Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-v5vhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-29T09:25:48.614Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophy of Psychology Meets the Semantic View

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Valerie Gray Hardcastle*
Affiliation:
Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University

Extract

Philosophers of science have much to say that could be useful to philosophers of mind, especially naturalistic philosophers of psychology. We should listen. In particular, I believe that if philosophers of mind were clearer on how explanations function in science in general, then many of their present worries would either dissolve or be altered beyond recognition. In what follows, I show you what I mean.

First, though, I shall spend a few moments recapitulating the semantic view of theories and how it applies to psychology. This section will be fairly brief since details have already been presented elsewhere (see esp. Bickle 1993). However, let me emphasize at the outset that I am not adopting the semantic view because I think it is inherently superior to the more traditional models (though I do). Indeed, everything that I claim can be translated into any view of theory you might have with greater or lesser ease.

Type
Part II. Philosophy of Psychology as Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1995 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armstrong, D.M. (1970), “The Nature of Mind”, in Borst, C.V., (ed.), The Mind/Brain Identity Theory. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Armstrong, D.M. (1977), “The Causal Theory of the Mind”, Neue Heft für Philosophie. 11: 8295.Google Scholar
Bickle, J. (1993), “Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Semantic View of Theories”, Erkenntnis 39: 359382.10.1007/BF01128508CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1980), Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1987), The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Pres.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1992), Explaining Consciousness. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Engel, A.K., Konig, P., and Singer, W. (1991), “Direct Physiological Evidence for Scene Segmentation by Temporal Coding”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 88: 9136–1940.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fodor, J.A. (1989), “Making the Mind Matter More”, Philosophical Topics 17: 5980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, J. (1983) “Supervenience and Supervenient Causation”, Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (Suppl.): 54.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1992a) “‘Downward Causation’ in Emergence and Nonreductive Physicalism”, in Beckerman, A., Flohr, H., and Kim, J., (eds.), Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism. New York: Walter de Gruyter, pp. 119138.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1992b) “Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LII: 126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1981), Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
LePore, E., and Loewer, B. (1987) “Mind Matters”, Journal of Philosophy 84: 630642.Google Scholar
LePore, E., and Loewer, B. (1989) “More on Making the Mind Matter”, Philosophical Topics 17: 175191.10.5840/philtopics198917117CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1970), “How to Define Theoretical Terms”, Journal of Philosophy 67: 427444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1972), “Psychophysical and Theoretical Identification”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50: 249258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1969), “Review of Art, Mind and Religion”, Journal of Philosophy 66: 2335.10.2307/2024154CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prinzmetal, W. (1981), “Principles of Feature Integration in Visual Perception”, Perception and Psychophysics 30: 330340.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schneider, W. and Shiffrin, R.M. (1977), “Controlled and Automatic Human Information Processing: I. Detection, Search, and Attention”, Psychological Review 84: 166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shiffrin, R.M. and Schneider, W. (1977), “Controlled and Automatic Human Information Processing: II. Perceptual Learning, Automatic Attending, and General Theory”, Psychological Review 84: 127190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. (1992), The Rediscovery of Mind. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shagrir, O. (1991), “Computation”, unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Smart, J.J.C. (1959), “Sensations and Brain Processes”, Philosophical Review 68: 141156.10.2307/2182164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smart, J.J.C. (1971), “Reports of Immediate Experience”, Synthese 22: 346359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stabler, E.P. Jr., (1987), “Kripke on Functionalism and Automata”, Synthese 70: 122.10.1007/BF00414025CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Treisman, A. (1986), “Features and Objects in Visual Processing”, Scientific American 254: 114b125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar