Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-cnmwb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T08:16:01.916Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Can We Reduce Causal Direction to Probabilities?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 June 2023

David Papineau*
Affiliation:
King's College London

Extract

This paper will be a mirror image of Huw Price's paper. Like Price, I shall first introduce the “fork asymmetry”, then consider objections to using it to analyse causal asymmetry, and finally examine the relation between causation and human agency. But where Price rejects analyses of causal asymmetry in terms of the fork asymmetry, and so turns to human agency to ground an alternative account of both the causal and fork asymmetries, I defend the fork asymmetry analysis of causation, and correspondingly want to explain agency in terms of the fork asymmetry, rather than vice versa.

Type
Part VIII. Statistical Asymmetries and the Direction of Causation
Copyright
Copyright © 1993 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Amtzenius, F. (1990), “Physics and Common Causes”, Synthese 82: 77-96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1989), Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. and Jones, M. (1991), “How to Hunt Quantum Causes”, Erkenntnis 35: 205-231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummett, M. (1964), “Bringing About the Past”, Philosophical Review 73: 338-359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehring, D. (1982), “Causal Asymmetry”, Journal of Philosophy 79: 761-774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. (1984), “Causal Priority, Nous 18: 143-54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Healey, R. (1992), “Causation, Robustness and EPR”, Philosophy of Science 59: 282-292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. (1987), Asymmetries in Time. Cambridge, Ma: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1979), “Counterfactual Dependence and Tune's Arrow”, Nous 13: 455-476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mellor, D. (1981), Real Time. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Papineau, D. (1985), “Causal Asymmetry”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36: 273-289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, H. (1992), “Agency and Causal Asymmetry”, Mind 101: 501-520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Redhead, M. (1987), Incompleteness, Non-Locality and Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. (1989), “Nonfactorizability, Stochastic Causality, and Passion-at-a-Distance”, in Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory, J. Cushing and E. McMullin (eds.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 145-153.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1956), The Direction of Time. Berkeley: University ofCalifornia Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1988), “The Principle of the Common Cause” in Probability and Causality: Essays in Honour of Wesley Salmon J. Fetzer (ed.). Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 211-228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spirtes, P., Glymour, G. and Scheines, R. (1992), Causation, Prediction and Search. Typescript, Department of Philosophy, Carnegie Mellon University.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spirtes, P., Glymour, G. and Scheines, R. (1992), Causation, Prediction and Search. Typescript, Department of Philosophy, Carnegie Mellon University.CrossRefGoogle Scholar