Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-wbk2r Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-19T01:55:04.885Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Consensus and Evolution in Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Gonzalo Munevar*
Affiliation:
University of Nebraska at Omaha

Extract

The bulk of this paper will be divided into three sections. I will first sketch what I take to be the main problem in the epistemology of science and explain how the issue of consensus is related to this problem. I will then try to solve the problem by using a social conception of scientific rationality based on evolutionary ideas. And I will finally elaborate that social conception by responding to several objections.

For over two decades now, many philosophers have talked about the existence of a crisis in the epistemology of science. This crisis presumably came about as the result of the dispute between two schools of thought: the logical and the socio-historical. The logical school is associated with the analytic and empiricist tradition in the field and is supposed to defend the rationality of science. The socio-historical, whose most notorious exponents are Kuhn (1970) and Feyerabend (1975), has been accused of irrationalism.

Type
Part IV. Science Studies
Copyright
Copyright © 1987 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Brush, S.G. (1986) “The Age of the Earth in the 20th Century,” in Inventing the World: Theories of the Origin and Structure of the Solar System. Work in progress. Preprints available from S.G. Brush at Committee on the History and Philosophy of Science, University of Maryland, College Park, MD 20742.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P.K. (1975) Against Method. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P.K. (1978) Science in a Free Society. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P.K. (1981a) Realism, Rationalism, and Scientific Method. Philosophical Papers, Vol 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, P.K. (1981b) Problems of Empiricism. Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, CG. (1978). “Scientific Rationality: Normative vs. Descriptive Construals,” in Wittgenstein, The Vienna Circle and Critical Rationalism. Proceedings of the 3rd International Wittgenstein Symposium.Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1978a) “Understanding Toulmin.” Minerva. 14, pages 126-143. (As reprinted in his Mathematics, Science and Epistemology. J. Worrall and G. Currie (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 224-243).Google Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1978b) The Problem of Appraising Scientific Theories.” Mathematics, Science and Epistemology. J. Worrall and G. Currie (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 107-120.Google Scholar
Lorenz, K. (1971) Studies in Animal Behavior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Munevar, G. (1981) Radical Knowledge: A Philosophical Inquiry into the Nature and Limits of Science. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Munevar, G. (1984) “Towards a Future Epistemology of Science.” Explorations in Knowledge. Vol. 1. Pages 1-17.Google Scholar
Munevar, G. (1987) “Peter Singer's The Expanding Circle: Ethics and Sociobiology.” Explorations in Knowledge. Vol. 4, No. 1. Pages 43-50.Google Scholar
Piaget, J. (1972) The Psychology of Intelligence. Translated by Piercy, M. and Berlyne, D.E.. Totowa, NJ: Littlefield, Adams, and Co.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1972) Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Toulmin, S. (1972) Human Understanding. Vol. 1. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar