Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-9pm4c Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T01:09:36.623Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Taking Unconsidered Preferences Seriously*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 April 2017

Extract

In normative economic analysis, it is conventional to treat each person's preferences as that person's own standard of value, and as the standard by which the effects of public policies on that person should be valued. The proposal that preferences should be treated in this way is usually qualified by two apparently natural conditions—that preferences are internally coherent, and that they reflect the considered judgements of the person concerned. However, there is now a great deal of evidence suggesting that, in many economic environments, preferences of the required kind simply do not exist. It seems that the preferences that govern people's actual behaviour are often incoherent and unstable. This prompts the following question: Is there a defensible form of normative economics which respects each individual's actual preferences, whatever form they take? I shall try to show that there is.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ariely, Dan, George, Loewenstein and Drazen, Prelec (2003). ‘Coherent arbitrariness’: stable demand curves without stable preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics 118: 73105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, Ken (1999). Why experiment in economics? Economic Journal 109: F16F24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broome, John (1991). Weighing Goods. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Camerer, Colin (1995). Individual decision making. In Kagel, John and Roth, Alvin (eds), The Handbook of Experimental Economics. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, pp. 587703.Google Scholar
Cubitt, Robin and Robert, Sugden (2001). On money pumps. Games and Economic Behavior 37: 121160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gauthier, David (1986). Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hey, John and Chris, Orme (1994). Investigating generalizations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica 62: 12911326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isen, A.M. (1999). Positive affect. In Dalgleish, T. and Power, M. (eds), Handbook of Cognition and Emotion. London: Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel and Amos, Tversky, eds (2000). Choices, Values and Frames. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, John (2003). Does market experience eliminate market anomalies? Quarterly Journal of Economics 118: 4171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewenstein, George (1999). Experimental economics from the viewpoint of behavioural economics. Economic Journal 109: F2534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, Graham (1999). Some lessons from past experiments and some challenges for the future. Economic Journal 109: F35F45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loomes, Graham, Chris, Starmer and Robert, Sugden (2003). Do anomalies disappear in repeated markets? Economic Journal 113: C 153166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plott, Charles (1996). Rational individual behaviour in markets and social choice processes: the discovered preference hypothesis. In Arrow, Kenneth J., Colombatto, Enrico, Perlman, Mark and Schmidt, Christian (eds), The Rational Foundations of Economic Behaviour. Basingstoke: Macmillan, pp. 225250.Google Scholar
Smith, Vernon (1994). Economics in the laboratory. Journal of Economic Perspectives 8: 113131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, Chris (1999). Experimental economics: hard science or wasteful tinkering? Economic Journal 109: F5F15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, Chris (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: the hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature 38: 332382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Starmer, Chris and Robert, Sugden (1989). Violations of the independence axiom in common ratio problems: an experimental test of some competing hypotheses. Annals of Operations Research 19: 79102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sugden, Robert (1989). Maximizing social welfare: is it the government's business? In Hamlin, Alan and Pettit, Philip (eds), The Good Polity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert (1998). The metric of opportunity. Economics and Philosophy 14: 307337.Google Scholar
Sugden, Robert (2004). The opportunity criterion: consumer sovereignty without the assumption of coherent preferences. American Economic Review 94: 10141033CrossRefGoogle Scholar