discuss the details of the environment in Part III of the book.

What kind of a subject is wellbeing science?

Finally, what kind of a subject is wellbeing science? It is a new, emerging field, which is totally interdisciplinary. Many of the most important subjects that have emerged in recent years are interdisciplinary – subjects like molecular biology or human geography. But this one is rather special, because it provides a rationale for each of the separate social sciences: they are only important because they help to explain wellbeing. If you look at Figure I.1, you will see what we mean. For example, international relations are important because of how they contribute to human wellbeing, and so on. In this sense, wellbeing science could be the queen of the social sciences: it gives a role to each science by showing quantitively how its own outcomes contribute to the overall good.

But, as we shall see in the chapters that follow, there are four key disciplines that are most central to the study of wellbeing: psychology, sociology, economics and statistics.

  • Psychology. The study of wellbeing started in psychology.Footnote 55 Psychologists study how human nature works at the individual level, using both surveys and experiments. They study how individual personality, family experience and education affect wellbeing. They also study how to make things better for individuals (clinical psychology) and at work (occupational psychology). However, except for social psychology, psychologists tend to ignore the role of social norms and social structures upon human wellbeing.

  • Sociology. That is where sociologists come in. They study, above all, the way people interact in groups and how that affects their wellbeing.

  • Economics. Economics brings four main contributions. First, economists have always focused on wellbeing as the overarching outcome (calling it ‘utility’), even though they often have a rather narrow view of it and what causes it. Second, they discuss policy in terms of maximising that single outcome. Third, they distinguish clearly between the things people choose and the things that just happen to them (which they call ‘externalities’). And fourth, they bring understanding of markets, income and unemployment.

  • Statistics. This is central to the preceding disciplines. When it is used to analyse the distribution of characteristics in a population, it is sometimes called epidemiology.

There are three other fields of study, which, though relevant, are not the same as the science of wellbeing.

  • Behavioural science. In recent years, economists have been developing, jointly with psychologists, a deeper understanding of how people actually behave – a subject sometimes known as behavioural economics. But the study of wellbeing is a different endeavour. It does not study how to get people to behave in a certain way. It studies the results of behaviour and thus which behaviours would maximise social wellbeing.

  • Health and wellbeing. This phrase, increasingly used, signifies a welcome extension of health science to include mental states as well as physical conditions. But it does not typically view wellbeing as the overarching good, with health as just one of many influences upon it. Wellbeing science, in contrast, studies the effects of everything in life upon the wellbeing of the population.

  • Finally, philosophy. ‘What is wellbeing?’, ‘Is it all that matters?’, ‘How should it be distributed?’, and so on, are, of course, philosophical issues. We turn to these issues in Chapter 2. After that, the rest of the book is about the science of what causes wellbeing and how it can be improved.

Conclusions

  1. (1) For many people, the reason to study wellbeing is the belief that it is the only thing that ultimately matters.

  2. (2) In this view, many other things are good, like health, freedom, income and so on, but they are good because (and only because of) how they affect wellbeing.

  3. (3) By wellbeing we mean subjective wellbeing – how people feel. This can be measured in three different ways:

    • Evaluative: how people feel about their life nowadays

    • Hedonic: how people feel at each moment

    • Eudaimonic: whether people believe their life is worthwhile

    The most commonly-used measure is evaluative, for example, ‘satisfaction with life’, but we shall also use hedonic measures where these are relevant.

  4. (4) Evaluative wellbeing differs hugely across countries and within countries, while hedonic wellbeing also varies across activities.

  5. (5) There is good evidence that these measures are reliable and valid. They are correlated with objective brain measurements, with third-party reports, with many consequences (like longevity, voting, productivity and learning) and with many plausible causes (which is mainly what the book is about).

  6. (6) Most human beings have similar fundamental needs and their wellbeing varies with how well these needs are met. However, people are not passive agents, simply affected by their environment. Their own behaviour affects what they and others experience. And their own thoughts mediate how these experiences affect their wellbeing.

So Chapters 25 deal with

  • The overall objective for society

  • The role of behaviour

  • The role of thoughts

  • The role of genes and the working of our bodies.

These are all issues of basic human nature.

Then in Part III we turn to the hugely different experiences that different people have and how they affect our wellbeing – the role of family life and schools, healthcare, employment, the quality of work, income, social connections, the physical environment and climate and government. We look at their effect and at how wellbeing could be improved in each of these dimensions. Finally, we look at the techniques of policy-making and show how every policy-maker could use wellbeing data to produce a better world.

Questions for discussion
  1. (1) Is there anything more important than how we feel? Is wellbeing the overarching goal? If not, what is, and how should we weight multiple goals?

  2. (2) What is the best way to measure wellbeing? Are these measurements ‘cardinal’?

  3. (3) How does wellbeing science relate to other subjects you have studied?

2 Wellbeing as the Goal for Society

Create all the happiness you are able to create: remove all the misery you are able to remove.

Jeremy Bentham
Some History

How would we recognise a good society? The idea that it is defined by the wellbeing of the citizens goes back at least to the ancient Greeks.Footnote 1 In this chapter, we shall see how this idea developed from then until now. We shall then provide a rigorous modern formulation of the idea. And finally, we shall discuss some of the main objections that people have made to it.

Greece and Rome

We can begin with the great Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 bc). He, more than anyone, is responsible for the idea that there must be some ultimate end that we should aim at – with other things like wealth, health and good relationships being good because of how they contribute to that end. That is the hierarchical idea we already displayed in Figure I.1. The ultimate end he called ‘eudaimonia’, which he envisaged as a balanced, rational and virtuous state of being. He especially emphasised virtue, which he considered essential if your experience of life is to be truly fulfilling. He did not define virtue exactly as this book does, but he had a realistic modern empiricist view on how it should be acquired – by constant repetition and habit-formation.

Greek philosophers who came after Aristotle emphasised different aspects of his message. Epicurus (341–270 bc) emphasised the importance of a simple life, focused on things you really enjoy, like friendship and family life. Zeno the Stoic (333–264 bc) emphasised civic virtue and the ability to calm your mind whatever adversity befell you. The ideas of these two thinkers spread widely through the Roman world. Eventually, it was Stoicism that became the philosophy of much of the Roman middle class – and of the emperor Marcus Aurelius (ad 121–180), who wrote much about the secrets of happiness. Similar ideas had already been developed in China by Confucius and in India by the Buddha.

However, in the centuries that followed, Christianity brought in a quite different perspective. Happiness was still to be sought but only in the afterlife. In this world, the aim was virtue alone and this would bring happiness after death.Footnote 2

The eighteenth-century Enlightenment

It was only in the late seventeenth century that philosophers dared to re-establish happiness on earth as the goal of life. The great English philosopher John Locke (1632–1704) took it as axiomatic that people wanted to feel good and that to acquire that feeling was their principal motivation. But it was a Scotsman, Francis Hutcheson (1694–1746), who took the first huge step towards establishing happiness as the goal for society, rather than just for the individual. He taught that the moral thing to do was whatever produced ‘the greatest happiness for the greatest number’Footnote 3 – or, more precisely, what produced the greatest total happiness. And he argued that this is what any ‘impartial spectator’ would think.

From the wellbeing point of view, this idea was probably the greatest idea of modern times. It has three key implications.

  1. (1) For judgements: If we want to compare two different situations and to say which is better, we should use the happiness of the people as the test. This would be so, for example, if we were asking which country is doing better, or whether the present is better than the past or which is the best way to spend public money.

  2. (2) For individual action: If we ask, ‘What is the ethical thing to do?’, the answer is, ‘Whatever produces the greatest overall happiness’.

  3. (3) For government policy: When we ask, ‘What should the government be trying to achieve?’, the answer is, ‘The greatest possible happiness for the people’.

As the eighteenth century progressed, these ideas took a firm hold among the educated classes in the English-speaking world, including in North America.Footnote 4 Thomas Jefferson, who drafted the US constitution, would write, ‘The life and happiness of the people is the first and only object of good government.’ But the writer who immortalised these ideas was the Englishman Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) in The Principle of Morals and Legislation. In this book, Bentham argued that all actions should be judged by their consequences – by their impact on the happiness of everyone. In other words, actions should be judged by their ‘utility’. Thus Bentham’s concept of ethics, which is so humane, became known as ‘utilitarianism’, which makes it sound quite the opposite. (Similarly economics, which was founded by Adam Smith (1723–1790) to study the economic conditions for the greatest happiness, chose the word ‘utility’ to describe individual wellbeing rather than the word ‘happiness’).

During the nineteenth century, the principle of the greatest happiness inspired many major social reforms. It was forcefully presented by John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) in his book Utilitarianism and in his essay ‘The Subjection of Women’. However, he also proposed that some pleasures are intrinsically better than others (for example, poetry was better than the game of pushpin). This was in our view a confusion of means with ends. You will certainly be happier in general if you have a clear purpose in life (as we show clearly in Chapter 4). And you will make others happier if you are virtuous. But the ultimate test of a society is how happy people are (irrespective of how they became so).

During the nineteenth century, economists continued to focus on happiness as the ultimate test of economic arrangements, and the economist Edgeworth (1845–1926) foreshadowed the modern science of wellbeing when he talked about the need for a ‘hedonimeter’ – a technique to measure happiness in a cardinal fashion. In the nineteenth century, most economists believed that an extra dollar gives more extra happiness to a poor person than to someone who is better off. Similarly, in psychology, the great psychologist William James was primarily concerned with life as people experienced it from the inside.

Behaviourism

But then in the twentieth century, psychology turned away from the study of wellbeing – to behaviourism. Scholars like Ivan Pavlov and John B. Watson argued that we could not know what occurred inside people or how they felt. One could only study how they behaved and how this was affected by external stimuli. This doctrine soon impacted on economics, and in 1932, the economist Lionel Robbins asserted that we could not compare the happiness of one person with another.Footnote 5 Even for the same person, he argued, we could only rank different situations, A, B and C, in order; we could not say whether going from A to B gave more (or less) extra happiness than going from B to C.

The consequences for economics were serious. It became impossible to evaluate any issue involving income distribution. We could not say whether it was better if two people had $50,000 dollars each or if one had $20,000 and the other had $80,000. All that could be claimed was that a change was good if some people gained and no one lost (a so-called Pareto improvement). When, as generally happens, a change involves some gainers and some losers, economists, according to Robbins, could say nothing. But in fact, this did not stop them from pronouncing in such cases, and John Hicks and Nicholas Kaldor quickly provided what they considered a justification. They argued that, even if some people lose, a change is good if the gainers could have compensated the losers – even if they actually didn’t.Footnote 6 This was the so-called Hicks–Kaldor criterion for a welfare improvement.

This criterion also justified a second dubious practice: the use of national income (or gross domestic product, GDP) as a measure of national wellbeing. GDP is a measure of the scale of economic activity, the things that happen for which people get paid. In the national income, everybody’s dollars are added up regardless of who has them; and, if the national income increases, that is a Hicks–Kaldor improvement, even if many poor people have become worse off. But GDP was invented for a quite different purpose – by Simon Kuznets – as a way of analysing the business cycle and the fluctuations of unemployment. It was not meant to measure wellbeing. As Kuznets himself said, ‘The welfare of a nation can scarcely be inferred from a measurement of national income.’Footnote 7 There are two obvious reasons for this view:

  • GDP adds up the dollars of rich and poor as if they are of equal value.

  • GDP fails to include any source of wellbeing other than things you can buy. As Robert Kennedy put it, ‘GDP does not allow for the health of our children, the quality of their education, or the joy of their play.’Footnote 8

But despite all this, GDP per head became the totem of national success in the post-WWII period.

In recent years, there has, however, been a massive pushback against the idea that GDP is an adequate measure of national progress. In 1974, the economist Richard Easterlin used psychological surveys to show that wellbeing in the United States had not risen since WWII, despite massive economic growth.Footnote 9 And subsequent research has shown that economic growth is no guarantee of increased wellbeing (see Chapter 13). So it is not surprising that even before the economic slowdown in the West from 2008 onwards, there was increased public demand for a wider goal than economic growth.

Taking feelings seriously again

But key to the demand for a new approach has been our increased ability to measure wellbeing and to understand its causes. The key figure here has been Edward Diener (1946–2021). Beginning in the early 1980s, he showed that wellbeing could be effectively measured and explained.Footnote 10 As time went on, more and more psychologists joined this enterprise, including Daniel Kahneman who in 2002 won the Nobel Prize for Economics. Economists also joined in, using large population surveys to throw light on the effect of different experiences upon individual wellbeing.

At the same time, ordinary citizens have become increasingly aware of their own mental states and interested in how to improve their own feelings. Two forces are at work here. The first is cognitive psychology (embodied in cognitive-behavioural therapy) and the second is mind-training techniques imported from the East. We discuss both at length in Chapter 4.

The Definition of Social Welfare

So it is time to lay out somewhat more formally a view of ethics based on the wellbeing of society as the goal.Footnote 11 The overall objective is called ‘social welfare(S). Social welfare is the concept we use when comparing one situation with another, to find out which is best. Any formula for social welfare must obviously satisfy some basic principles including these:

  • Everybody’s wellbeing is of equal importance. So every person’s wellbeing should be treated in the same way when we compute social welfare.Footnote 12

  • Social welfare must be higher if one person’s wellbeing increases and no one else’s falls.

But we need to be more specific than this. The measure of social welfare that Hutcheson, and then Bentham, proposed was the simple sum of wellbeing (W) across all the members of the population. In other words, if Wi is the wellbeing of the ‘i’th person and ∑ means the sum across all members of the population, then at any point in time social welfare is

Current Social Welfare=S=ΣiWi(1)

This is the classic utilitarian approach. Later in this chapter, we shall consider a more egalitarian or ‘prioritarian’ approach. But the classic utilitarian approach is a good starting point.

Wellbeing over time and WELLBYs

Of course, most decisions affect wellbeing over a period of time. For example, decisions affecting the climate will affect generations yet unborn. So we need a social welfare function that enables us to find the best path of wellbeing over the future and not just in the current period. So how should we value future wellbeing?

An obvious starting point is that the wellbeing of every human being in every year matters equally. However, since there is major uncertainty about the future, we should slightly discount the wellbeing that could be expected in future years – by multiplying wellbeing in t years hence by 1δt where δ is the discount rate per annum. (In Britain, the official value of this ‘pure time preference rate’ is 1.5% per annum).Footnote 13 In proceeding in this way, we are assuming that a person’s suffering in any one year is equally important, whether or not the rest of their life is happy.

On this basis, intertemporal social welfare (S*) becomes simply the discounted sum of all future wellbeing, whoever is experiencing it:

Future Social Welfare=S=ΣiΣt1δtWit(2)

So if we want to decide whether a policy change is desirable, we should evaluate whether the following expression is positive:

ΔS=ΣiΣt1δtΔWit(3)

To make this practical, we have to decide on the length of each period. If we take it as a year, ΔWit would be the change in wellbeing for person i in year t. In other words, it is a change in Wellbeing-Years (or WELLBYs). So when we come to methods of policy evaluation in Chapter 18, the key issue will be how a policy affects the number of (discounted) WELLBYs.

Sustainability and climate change

Thus the wellbeing approach provides a comprehensive framework for considering the future of our society from the smallest choices to the biggest. Of these, the biggest of all is the future of the planet. A central issue here is the wellbeing of future generations.Footnote 14

Wellbeing science favours a low discount rate, so that what happens to future generations is really important when we decide what to do now. The only legitimate reason for discounting future wellbeing is ‘pure time preference’, based on uncertainty about the future. Typical rates of pure time preference are 1.5% a year. By contrast economists mainly analyse the future in terms of levels of real income. They generally assume that real incomes will rise steadily, which will reduce the impact of extra future income on future wellbeing. They therefore discount future income by at least 3.5% a year – making the future appear much less important relative to the present.Footnote 15 So it is not surprising that those who want everything analysed in terms of wellbeing find strong allies among those who want more attention to the future of the planet. For both groups, sustainability is crucial.

Length of life and the birth rate

There is one further issue – the issue of life and death. One way to increase future social welfare (as in equation 2) is to help people live longer. If someone lives longer and has wellbeing greater than zero, that increases social welfare.Footnote 16

But can we also increase future social welfare by increasing the birth rate? If we could, it would be one of the least expensive ways of increasing future social welfare, and we would therefore choose to do it even if it decreased the number of Wellbeing-Years (or WELLBYs) per person born. John Stuart Mill rejected the idea that social welfare depended on the size of the population, and we shall focus instead on the number of WELLBYs per person born.

Today’s medical policy-makers have adopted the same approach. Their aim is to produce the highest possible number of Quality-Adjusted Life Years (suitably discounted) for each person born.Footnote 17 We shall follow this approach. So when we use equation (3) to evaluate a policy change, we do not include in our evaluation any effect of the policy change upon the number of people born.

How egalitarian should we be?

We have thus far adopted the stand of classic utilitarianism – that all that matters is average lifetime wellbeing, regardless of how unequally it is distributed. This means that the following distributions of wellbeing are of equal value:

Situation 1Situation 2
Person A85
Person B25

But today many people are more egalitarian than Hutcheson and Bentham were and believe that it is more important to raise the wellbeing of the least happy people than to raise by an equal amount the wellbeing of those who are already quite happy.Footnote 18 In other words, the social value of i’s wellbeing is not identical to Wi. Instead, it rises with Wi but it rises at a declining rate. So the social value of Wi is a ‘function’ of Wi, f (Wi), which has the property we have just described.Footnote 19 And social welfare is the sum of f (Wi) added up across all members of society. Thus,

Foregalitarians:S=ΣifWif>0f<0(4)

There are thus two alternative concepts of social welfare that we could use to decide whether one situation is better than another. Which of them should we use? In choosing between the Benthamite (or strictly ‘utilitarian’) view and the more egalitarian (or ‘prioritarian’) view, a good approach is the one pioneered after WWII by Jan Harsanyi and John Rawls.Footnote 20 In this approach, we imagine ourselves in an ‘original position’ behind a ‘veil of ignorance’, not knowing which actual human being we are going to be. We then ask ourselves to choose between different situations, not knowing who we will be in each situation.

So how would we evaluate different situations? Egalitarians who use this framework believe that most individuals have a degree of risk-aversion. They would not therefore evaluate a distribution of possible levels of wellbeing entirely according to its average value. They would also look at the spread of the possible outcomes. And they would prefer prospects where the probability of experiencing low wellbeing was low. In other words, for any given average wellbeing in the population, they would prefer a more equal to a less equal distribution of wellbeing.Footnote 21 The simplest way to represent this set of values is by a concept of social welfare of the type we have already described, ΣifWi where the social value of additional W declines as W increases.Footnote 22

If one accepts this argument, the issue is then ‘How fast is the decline?’Footnote 23 The most extreme view is one inspired by the work of the Harvard philosopher John Rawls.Footnote 24 In this view, the decline is so sharp that the only thing that really matters is the wellbeing of the least happy person. So the social welfare equals the wellbeing of the least happy person.

Forfollowers of Rawls:S=MinW1Wn(5)

A less extreme view is that the only thing that really matters is the number of people below some acceptable level of wellbeing.Footnote 25

Choosing a social welfare function is not a scientific matter – it involves normative considerations, even if we try to solve the issue by ‘positive’ thought experiments or by surveying the population. This is why, however much the science of wellbeing improves, there will always be a spread of views on the exact definition of social welfare.

Therefore, the most practical approach in any choice situation is to begin by first examining the difference in ΣiWi and then seeing how far the result would be altered by varying assumptions about the form of fWi.Footnote 26 A further practical step is to begin the search for new policies in those areas of life that account for the greatest amount of misery (on which Chapter 8 provides relevant evidence).

Criticisms

It is time now to face the music. For, despite its powerful approach, a philosophy based on subjective wellbeing has been subject to major criticisms. Here are some of the main criticisms, together with a typical reply from the advocates of wellbeing. It should be pointed out that many of these problems are extremely difficult to handle using any philosophical system, and the real issue is whether there is any other ethical system that is more defensible than that based on wellbeing.

Consequentialism and rights: The fat man

The first criticism is that we only take into account the consequences of actions (even though we do include in that the experiences that occur during the action itself). Critics often use the following example.Footnote 27 You are on a railway bridge. You see a train approaching from one side of the bridge, while down the line are five people on the track who will be killed by the train. However there is a fat man sitting on the bridge. Should you push the fat man to his death in order to save five others?

The calculus says there would be a net gain of four lives from this action (5 minus 1). So is it the right thing to do? Critics argue that the wellbeing approach says Yes, and this shows that the wellbeing approach is inadequate. However, how would millions of people in our society feel about their own lives if such actions became acceptable? Clearly, society has to have rules that make its members flourish. The philosophy of utilitarianism thus has two functions.Footnote 28 First, it helps us to choose the rules we should generally follow, and second, it helps us to decide when we should break the rule (for example, when we should lie to protect a Jew in hiding from the Nazis).

Some of the rules will be moral principles we teach our children, while others will be rights enshrined in law. We will teach our children to be kind because that makes other people feel better. But we also need legislated rights, especially for minorities. If we wish to prevent misery, we have to establish many legal rights. But these are deliberate legislative acts designed to promote social welfare; they are not the recognition of some pre-existing ‘natural rights’.Footnote 29 The only natural right is that each individual’s feelings count equally.

The experience machine

But are good feelings the only things that matter? In 1974, the Harvard philosopher Robert Nozick questioned the primacy of feelings by posing the following hypothetical question: ‘Suppose there was an “experience machine” you could link up to, which would make you feel anything you desire and which was equally available to other people. Would you link up to it?’Footnote 30

Many people say No. They say it matters that the experience is real. But what if the real experience was awful and that we reverse the sequence of the question. So imagine you are having a lovely time in the experience machine and are offered instead the real experience of solitary confinement in a rat-infested cell. Which would you choose?Footnote 31

A more likely possibility is that scientists come up with a drug that makes everybody feel better and has no bad side effects. This issue was raised in a striking form by Aldous Huxley in his book Brave New World. In it he has people taking soma to make themselves feel better. This was meant to appal the readers. But most people throughout history have used alcohol or other substances to improve their mood. The problem has been that all known substances of this kind also bring bad side effects. But it may be hard to object to a substance that improves mood without any bad side effects.

Adaptation

Then there is the issue that our feelings adapt (see Chapter 3). Most people adapt to hardship to a considerable extent, so that it causes less misery than might be expected.Footnote 32 If we take this fact into account, critics say, we shall do less to reduce hardship than we should.Footnote 33 But this does not follow, because people who are more fortunate also adapt to their good fortune. So if we take from the privileged and give to the deprived, the privileged will also suffer less than might be expected. Thus the case for redistribution is hardly affected by the fact of adaptation: the poor may gain less extra wellbeing from it than might be expected, but the rich also suffer less than might be expected.Footnote 34 The balance of the argument is thus unaffected.

However, adaptation does have important implications if some experiences are less subject to adaptation than others. It is therefore important to distinguish between hardships that cannot be adapted to and those that can be. Hardships that are hard or impossible to adapt to include mental pain, chronic physical pain, incarceration, torture, indignity and intolerable noise.Footnote 35 These types of hardship need high priority in public policy.

Selfishness is encouraged

Critics often complain that, if we accept wellbeing as the supreme goal, this means that individuals should simply maximise their own wellbeing. Far from it. For each person’s wellbeing depends hugely on the benevolent behaviour of others. This is illustrated in Figure 2.1.

Figure 2.1 How wellbeing is determined by behaviour

In this profoundly important diagram, the outcome we care about is the overall wellbeing of society, represented by the whole right-hand side of the diagram. How can it be maximised? The answer is: only if everyone chooses to behave so as to maximise the overall wellbeing of society. That is the fundamental ethical principle proclaimed by Bentham and by all other supporters of the greatest happiness principle. This aspiration should inform a person’s whole life – both in private matters and also in the job they choose to do. In this view, morality is not just about what you should not do but also what you should do. For example, it is wrong to hurt someone but it is also wrong not to help them.

Some people say this is too ‘demanding’Footnote 36 – it takes over too much of your life. As with all other moral theories, it is hard to specify exactly how far we should sacrifice our individual happiness for the sake of others. But, if we want to reduce suffering, we clearly have to avoid not only hurting people (sins of commission) but also failing to help them (sins of omission).

To encourage good lives, we have two key psychological traits we can build on. The first is the pleasure that people derive from helping others: doing the right thing is not always pleasurable but it often is (see Chapter 3). The second is the impact of norms on habit. If people are expected to behave well from an early age, it just becomes a habit. This was the route that Aristotle stressed.

Both of these routes are at variance with the doctrines of Immanuel Kant, the great philosopher of the German Enlightenment, which provide the main alternative system of ethics to that based on the maximisation of wellbeing.Footnote 37 In the Kantian system, the ethical rightness of a person’s actions are judged by the person’s motives and not by their consequences. A moral action has to be a conscious act of will, and pleasure and habit are considered antithetical to truly moral action. There is, however, one key feature on which both Kantian and Benthamite approaches are agreed: every individual is of equal ultimate importance. This is fundamental to any ethical theory based on reason.

The nanny state

Turning to political theory, critics of the wellbeing approach sometimes claim that, if the government concerns itself with how people feel, this will lead to excessive interference in people’s lives. But wellbeing science itself shows the huge importance of freedom for personal wellbeing (see Chapters 8 and 16). So any government aiming at wellbeing will be constantly restrained by that consideration. Whenever possible, the government will provide opportunities that people can use or not, as they prefer.

It is, however, crucial to realise that many of the things that matter most to people are intensely personal (their mental health, their family relationships and their work situation) and failures in these dimensions are major sources of human misery. So a benevolent state is bound to offer help, if there are cost-effective forms of help that can be made available.

Social justice

A final problem is one that affects all ethical theories – how much weight to give to the interests of the least fortunate. Classic utilitarianism can be criticised because it gives equal value to more happiness whether it accrues to someone who is already happy or to someone who is miserable. But the ‘prioritarian approach’ we advocated earlier avoids this problem, and it provides a stronger basis for the legal creation of rights. It also asserts that income inequality is bad because an extra dollar is worth more to a poor person than a rich one. So a good society establishes rights (as a form of safety net) and it redistributes income.Footnote 38

No ethical theory is without problems. If you find the wellbeing approach problematic, can you think of a better criterion for how to live or how to make policy?

We can end with a different question. Is wellbeing an experience that humans were designed for? The answer from ‘evolutionary psychology’ is ‘Partly yes and partly no’. The basic features of human nature were created by natural selection about 200,000 years ago in Africa. The genes that survived in the struggle for survival were those that maximised our ‘inclusive fitness’ – in other words, the genes that were most likely to produce successive generations carrying the same genes. So how conducive to wellbeing were the genes that got selected? We were certainly constructed to enjoy many of the things necessary for survival and reproduction – sex, food, drink and a capacity to cooperate (see Chapter 3). Moreover, as we have seen, wellbeing is extremely good for many other things that are good for our survival – good for our physical health, for our productivity and for our creativity.Footnote 39

There were, however, some traits that were essential for survival in the Savannah that are not particularly conducive to an enjoyable life. The most obvious of these is anxiety. If lions are about, it is a good thing to be anxious. But life today is a lot more safe, and most people would have a more enjoyable life if they were less anxious (see Chapter 4).

As this book shows, we have the knowledge to improve our own wellbeing and that of others – a noble cause.

Conclusions
  1. (1) We are considering a very powerful idea – that social welfare depends only on the subjective wellbeing of the population. This is relevant to all aspects of life from public policy-making to personal behaviour. It is a concept with at least three uses.

    • It provides a measure for comparing situations, for example, comparing countries or comparing the same country at different periods in time.

    • It provides the fundamental principle of moral philosophy: that we personally should at all times do what we can to maximise social welfare.

    • It provides the fundamental principle of political philosophy: that governments should provide the conditions for the greatest possible social welfare.

  2. (2) Wellbeing has been a central issue in philosophy from the earliest times.

  3. (3) In the eighteenth century, Anglo-Scottish philosophers proposed the ‘greatest happiness’ of the people as the goal of moral and political action. Thus individuals should aim to be ‘creators of happiness’ and policy-makers should target the wellbeing of the people.

  4. (4) In the early twentieth century, behaviourism postulated that we could not know how others feel. In consequence, economists abandoned the policy goal of maximising happiness and moved to maximising aggregate income (GDP).

  5. (5) There is now a strong movement against using GDP as an indicator of wellbeing and in favour of some measure of the quality of life.

  6. (6) One version of the ‘social welfare function’ is ΣWi, where Wi is the wellbeing of the ith person. But most policies have impacts over a number of years. Thus forward looking social welfare is measured by ΣiΣt1δtWit, the discounted sum of future Wellbeing Years (WELLBYS).

  7. (7) The discount rate should be low. In this case the wellbeing of future generations is given the weight it deserves – making climate change and sustainability into hugely important issues.

  8. (8) Egalitarians prefer to measure the social value of today’s wellbeing not by ΣWi but by ΣfWi where fWirises at a diminishing rate as Wiincreases. In policy evaluation, a practical approach is to start with ΣWi and then test for sensitivity to different forms offWi. In addition we can mainly search for new policies in those areas of life which account for the greatest amount of misery.

  9. (9) The wellbeing approach has been criticised on many grounds including rights, ‘experience machine’, adaptation, selfishness and the ‘nanny state’. This book discusses these criticisms.

Questions for discussion
  1. (1) Do you agree that coherent policy-making requires some single overarching criterion? Should this be wellbeing?

  2. (2) Should the same idea govern our personal ethical choices?

  3. (3) Should the social welfare function be the simple sum of wellbeing across people? Or should it give extra weight to the scale of misery?

  4. (4) What is your view on the main criticisms made of the wellbeing approach to ethics and policy choice:

    • Consequentialism, rights and social justice

    • The experience machine.

    • Adaptation

    • Selfishness

    • Nanny state

Footnotes

1 What Subjective Wellbeing Is and Why It Matters

2 OECD (2013).

3 As of writing, Finland, Iceland, New Zealand, Scotland and Wales.

4 The leading advocate of this approach is Sen (Reference Sen1999). But many other distinguished writers also follow the dashboard approach, including Pinker (Reference Pinker2018) (health, happiness, freedom, knowledge, love and richness of experience); Seligman (2018) (positive emotion, engagement, relationships, meaning and accomplishment); and Skidelsky and Skidelsky (2012).

5 On this section, see Helliwell (2021).

6 This is the version used by the United Kingdom’s Office for National Statistics (ONS).

7 Couper et al. (2006). But see also Cowley and Youngblood (2009). Neither of these surveys was measuring life satisfaction.

9 We are using Gallup data a lot in this book because it covers almost every country. But in many cases, similar findings were obtained earlier from sources like Eurobarometer and the World Values Survey.

12 A comparable ranking of life satisfaction among 15-year-olds can be found in Table 6.1.

13 A. E. Clark et al. (Reference Clark and Georgellis2012); Figure 3.4.

14 Helliwell et al. (Reference Helliwell, Layard and Sachs2020); Figure 2.2.

16 For an attempt at this see Hills et al. (Reference Hills, Proto, Sgroi and Seresinhe2019).

17 Pinker (Reference Pinker2018). However, in studies of the Masai and Inuit (both Old Stone Age cultures), surveys registered quite high levels of positive affect. Biswas-Diener et al. (Reference Biswas-Diener, Vittersø and Diener2005).

18 There is an obvious issue of what time period people have in mind when they answer this question. Benjamin et al. (2021) investigate this issue asking people whether they are ‘evaluating their situation’ as it is right now or also as it was in the past or will be in the future. Clearly, how people feel now is affected by things that have happened or may happen. But their answers may still be reflecting their current state of feeling.

19 Frijters and Krekel (Reference Frijters and Krekel2021).

22 Bradburn (Reference Bradburn1969).

23 Jaidka et al. (Reference Jaidka, Giorgi, Schwartz, Kern, Ungar and Eichstaedt2020). Metzler et al. (Reference Greenberger and Padesky2022) show a good intertemporal correlation between text-based and questionnaire-based estimates of SWB. For an interesting analysis of emotions during the COVID-19 pandemic, based on Google searches, see Brodeur et al. (Reference Brodeur, Clark, Fleche and Powdthavee2021).

24 Answers on life satisfaction are similar on weekdays and weekends, while those on happiness yesterday give higher scores at weekends.

25 Hedonic measures are usually subjected to some form of weights, e.g., to produce a measure of affect balance.

26 When philosophers discuss wellbeing, they generally consider there to be three main theories of what wellbeing is: (i) desire-fulfilment theories, where wellbeing consists in getting what you want; (ii) hedonism, where wellbeing consists in happiness, that is, how good you feel; and (iii) objective list theories, where wellbeing might consist in happiness or desire fulfilment but also consists in some ‘objective’ goods, perhaps achievement, love, knowledge or virtue.

For reasons we have given, we do not accept (iii) – it does not solve the problem of multiple objectives. Our ‘hedonic’ measure is (ii) and so is life satisfaction (unless we consider people to have an overarching desire to be satisfied with their lives).

As regards (i) there is the empirical issue of what people really desire. Surveys show that, when asked to make choices, people most commonly, but not always, choose what will make them happy (see, for example Benjamin et al. Reference Benjamin, Heffetz, Kimball and Rees-Jones2012; and Perez-Truglia Reference Perez-Truglia2015). In another study, people were asked to make choices that required pitching happiness against other outcomes like income, health, etc. (Adler et al. Reference Adler, Dolan and Kavetsos2017) – happiness came top except for health (but in this study there was no distinction between health as quality of life and health as a factor affecting survival). We do not however accept the desire-fulfilment approach since people often make choices which have bad effects.

Thus, we opt for (ii) how people feel, because of its self-evident value (i.e., that no further reason can be given for its importance).

27 For a modern empirical definition of eudaimonia see Ryff (Reference Ryff1989).

28 We do urgently need to know how to produce virtuous people (see Chapter 3). But this is a different issue from the definition of wellbeing.

29 It is in fact highly correlated with evaluative wellbeing. See Keyes et al. (Reference Keyes, Shmotkin and Ryff2002), Model 4; and Ryff and Singer (Reference Ryff and Singer2003).

30 Krueger and Schkade (Reference Krueger and Schkade2008). See also Fujita and Diener (Reference Fujita and Diener2005).

31 For an economist’s discussion of the issue of comparability, see Sen (Reference Sen1970).

33 Davidson (2004).

34 Diener and Suh (Reference Diener1999).

35 Seder and Oishi (Reference Oishi, Schimmack and Diener2012) r = 0.38. The correlation with life satisfaction 3 years later was even higher (r = 0.57).

36 Veenhoven (Reference Veenhoven2012). See also Diener et al. (Reference Diener, Suh, Smith and Shao1995). It is sometimes suggested that people re-norm the scale in the light of experience. Evidence against this is presented in Odermatt and Stutzer (Reference Odermatt and Stutzer2019).

37 See, for example, Stevens (1986), chapter 1 (not an easy read).

38 Kruger and Schkade (Reference Krueger and Schkade2008).

41 For a different view on all this, see Bond and Lang (Reference Bond and Lang2019). And for a response to Bond and Lang, see Kaiser and Vendrik (Reference Kaiser and Vendrik2020).

42 US Business Roundtable (2019). On work and wellbeing, see Chapter 12.

43 Jefferson (Reference Jefferson1809).

44 The best evidence comes from interventions to improve wellbeing. See Durlak et al. (Reference Durlak, Weissberg, Dymnicki, Taylor and Schellinger2011); Hanh and Weare (Reference Hanh and Weare2017); Adler (Reference Adler2016); and Frederickson and Branigan (2005).

45 For UK data, see Steptoe and Wardle (Reference Steptoe, Hamer and Chida2012). On the United States, see Lee and Singh (Reference Lee and Singh2020).

48 Ward (Reference Ward, De Neve, Ungar and Eichstaedt2020) and Ward et al. (Reference Ward, De Neve, Ungar and Eichstaedt2020) show that incumbent governments do worse when people are less happy. On populism, see Nowakowski (Reference Nowakowski2021).

51 See Tay and Diener (Reference Tay and Diener2011). The questions are binary (Yes/No). For food and shelter: enough money for food and shelter and did not go hungry. For safety: safe walking alone, nothing stolen nor assaulted in the last 12 months. For love and support: experienced love yesterday and have someone to count on. For respect and pride: treated with respect and proud of something. For mastery: did what you do best at work, learned something. For autonomy: chose how best to spend your time, and experienced freedom. These are similar to the basic needs identified by Maslow (Reference Maslow1954); Deci and Ryan (Reference Ryan and Deci2000); Ryff and Keyes (Reference Ryff and Keyes1995); and Sen (Reference Sen1999).

52 See, for example, Fowler and Christakis (Reference Fowler and Christakis2008).

54 Tay and Diener (Reference Tay and Diener2011).

55 Some key figures were Hadley Cantril (1906–1969) and Angus Campbell (1910–1980) – see Cantril (Reference Cantril1965) and Campbell, Converse and Rodgers (Reference Campbell, Converse and Rodgers1976).

2 Wellbeing as the Goal for Society

1 We discuss the contribution of the Buddha in Chapter 4.

2 Of course, Christianity also forecast a new world on earth but only after the Second Coming.

4 There were also supporters on the continent of Europe but not so numerous. Notable contributors included the Italian jurist Cesare Beccaria (1738–1794) and the French philosopher Claude Adrien Helvétius (1715–1771).

6 Kaldor (Reference Kaldor1939); and Hicks (Reference Hicks1940).

8 Robert Kennedy in a speech at the University of Kansas on 18 March 1968.

9 Easterlin (Reference Clark1974).

10 See Diener (Reference De Neve, Ward, De Keulenaer, Van Landeghem, Kavetsos and Norton1984). Important forerunners were Cantril (Reference Cantril1965); Campbell, Converse and Rodgers (Reference Campbell, Converse and Rodgers1976); and Andrews and Withey (Reference Andrews and Withey1976). These books used the new wellbeing metric.

11 There are some wellbeing scientists who would only use the social welfare function as a guide to the choice of political constitutions, not as a guide on individual policies (see Frey Reference Frey2008).

12 As we argue later, future wellbeing should be slightly discounted.

13 HM Treasury (2020, 2021).

15 HM Treasury (2020).

16 We are now measuring wellbeing on a ‘ratio scale’ implying that we can say A is twice as happy as B. This is a further assumption that goes beyond (but does not contradict) the case for an interval scale which we made in Chapter 1.

17 See Chapter 10.

18 For example, Rawls (Reference Rawls1971) – see equation (5) below.

19 The symbol f(Wi) means a magnitude that varies with Wi. The symbol f′ means the increase in that magnitude as Wi increases by 1 unit. The symbol f′′ means the increase in f′ as Wi grows by one unit. If we assume that dead people have no social value, we have to choose a f(W) function that has the property that f(0) = 0.

20 Harsanyi (1953, Reference Harsanyi1955); Rawls (Reference Rawls1971).

21 Dolan (Reference Dolan2014) p. 179.

22 This is not contrary to the principle that future prospects should be valued according to their ‘expected utility’, as Harsanyi (1953, Reference Harsanyi1955) argued, i.e., according to Σπiui where πi is the probability of outcome i and ui is the ‘utility’ of outcome i. This is because for every outcome i there is a value ui such that the person is indifferent between the outcome i (experienced with certainty) and, alternatively, the probability ui of the best outcome plus the probability 1−ui of the worst outcome. But Egalitarians would argue that if people are risk averse, uiwill be a concave function of true happiness, Wi: thus ui=fWif′>0f″<0.

23 One formulation of this question is to assumeS=Σ1λWiλλ≤1. We then debate the value of λ.

24 Rawls (Reference Rawls1971). (Rawls applied this judgement only to the distribution of ‘primary goods’).

25 This approach has been called ‘sufficientarian’. To encourage a focus on misery Kahneman and his colleagues devised a so-called u-index, which measures the proportion of the day in which a person is predominantly miserable (Krueger Reference Krueger2009).

26 Some modern philosophers, like the leading utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer, argue that we should stop at ΣWi partly because going any further takes us too far from what could in principle be objectively measured. De Lazari-Radek and Singer (Reference de Lazari-Radek and Singer2017).

27 Sen and Williams (Reference Sen and Williams1982). For a different view, see Smart in Smart and Williams (Reference Mill1973).

29 According to Bentham the doctrine of natural rights is ‘nonsense on stilts’. See Bentham (Reference Bentham2002).

31 See Hindriks and Douven (Reference Deaton and Cartwright2018).

32 For the scale of adaptation to many types of experience, see A. E. Clark et al. (Reference Clark, Flèche, Layard, Powdthavee and Ward2018).

34 Actually, there is not much evidence of adaptation to income once social comparisons are taken into account – see Chapter 13.

35 On noise, see Weinstein (Reference Weinstein1982).

36 See Railton (1984).

37 See, for example, Scruton (Reference Scruton1982).

38 Layard and Walters (Reference Layard and Walters1978) pp. 47–51 and references therein.

References

Further Reading

Coghill, R. C., McHaffie, J. G., and Yen, Y. F. (2003). Neural correlates of interindividual differences in the subjective experience of pain. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 100(14), 85388542.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Helliwell, J. F. (2021). Measuring and using happiness to support public policies. In , Lee et al. (Eds.). Measuring Well-Being: Interdisciplinary Perspectives from the Social Sciences and the Humanities (pp. 2949). Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. (1999). Development as Freedom. Alfred Knopf.Google Scholar
Tay, L., and Diener, E. (2011). Needs and subjective well-being around the world. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 101(2), 354.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
World Happiness Report, New York: Sustainable Development Solutions Network. Chapter 2 of the latest report.Google Scholar

Further Reading

de Lazari-Radek, K., and Singer, P. (2017). Utilitarianism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Layard, R., and Ward, G. (2020). Can We Be Happier? Evidence and Ethics. Penguin UK.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1863). Utilitarianism. Parker, Son & Bourn, West Strand.Google Scholar
Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C., and Williams, B. (1973). Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1.1 Percentage at each level of life satisfaction (0–10): United States and India

Source: Gallup World Poll 2016–2018, Cantril ladder
Figure 1

Table 1.1 Ranking of countries by their average life satisfaction (0–10)

Source: Helliwell et al (2020) Gallup World Poll 2017–2019, Cantril ladder
Figure 2

Figure 1.2 Average happiness in the United States (on a scale of 1–3)

Source: AIPO (1956–1970); NORC (1963–1976); GSS (1972–2018) grafted together onto the GSS scale based on overlapping years (see online Annex 1.1)
Figure 3

Table 1.2 Happiness in different activities

Source: Kahneman et al. (2004) Table 1. 900 Texan women
Figure 4

Figure 1.3 How genes and external environment determine wellbeing

Figure 5

Figure 1.4 How the individual and the external environment interact to produce wellbeing

Figure 6

Figure 2.1 How wellbeing is determined by behaviour

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×