Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T04:04:59.165Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Value-definiteness and Contextualism: Cut and Paste with Hilbert Space

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Allen Stairs*
Affiliation:
University of Maryland

Extract

My topics are two theses about quantum mechanics that are widely doubted but curiously tempting: value-definiteness and contextualism. Value-definiteness holds that every observable has a definite value; contextualism follows from value-definiteness, and claims that one Hermitian operator can represent many observables. In fact, contextualism is my deeper interest Although it is not a view with an army of defenders, it has a long history of discussion in the literature. (See, for example, Belinfante 1973, van Fraassen 1973, Shimony 1984, Redhead 1987). The bulk of this paper will be concerned with a puzzle about degenerate operators that arises out of the standard accounts of contextualism. But before we get to the details, let us begin with a lurid example.

Type
Part III. Quantum Theory I
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Belinfante, FJ. (1973), A Survey of Hidden Variable Theories, Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
Bohm, David (1980), Wholeness and the Implicate Order. London: Routledge, Kegan and Paul.Google Scholar
Fine, A. (1974), “On the Completeness of Quantum Theory”, Synthese 29,257-89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Arthur (1987), “With Complacency or Concern: Solving the Quantum Measurement Problem”, in Kelvin's Baltimore Lectures and Theoretical Physics: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives Kargon, Robert and Achinstein, Peter (eds.). Cambridge: The MIT Press, pp. 491-506.Google Scholar
Hughes, R.I.G. (1989), “Bell's Theorem, Ideology and Structural Explanation”, in Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory: Reflections on Bell's Theorem Cushing, James T. and McMullin, Ernan (eds.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 195-207.Google Scholar
Jarrett, Jon P. (1984), “On the Physical Significance of the Locality Conditions in the Bell Arguments”, Noûs 18:569-589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Martin and Clifton, Robert K. (unpublished), “Incompleteness and Superluminal Signalling”.Google Scholar
Kochen, S. and Specker, E.P. (1967), “The Problem of Hidden Variables in Quantum Mechanics”, Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics 17:59-87.Google Scholar
Redhead, Michael (1987), Incompleteness, Nonlocality and Realism: A Prolegomenon to the Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Shimony, Abner (1984), “Contextual Hidden Variable Theories and Bell's inequalities”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35: 25-45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stairs, Allen (1983), “On the Logic of Pairs of Quantum Systems”, Synthese 56: 437-460Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. (1973), “Semantic Analysis of Quantum Logic”, in Hooker, C.A. (ed.) Contemporary Research in the Philosophy and Foundations of Quantum Theory. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 80-113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar