Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-t6hkb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T10:14:31.014Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconstructed Science as Philosophical Evidence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Nancy L. Maull*
Affiliation:
Yale University

Extract

Since there is a philosophy of science, it is not surprising that philosophers make use of case studies from the history of science in their work. However, the uses to which such case studies can be put depend on important, but not always acknowledged, ideas about how to understand science. According to one view, philosophy provides a theoretically precise account of science,and case studies are the raw material which, when reinterpreted according to a theoretical account, illustrate that account. Thus, just as formal logic is sometimes said to reduce ordinary language to a fixed and, from one standpoint, more convenient form, so the philosophy of science is often thought to perform a similar function for science. But other philosophers, with different ideas about how to understand science, think that case studies from the history of science can provide evidence for philosophy's claims about (scientific) rationality.

Type
Part IV. History and Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1976 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Feyerabend, P. K.. “Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. 3. Edited by Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G.. Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1962. Pages 28-97.Google Scholar
Giere, R. “History and Philosophy of Science: Intimate Relationship or Marriage of Convenience.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (1973): 282-297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R. Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1958.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press, 1962.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Edited by Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970. Pages 91-196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, E. “The History and Philosophy of Science: A Taxonomy.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. 5. Edited by Stuewer, R. H.. Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 1970. Pages 12-67.Google Scholar
Masterman, M. “The Nature of a Paradigm.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Edited by I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970. Pages 59-90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper & Row, 1965.Google Scholar
Shapere, D. “Scientific Theories and Their Domains.” In The Structure of Scientific Theories. Edited by Suppe, F.. Urbana, Illinois: University of Illinois Press, 1974. Pages 518-565.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. “Of the Transformation of Hypotheses in the History of Science.” In William Whewell's Theory of Scientific Method. Edited by Butts, R. E.. Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1968. Pages 251-264.Google Scholar