Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-p2v8j Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2024-05-21T02:51:21.329Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

In the Mood: Why Vibes Matter in Reading and Writing Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 May 2023

Abstract

Philosophers often write in a particular mood; their work is playful, strident, strenuous, or nostalgic. On the face of it, these moods contribute little to a philosophical argument and are merely incidental. However, I will argue that the cognitive science of moods and emotions offers us reasons to suspect that mood is relevant for philosophical texts. I use examples from Friedrich Nietzsche and Rudolph Carnap to illustrate the role moods play in their arguments. As readers and writers of philosophical texts, we do well to attend to mood.

Type
Paper
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ansell-Pearson, K. and Bamford, R., Nietzsche's Dawn. Philosophy, Ethics, and the Passion of Knowledge (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell, 2021).Google Scholar
Ayala, S., ‘Philosophy and the Non-Native Speaker Condition’, American Philosophical Association Newsletter, 14:2 (2015), 29.Google Scholar
Baas, M., De Dreu, C.K., and Nijstad, B.A., ‘A Meta-Analysis of 25 Years of Mood-Creativity Research: Hedonic Tone, Activation, or Regulatory Focus?’, Psychological Bulletin, 134:6 (2008), 779806.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bamford, R., ‘Mood and Aphorism in Nietzsche's Campaign against Morality’, Pli: The Warwick Journal of Philosophy, 25 (2014), 5576.Google Scholar
Bamford, R., ‘The Relationship between Science and Philosophy as a Key Feature of Nietzsche's Metaphilosophy’, in Meyer, M. and Loeb, P.S. (eds.), Nietzsche's Metaphilosophy: The Nature, Method, and Aims of Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2019), 6582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beedie, C., Terry, P., and Lane, A., ‘Distinctions between Emotion and Mood’, Cognition & Emotion, 19:6 (2005), 847878.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blanchette, I. and Richards, A., ‘The Influence of Affect on Higher Level Cognition: A Review of Research on Interpretation, Judgement, Decision Making and Reasoning’, Cognition & Emotion, 24:4 (2010), 561595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bless, H., Bohner, G., Schwarz, N., and Strack, F., ‘Mood and Persuasion: A Cognitive Response Analysis’, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 16:2 (1990), 331345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bower, G.H., ‘Mood and Memory’, American Psychologist, 36:2 (1981), 129148.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cappelen, H., Philosophy without Intuitions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, R., The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems in Philosophy (George, R.A., trans.), (Chicago and LaSalle, IL: Open Court, 1928 [2003]).Google Scholar
Clore, G.L. and Huntsinger, J.R., ‘How Emotions Inform Judgment and Regulate Thought’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11:9 (2007), 393399.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Danto, A.C., ‘Philosophy as/and/of Literature’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 58:1 (1984), 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Djikic, M., Oatley, K., Zoeterman, S., and Peterson, J.B., ‘On Being Moved by Art: How Reading Fiction Transforms the Self’, Creativity Research Journal, 21:1 (2009), 2429.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dutilh Novaes, C., ‘Carnapian Explication and Ameliorative Analysis: A Systematic Comparison’, Synthese, 197:3 (2020), 10111034.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ekkekakis, P., ‘Affect, Mood, and Emotion’, in Tenenbaum, G., Ecklundt, R.C., and Kamata, A. (eds.), Measurement in Sport and Exercise Psychology (Campaign, IL: Human Kinetics, 2012), 321332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeman, L., ‘Toward a Phenomenology of Mood’, Southern Journal of Philosophy, 52:4 (2014), 445476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frijda, N.H., ‘Mood’, in Sander, D. and Scherer, K. (eds.), The Oxford Companion to Emotion and the Affective Sciences (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 258259.Google Scholar
Galison, P., ‘Aufbau/Bauhaus: Logical Positivism and Architectural Modernism’, Critical Inquiry, 16:4 (1990), 709752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gendolla, G.H. and Brinkmann, K., ‘The Role of Mood States in Self-Regulation: Effects on Action Preferences and Resource Mobilization’, European Psychologist, 10:3 (2005), 187198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, M.C., ‘How Narrative Relationships Overcome Empathic Bias: Elizabeth Gaskell's Empathy across Social Difference’, Poetics Today, 32:2 (2011), 255288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartley, J., Sotto, E., and Fox, C., ‘Clarity across the Disciplines’, Science Communication, 26:2 (2004), 188210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heidegger, M., Being and Time (Macquarrie, J. and Robinson, E., trans.), (Oxford, UK, and Cambridge, MA): Blackwell, 1927 [1962]).Google Scholar
Kramer, A.D., Guillory, J.E., and Hancock, J.T., ‘Experimental Evidence of Massive-Scale Emotional Contagion through Social Networks’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 111:24 (2014), 87888790.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Krueger, J., ‘Affordances and the Musically Extended Mind’, Frontiers in Psychology, 4:1003 (2014), 112.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mar, R.A., Oatley, K., Djikic, M., and Mullin, J., ‘Emotion and Narrative Fiction: Interactive Influences Before, During, and After Reading, Cognition & Emotion, 25:5 (2011), 818833.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mitchell, P.B. and Malhi, G.S., ‘Bipolar Depression: Phenomenological Overview and Clinical Characteristics’, Bipolar Disorders, 6:6 (2004), 530539.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Moeller, H.G. and D'Ambrosio, P., Genuine Pretending. On the Philosophy of the Zhuangzi (New York: Columbia University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morton, A., Emotion and Imagination (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2013).Google Scholar
Nersessian, N.J., ‘In the Theoretician's Laboratory: Thought Experimenting as Mental Modeling’, in PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 291301.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F., Daybreak. Thoughts on the Prejudices of Morality, (Clark, M. and Leiter, B., eds. and Hollingsdale, R.J., trans.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1881 [1997]).Google Scholar
Nietzsche, F., On the Genealogy of Morality, (Ansell-Pearson, K., ed. and Diethe, C., trans.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1887 [2006]).Google Scholar
Norton, J.D., ‘Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26:3 (1996), 333366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oliver, M.B., ‘Tender Affective States as Predictors of Entertainment Preference’, Journal of Communication, 58:1 (2008), 4061.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Paul, L.A., Transformative Experience (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R., Choosing for Changing Selves (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020).Google Scholar
Potochnik, A. and Yap, A., ‘Revisiting Galison's ‘Aufbau/Bauhaus’ in Light of Neurath's Philosophical Projects’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 37:3 (2006), 469488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ratcliffe, M., ‘Why Mood Matters’, in Wrathall, M.A. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger's Being and Time (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), 157176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, R.C., Emotions: An Essay in Aid of Moral Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwitzgebel, E. and Cushman, F., ‘Expertise in Moral Reasoning? Order Effects on Moral Judgment in Professional Philosophers and Non-Philosophers’, Mind & Language, 27 (2012), 135153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strohminger, N., Lewis, R.L., and Meyer, D.E., ‘Divergent Effects of Different Positive Emotions on Moral Judgment’, Cognition, 119:2 (2011), 295300.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thomson, J.J., ‘A Defense of Abortion’, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 7:1 (1971), 4766.Google Scholar
Valdesolo, P. and DeSteno, D., ‘Manipulations of Emotional Context Shape Moral Judgment’, Psychological Science, 17:6 (2006), 476477.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Vavova, K., ‘Irrelevant Influences’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 96:1 (2018), 134152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar