Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T16:27:50.367Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reply to Giere

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

In his “A New Program for Philosophy of Science?”, Ronald Giere expresses qualms regarding the critical and political projects I advocate for philosophy of science—that the critical project assumes an underdetermination absent from actual science, and the political project takes us outside the professional pursuit of philosophy of science. In reply I contend that the underdetermination the critical project assumes does occur in actual science, and I provide a variety of examples to support this. And I contend that the political project requires no more than what other academic fields even in science studies are already providing.

Type
Reply
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Cross, Rod (1982), “The Duhem-Quine Thesis, Lakatos and the Appraisal of Theories in Macroeconomics”, The Duhem-Quine Thesis, Lakatos and the Appraisal of Theories in Macroeconomics 92:320340.Google Scholar
Cushing, James T. (1994), Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Dranginis, Anne M. (2002), “Why the Hormone Study Finally Happened”, Why the Hormone Study Finally Happened 151: A21 [July 15].Google Scholar
Glymour, Clark (1997), “Social Statistics and Genuine Inquiry: Reflections on The Bell Curve”, in Devlin, Bernie, Fienberg, Stephen E., Resnick, Daniel P., and Roeder, Kathryn (eds.), Intelligence, Genes, and Success: Scientists Respond to the Bell Curve. New York: Springer-Verlag, 257280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, Clark (1998), “What Went Wrong? Reflections on Science by Observation and The Bell Curve”, What Went Wrong? Reflections on Science by Observation and The Bell Curve 65:132.Google Scholar
Hands, D. Wade (2001), Reflection without Rules: Economic Methodology and Contemporary Science Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heilbron, John L. (1987), “Applied History of Science”, Applied History of Science 78:552563.Google Scholar
Kolata, Gina, and Petersen, Melody (2002), “Hormone Replacement Study: A Shock to the Medical System”, Hormone Replacement Study: A Shock to the Medical System 151: A1, A16 [July 10].Google Scholar
Kukla, André (1998), Studies in Scientific Realism. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry, and Leplin, Jarrett (1991), “Empirical Equivalence and Underdetermination”, Empirical Equivalence and Underdetermination 88:449472.Google Scholar
Longino, Helen (1990), Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Love, Susan M., and Lindsey, Karen (1998), Dr. Susan Love’s Hormone Book. New York and Toronto: Random House.Google Scholar
National Women’s Health Network (2000), Taking Hormones and Women’s Health: Choices, Risks and Benefits, 5th ed. Washington, DC: National Women’s Health Network.Google Scholar
National Women’s Health Network (2002), The Truth about Hormone Replacement Therapy: How to Break Free from the Medical Myths of Menopause. Westminster, MD: Prima Publishing.Google Scholar
Smith, Vernon (1989), “Theory, Experiment, and Economics”, Theory, Experiment, and Economics 3:151169.Google Scholar
Wylie, Alison (1985), “The Reaction against Analogy”, in Schiffer, Michael B. (ed.), Advances in Archaeological Method and Theory, Vol. 8. New York: Academic Press, 63111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, Alison (1988), “‘Simple’ Analogy and the Role of Relevance Assumptions: Implications of Archaeological Practice”, ‘Simple’ Analogy and the Role of Relevance Assumptions: Implications of Archaeological Practice 2:134150.Google Scholar