Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-n9wrp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T01:13:35.590Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Dynamics of Theory Change: The Role of Predictions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Stephen G. Brush*
Affiliation:
University of Maryland, College Park

Extract

“What did the President know and when did he know it?”

Senator Howard Baker, Watergate hearings, 1973

Why do scientists accept or reject theories? More specifically: why do they change from one theory to another? What is the role of empirical tests in the evaluation of theories?

This paper focuses on a narrowly-defined question: in judging theories, do scientists give greater weight (other things being equal) to successful novel predictions than to successful deductions of previously-known facts? The affirmative answer is called the “predictivist thesis” (Maher 1988).

It is primarily philosophers who are interested in this question, and they have treated it mostly as a normative or logical problem. Can the writings of historians of science tell us how scientists have treated novel predictions in the past? Until recently historians have rarely addressed this point.

Type
Part V. Do Explanations or Predictions (or Neither) Provide More Evidential Support for Scientific Theories?
Copyright
Copyright © 1995 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I thank Lindley Darden and Frederick Suppe for valuable criticism of earlier drafts; useful suggestions and comments have been received from Laurie Brown, David Cassidy, Max Jammer, Helge Kragh, Larry Laudan, Edward MacKinnon, Arthur Miller, Helmut Rechenberg, Eric Scerri, and Katherine Sopka. Louis Brown first called my attention to the significance of Mott scattering as a novel prediction of quantum mechanics.

My research has been supported by the National Science Foundation, the National Endowment for the Humanities, the Institute for Advanced Study (Princeton), the Andrew W. Mellon Foundation, and the University of Maryland General Research Board.

References

Achinstein, P. (1991), Particles and Waves: Historical Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brush, S.G. (1989), “Prediction and Theory Evaluation: The Case of Light Bending”, Science 246: 11241129.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brush, S.G. (1990), “Prediction and Theory Evaluation: Alfvén on Space Plasma Phenomena”, Eos: Transactions of the American Geophysical Union 71: 1933.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brush, S.G. (1993a), “Prediction and Theory Evaluation: Cosmic Microwaves and the Revival of the Big Bang”, Perspectives on Science 1: 565602.Google Scholar
Brush, S.G. (1993b), “Prediction and Theory Evaluation: Subatomic Particles”, Rivista di Storia della Scienza [2] 1, no. 2: 47152.Google Scholar
Carrier, M. (1991), “What is wrong with the Miracle Argument?”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22: 2336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrier, M. (1993), “What is right with the Miracle Argument: Establishing a Taxonomy of Natural Kinds”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 24: 391409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C.G. (1931), The New Conceptions of Matter. London: Bell & Sons.Google Scholar
Donovan, A., Laudan, L. and Laudan, R. (eds.), (1988), Scrutinizing science: Empirical Studies of Scientific Change. Boston: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, J. and Glymour, C. (1978), “Einstein and Hilbert: Two Months in the History of General Relativity”, Archive for History of Exact Sciences 19: 291308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Everitt, C.W.F. (1980), “Experimental Tests of General Relativity: Past, Present and Future”, in Physics and Contemporary Needs, volume 4, Riazuddin (ed.) New York: Plenum, pp. 529555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feynman, R.P. (1967), The Character of Physical Law. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Garber, D. (1983), “Old Evidence and logical omniscience in Bayesian confirmation Theory”, in Testing Scientific Theories, Earman, J. (ed.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 99131.Google Scholar
Gardner, M.R. (1982), “Predicting Novel Facts”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33: 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gingras, Y. (1981), “La Physique à McGill entre 1920 et 1940: La Réception de la Mécanique Quantique par une Communauté Scientifique Péripherique”, HSTC Bulletin 5 (1): 1539. Reprinted in Science, Technology and Medicine in Canada's Past, R. A. Jarrell and J. P. Hull (eds.). Thornhill, Ontario, Canada: Scientia Press (1991), pp. 105-128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence. Princeton:Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Gurr, T.R. and Lichbach, M.I. (1986), “Forecasting Internal Conflict: A Competitive Evaluation of Empirical Theories”, Comparative Political Studies 19: 338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heisenberg, W. (1963), Interviews with Thomas S. Kuhn. Tapes 50b and 52. Archive for History of Quantum Physics. Transcript at Niels Bohr Library, Center for History of Physics, College Park, MD.Google Scholar
Howson, C. (1984), “Bayesianism and support by novel facts”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35: 245-51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. (1989), “Accommodation, Prediction, and Bayesian Confirmation Theory”, in PSA 1988, vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 381392.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993), The Advancement of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970), “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes”, in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.). New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 91196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1974), “Popper on Demarcation and Induction”, in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Schilpp, P.A. (ed.). La Salle, IL: Open Court, pp. 241273.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981), “A Confutation of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science 48: 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1982), “The Historical Objection to Scientific Realism”, in PSA 1982, volume 1, East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 8897.Google Scholar
Leplin, J., (ed.) (1984), Scientific Realism. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P. (1990), “Prediction and Prejudice”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4, no 1: 5165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P. (1991), Inference to the Best Explanation. London & New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P. (1988), “Prediction, Accommodation, and the Logic of Discovery”, in PSA 1988, volume 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 273285.Google Scholar
Margenau, H. (1950) The Nature of Physical Reality. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. (1988), “Brownian Motion and the Appraisal of Theories”, in Donovan, A., Laudan, L. and Laudan, R. (eds.) (1988), pp. 219243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. (1991), “Novel Evidence and Severe Tests,Philosophy of Science 58: 523552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayr, E. (1985), “How Biology differs from the Physical Sciences”, in Evolution at a Crossroads, Depew, D.J. and Weber, B.C. (eds.). Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 4963.Google Scholar
Meehl, P.E. (1992), “The Miracle Argument for Realism: An important Lesson to be Learned by Generalizing from Carrier's Counter-examples”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 23: 267-82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendeleev, D. (1902), The Principles of Chemistry, Volume 2, Part 3. 2nd English ed. New York: Collier.Google Scholar
Mott, N.F. (1962) “Notes by Prof. Mott on his Personal Experiences of the Development of Quantum Physics.” Unpublished memoir in Archive for History of Quantum Physics. Copy at Niels Bohr Library, Center for History of Physics, College Park, MD.Google Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1988), “The Ultimate Argument for Scientific Realism”, in Relativism and Realism in Science, Nola, R. (ed.). Boston: Kluwer, pp. 229252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Petroni, A. (1993), “Conventionalism, Scientific Discovery and the Sociology of Knowledge”, International Studies in Philosophy of Science 7: 225240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1978), Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Scerri, E.R. (1994), “Prediction, Accommodation and the Periodic Table”, preprint.Google Scholar
Schrödinger, E. (1952), “Are there Quantum Jumps?”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 3: 109123, 233-242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, J.L. (1980), “Resources, Population, Environment: An Oversupply of False Bad News”, Science 208: 14311437.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Simon, J.L. (1981), The Ultimate Resource. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simon, J.L. (1990), Population Matters: People, Resources, Environment, and Immigration. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Small, H. (1981), Physics Citation Index 1920-1929. Philadelphia: Institute for Scientific Information.Google Scholar
Spottiswoode, W. (1882), President's Address, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 34: 302329.Google Scholar
Strahler, A.N. (1987), Science and Earth History. The Evolution/Creation Controversy. Buffalo: Prometheus.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1992), Dreams of a Final Theory. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
Zahar, E. (1973), “Why did Einstein's Programme supersede Lorentz's?”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24: 95123, 223-262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar