Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-xfwgj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-19T22:25:18.487Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Folk Psychology and the Biological Basis of Intersubjectivity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 April 2017

Extract

Recent philosophical discussions of intersubjectivity generally start by stating or assuming that our ability to understand and interact with others is enabled by a ‘folk psychology’ or ‘theory of mind’. Folk psychology is characterized as the ability to attribute intentional states, such as beliefs and desires, to others, in order to predict and explain their behaviour. Many authors claim that this ability is not merely one amongst many constituents of interpersonal understanding but an underlying core that enables social life. For example, Churchland states that folk psychology ‘embodies our baseline understanding’ of others (1996, p. 3). Currie and Sterelny similarly assert that ‘our basic grip on the social world depends on our being able to see our fellows as motivated by beliefs and desires we sometimes share and sometimes do not’ (2000, p. 143). And, as Frith and Happe put it, ‘this ability appears to be a prerequisite for normal social interaction: in everyday life we make sense of each other's behaviour by appeal to a belief-desire psychology’ (1999, p. 2).

Type
Papers
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy and the contributors 2005

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baron-Cohen, S., Tager-Flusberg, H. and Cohen, D. J. (eds.) 1993. Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Bloom, P. and German, T. P.. 2000. ‘Two Reasons to Abandon the False Belief Task as a Test of the Theory of Mind’, Cognition, 77, 2531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruner, J. 1990. Acts of Meaning (Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Bruner, J, and Feldman, C.. 1993. ‘Theories of Mind and the Problem of Autism’, in Tager-Flusberg, Baron-Cohen and Cohen, (eds.), 267–91.Google Scholar
Byrne, R. and Whiten, A. (eds.) 1988. Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys, Apes and Humans (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. 2000. ‘The Evolution of Consciousness’, in Carruthers, and Chamberlain, (eds.), 254275.Google Scholar
Carruthers, P. and Smith, P. K. (eds.) 1996. Theories of Theories of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carruthers, P. and Chamberlain, A. (eds.) 2000. Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Meta-Cognition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. 1996. ‘Folk Psychology’, in Churchland, P. M. and Churchland, P. S.. On the Contrary: Critical Essays 1987—1997 (Cambridge Mass., London: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Clark, A. 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again (Cambridge Mass., London: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Cole, J. 1998. About Face (Cambridge Mass., London: MIT Press).Google Scholar
Cole, J. 2001. ‘The Contribution of the Face in the Development of Emotion and Self, in Kaszniak, (ed.), 478–82.Google Scholar
Currie, G. and Sterelny, K.. 2000. ‘How to think about the Modularity of Mind-Reading. Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 143–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds.) 1995a. Mental Simulation: Evaluations and Applications (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Stone, T. (eds.) 1995b. Folk Psychology: The Theory of Mind Debate (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Donald, M. 1991. Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages in the Evolution of Culture and Cognition (Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Dunbar, R. 2000. ‘On the Origin of the Human Mind’, in Carruthers, and Chamberlain, (eds.), 238—53.Google Scholar
Frith, U. and Happe, F.. 1999. ‘Theory of Mind and Self-Consciousness: What is it Like to be Autistic?’ Mind and Language, 14, 1—22.Google Scholar
Fogassi, L. and Gallese, V.. 2002. ‘The Neural Correlates of Action Understanding in Non-Human Primates’, in Stamenov, and Gallese, (eds), 1335.Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. 2001. ‘The Practice of Mind: Theory, Simulation, or Primary Interaction?’, in Thompson, (ed.), 83108.Google Scholar
Gallese, V. and Goldman, A.. 1998. ‘Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind-Reading’, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 2, 493501.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Garfield, J. L., Peterson, C. C. and Perry, T.. 2001. ‘Social Cognition, Language Acquisition and the Development of the Theory of Mind’, Mind and Language, 16, 494—541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. 2000. The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Gopnik, A. 1996. ‘Theories and Modules: Creation Myths, Developmental Realities, and Neurath's Boat’, in Carruthers, and Smith, (eds.), 169–83.Google Scholar
Gordon, R. 1996. ‘“Radical” Simulation’, in Carruthers, and Smith, (eds.), 1121.Google Scholar
Hobson, P. 1993(a) Autism and the Development of Mind (Hove (UK): Lawrence Erlbaum Associates).Google Scholar
Hobson, P. 1993(b). ‘Understanding Persons: The Role of Affect’, in Baron-Cohen, , Tager-Flusberg, and Cohen, (eds.), 204—27.Google Scholar
Hobson, P. 2002. The Cradle of Thought (London: Macmillan).Google Scholar
Kaszniak, A. (ed.) 2001. Emotions, Qualia and Consciousness (London: World Scientific).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lord, C. 1993. ‘The Complexity of Social Behaviour in Autism’, in Baron-Cohen, , Tager-Flusberg, and Cohen, (eds.), 292316.Google Scholar
Morton, M. 2003. The Importance of being Understood: Folk Psychology as Ethics (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Papafragou, A. 2002. ‘Mindreading and Verbal Communication’, Mind and Language, 17, 5567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rizzolatti, G., Craighero, L. and Fadiga, L.. 2002. ‘The Mirror System in Humans’, in Stamenov, and Gallese, (eds.), 37—9.Google Scholar
Rotondo, J. L. and Boker, S. M.. 2002. ‘Behavioral Synchronization in Human Conversational Interaction’, in Stamenov, and Gallese, (eds.), 151–62.Google Scholar
Sartre, J. P. 1989. Being and Nothingness (trans. Barnes, H. E.) (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Scholl, B. J. and Leslie, A. M.. 1999. ‘Modularity, Development and “Theory of Mind”’, Mind and Language, 14, 131–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sperber, D. and Wilson, D.. 2002. ‘Pragmatics, Modularity and Mindreading’, Mind and Language, 17, 323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stamenov, M. I. and Gallese, V. eds. 2002. Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language (Amsterdam, Philadelphia: John Benjamins).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. and Ravenscroft, I.. 1996. ‘What Is Folk Psychology?’, in Stich, . Deconstructing the Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Studdert-Kennedy, M. 2002. ‘Mirror Neurons, Vocal Imitation, and the Evolution of Particulate Speech’, in Stamenov, and Gallese, (eds.), 207–27.Google Scholar
Thompson, E. ed. 2001. Between Ourselves: Second-Person Issues in the Study of Consciousness (Thornton, UK: Imprint Academic).Google Scholar
Walsh, D. (ed.) 2001. Naturalism, Evolution and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimmer, H. and Perner, J.. 1983. ‘Beliefs about Beliefs: Representation and Constraining Function of Wrong Beliefs in Young Children's Understanding of Deception’, Cognition, 13, 103–28.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Whiten, A. 2001. ‘Theory of Mind in Non-Verbal Apes: Conceptual Issues and the Critical Experiments’, in Walsh, (ed.), 199223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar