Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-lrf7s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-31T09:12:27.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Salmon, Statistics and Backwards Causation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

David Papineau*
Affiliation:
Macquarie University

Extract

Smokers are more likely to develop lung cancer than non-smokers. This statistical association gives us reason to suppose that smoking can cause lung cancer. But we would come to reject this supposition if we discovered that when family histories of lung cancer are taken into account smoking makes no further difference to the probability of lung cancer: that amongst those with a family history of lung cancer (and amongst those without) non-smokers are just as likely to develop lung cancer as smokers. Such a discovery would lead us to conclude that, despite initial appearances, smoking actually makes no causal contribution to lung cancer, but is statistically associated with it only because a genetic predisposition to lung cancer also somehow predisposes people to smoke.

Type
Part VIII. Applications of Statistical Ideas
Copyright
Copyright © 1978 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I am grateful to Hugh Mellor and Graham Nerlich for comments on earlier versions of this paper. The argument about backwards causation was originally suggested by a conversation with Dan Gvirtzman. Further treatment of some of the issues herein is given in Chapter 3 of my forthcoming For Science in the Social Sciences, London: Macmillan, 1978.

References

Mackie, J.L.Causes and Conditions.American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (1965): 245-55 and 261-4.Google Scholar
Mackie, J.L. The Cement of the Universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974.Google Scholar
Salmon, W.C.Statistical Explanation.” In Nature and Function of Scientific Theories. (University of Pittsburgh Series in Philosophy of Science, Volume 4.) Edited by Colodny, Robert G.. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1970. Pages 173231. (As reprinted in Salmon, W.C. et. al. Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1971. Pages 29-87.)Google Scholar
Salmon, W.C.Theoretical Explanation.” In Explanation. Edited by S. Körner. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975. Pages 118145 with discussion to p. 184.Google Scholar
Sanford, D.H.The Direction of Causation and the Direction of Conditionship.Journal of Philosophy 73 (1976): 193207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sayre, K.M.Statistical Models of Causal Relations.Philosophy of Science 44(1977): 203-14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppes, P. A Probabilistic Theory of Causality (Acta Philosophica Fennica XXIV.) Amsterdam: North Holland, 1970.Google Scholar