Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-tdptf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-08T11:01:41.249Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Dutch Book Arguments and Consistency

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 June 2023

Colin Howson*
Affiliation:
The London School of Economics and Political Science

Extract

Classical Bayesian methodology is based on the following three principles:

  1. (i) individuals have degrees of belief which, measured in the closed unit interval, and subject to a mild consistency constraint, are fonnally probabilities.

  2. (ii) belief functions are updated with the acquisition of new evidence by Bayesian conditionalisation. In other words, if B is learned to be true, then your new probability function P′ takes the value P′(A) = P(A/B) on every A in domain P′, where P is your probability function prior to learning B.

  3. (iii) where Hi is a statistical hypothesis and E sample data, the tenns P(E|Hi) in Bayes’ Theorem calculations are set equal to the probability assigned E by Hi.

Type
Part V: Bayesian Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1993 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Armendt, B. (1980), “ Is there a Dutch Book Argument for Probability Kinematics?”, Philosophy of Science, 47: 583-588CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (1991), “Clever Bookies and Coherent Beliefs”, Philosophical Review, 229-247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Finetti, B. (1937), “Foresight: its Logical Laws, its Subjective Sources”, (English translation of “La prevision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives“) Studies in Subjective Probability, H.E. Kyburg and H. Smokler (eds), New York: Krieger, 1980.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1967), “Slightly More Realistic Personal Probability”, Philosophy of Science, 34: 311-325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halmos, P. (1950), Measure Theory, New York: van Nostrand.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1993), Scientific Reasoning: the Bayesian Approach (second edition). Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Jeffrey, R. C. (1987), Probability and the Art of Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1976), “Probabilities of Conditionals and Conditional Probabilities”, Philosophical Review, 85: 297-315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mellor, D. H. (1971), The Matter of Chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (forthcoming), “A Mistake in Dynamic Coherence Arguments”Google Scholar
Teller, P. (1973), “Conditionalisation and Observation”, Synthese, 26: 218-258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B.C. (1984), “Belief and the Will”, Journal of Philosophy, 81: 235-256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B.C. (1989), Laws and Symmetry, Oxford: the Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar