Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-xq9c7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-22T03:40:36.718Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Making the World Safe for Utilitarianism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 April 2017

Extract

Utilitarianism has a curious history. Its most celebrated founders—Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill—were radical progressives, straddling the worlds of academic philosophy, political science, economic theory and practical affairs. They made innumerable recommendations for legal, social, political and economic reform, often (especially in Bentham's case) described in fine detail. Some of these recommendations were followed, sooner or later, and many of their radical ideas have become close to articles of faith of western liberalism. Furthermore many of these recommendations were made expressly to improve the condition of the deprived, or of oppressed groups. Yet the moral theory which inspired this reforming zeal is, at least officially, utilitarianism, and when we teach this theory to our students we feel it our duty to point out the horrors that could be justified by any theory which assesses the moral quality of actions in terms of the maximization of good consequences over bad. No consequence is so bad that it cannot, in principle, be outweighed by a large aggregation of smaller goods. Hence there are circumstances in which utilitarianism can require slavery, the punishment of the innocent, and redistribution of resources from the poor to the rich, or from the disabled and the sick to the able bodied and healthy. Indeed, in the right circumstances, it can justify pretty much anything you can think of. For all their intelligence and imagination neither Bentham nor Mill seemed to recognise or discuss these catastrophic possibilities.

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, revised edition 1999), 24.Google Scholar

2 Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974), 33.Google Scholar

3 Of course Nozick also believes that Rawls has not appreciated the full force of this objection, for it undermines Rawls’ own theory too, so Nozick argues.

4 See, for example, the rule-consequentialism of Hooker, Brad, Ideal Code, Real World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

5 Anderson, Elizabeth, Value in Ethics and Economics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993)Google Scholar, and Richardson, Henry S., ‘The Stupidity of the Cost Benefit Standard’, in Cost-Benefit Analysis: Legal, Economic, and Philosophical Perspectives, Adler, M.D. and Posner, E.A. (eds.) (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001), 135167.Google Scholar

6 There is a third qualification. I believe that in some cases, in order to make adequate decisions, we need to add in factors which would not normally form part of an economic decision making mechanism. This is to say that cost-benefit analysis will often need to be supplemented by other considerations, especially where issues of risk to safety are concerned. This takes us beyond the terrain of this paper. I discuss it in Wolff, Jonathan ‘Risk, Fear, Blame, Shame and the Regulation of Public Safety’, Economics and Philosophy forthcoming.Google Scholar

7 For this way of breaking CBA into separate steps see Wolff, J. and Haubrich, D., ‘Economism and Its Limits’, in Rein, M., Moran, M. and Goodin, R. (eds.) Oxford Handbook to Public Policy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming 2006).Google Scholar

8 O'Neill, Onora, Faces of Hunger An Essay on Poverty, Development and Justice (London: Allen and Unwin, 1986), 7196.Google Scholar

9 Health and Safety Executive, Reducing Risk, Protecting People, 2001, http://www.hse.gov.uk/risk/theory/r2p2.htmGoogle Scholar

10 SirBudd, Alan et al. , Gambling Review Body Report, DCMS 2001, http://www.culture.gov.uk/global/publications/archive_2001/gamb_rev_report.htm Interestingly this highest figure was mentioned on the front page of the Daily Mail on 16 October 2004 as part of their campaign against the liberalisation of U.K. gambling laws. It was not mentioned that this figure was the highest of a range of estimates, or that it was produced by a group of researchers who were trying to convince their audience that an expensive form of proposed therapy for problem gamblers provided good value for money.Google Scholar

11 Sunstein, Cass, Risk and Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002)Google Scholar, Schmidtz, David, ‘A Place for Cost-Benefit Analysis’, Nous 35, No. s1 (10 2001), 148171.Google Scholar

12 Shrader-Frachette, K.S., Risk and Rationality (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991).Google Scholar

13 HM Treasury Green Book, Appraisal and Evaluation in Central Government, 2003, Annex 5 http://greenbook.treasury.gov.uk/Google Scholar

14 Parfit, Derek, ‘Equality and Priority’, Ratio 10, No. 3 (12 1997)Google Scholar, ‘Equality and Priority’, 202–221.

Banner, Michael et al. Animal Procedures Committee Recommendations On Cost-Benefit Assessment Under The Animals (Scientific Procedures) Act 1986, 2003, http://www.apc.gov.uk/Google Scholar

16 Bentham, Jeremy, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Burns, J.H. and Hart, H.L.A. (eds.) (London: Athlone, 1970,) 1721.Google Scholar

17 Op. cit. note 16, 25.

18 See, for example, Gutmann, A. and Thomson, D., Why Deliberative Democracy? (Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19 Op. cit. note 1, 19–36.

20 Kukathas, C. and Pettit, P., John Rawls' ‘Theory of Justice’ and Its Critics (Oxford: Polity Press, 1991)Google Scholar

21 Barry, Brian, ‘Does Democracy Cause Inflation? The Political Ideas of Some Economists’Google Scholar, in Lindberg, L. and Maier, C.The Politics Of Inflation And Economic Stagnation (Washington DC: The Brookings Institute, 1985), 280318.Google Scholar

22 Still less by deliberative democracy, of course.

23 And indeed where a large surplus is envisaged compensation to those who lose in the short-term may often be possible (although for some qualifications to this see note 32 below).

24 Op. cit. note 1, 134.

25 Op. cit. note 1, 147–8. Indeed after this paper was substantially drafted I noticed that in these pages Rawls attributes a version of the view defended here to Edgeworth, and then points out and challenges the underlying assumptions. Some of the arguments of this paper can, therefore, be read as responses to Rawls' criticisms of Edgeworth.

26 However although a different choice is called for, it is less obvious that this case shows that the policy of maximizing average utility has been abandoned. Those with no money at all have steeply diminishing marginal utilities for money, and so 50% chance of £300 will, under these circumstances, have less utility than £100.

27 Can it be that the policies of maximizing expected money and maximizing expected utility come apart? In the short term this is possible, and it is even possible to think up examples in which one maximizes actual utility by following the policy of maximizing not expected utility but expected money (where marginal utilities decline one will refuse risks that would be profitable in utility terms in a longer series). However in a longer series the calculations are more awkward as the utility of money depends not only on how much you receive in total but whether you receive it when you need it or can otherwise make good use of it.

28 Does this reveal some sort of class bias? Martin O'Neill asks whether we would accept the loss so easily if we could predict the death of a teacher or doctor?

29 For further discussion see Wolff, , op. cit. note 6.Google Scholar

30 Wolff, Jonathan and de-Shalit, Avner, Disadvantage (Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming 2006)Google Scholar. For similar arguments, see Barry, Brian, Why Social Justice Matters (Oxford: Polity Press, 2005).Google Scholar

31 See, for example, Sen, A. and Williams, B., Introduction to Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982)Google Scholar. And, indeed, I have argued for incommensurability myself, see Jonathan Wolff, Addressing Disadvantage and the Good, Human, Journal of Applied Philosophy 2002, 19, No. 3, (2002), 207218.Google Scholar

32 If this is right then it explains why the apparently appealing idea of ‘cost-benefit analysis with real compensation’; (i.e., those who would lose are compensated with money so that no one actually loses) is more problematic than it may seem. Of course compensation with money can be better than no compensation (although not in every case, see Frey, Bruno, Not Just for the Money (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 1997))Google Scholar but unless strong commensurability holds it will not ‘return’ people to their baseline situation.

33 See note 13.

34 Wolff, Jonathan, ‘Rational, Fair and Reasonable in Kelly, P. J. (ed.) Impartiality, Neutrality and Justice (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1998), 3543Google Scholar. This is, of course, very similar to the idea of cost-benefit analysis with real compensation, mentioned in footnote 32.

35 Bentham, Jeremy, Securities Against Misrule and Other Constitutional Writings for Tripoli and Greece, (ed.) Schofield, Philip (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 38Google Scholar. I thank Philip Schofield for drawing my attention to this text.

36 Op. cit note 1, xiv.

37 I am very grateful Shepley Orr for bringing this to my attention. Musgrave, Richard, The Theory of Public Finance (New York: McGraw Hill, 1959).Google Scholar

38 Kymlicka, Will, Contemporary Political Philosophy, 2nd edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar

39 I would like to thank audiences at the R.I.P. lecture in London, and Cambridge for their comments and criticisms. I would especially like to thank Veronique Munoz Darde, Martin O'Neill, Shepley Orr, and Michael Otsuka, for extremely helpful written comments.