Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-68ccn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T18:11:59.187Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Prospects for Naturalizing Color

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Paul Churchland has recently offered a novel argument for the “objective reality” of color. The strategy he employs to make this argument is an instance of a more general research program for interpreting perceptual content, “domain-portrayal semantics.” In the first half of the article, I point out some features of color vision that complicate Churchland's conclusion, in particular, the context-sensitive and inferential nature of color perception. In the second half, I examine and defend the general research program, concluding it is naturalistic in a minimal sense and should be of interest to naturalists and nonnaturalists alike.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Churchland, Paul (2005), “Chimerical Colors: Some Phenomenological Predictions from Cognitive Neuroscience”, Chimerical Colors: Some Phenomenological Predictions from Cognitive Neuroscience 18 (5): 527560..Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul (2007), “On the Reality (and Diversity) of Objective Colors: How Color-Qualia Space Is a Map of Reflectance-Profile Space”, On the Reality (and Diversity) of Objective Colors: How Color-Qualia Space Is a Map of Reflectance-Profile Space 74:119149.Google Scholar
Derrington, A. M., Krauskopf, J., and Lennie, P. (1984), “Chromatic Mechanisms in Lateral Geniculate Nucleus of Macaque”, Chromatic Mechanisms in Lateral Geniculate Nucleus of Macaque 357:241265.Google ScholarPubMed
Gärdenfors, Peter (2000), Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helmholtz, Hermann ([1910] 1925), Treatise on Physiological Optics, Vol. 3, The Perceptions of Vision. 3rd ed. Translated by James P. C. Southall. Originally published as Handbuch der Physiologischen Optik (Hamburg: Verlag von Leopold Voss). Menasha, WI: Optical Society of America.Google Scholar
Hurvich, Leo M. (1981), Color Vision. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar
Jameson, D., and Hurvich, L. M. (1959), “Perceived Color and Its Dependence on Focal, Surrounding, and Preceding Stimulus Variables”, Perceived Color and Its Dependence on Focal, Surrounding, and Preceding Stimulus Variables 49 (9): 890898..Google ScholarPubMed
Suppes, Patrick (2002), Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures. Stanford, CA: CSLI.Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, Krantz, David H., Luce, R. Duncan, and Tversky, Amos ([1989] 2007), Foundations of Measurement, Vol. 2, Geometrical, Threshold, and Probabilistic Representations. Reprint. (San Diego, CA: Academic Press). Mineola, NY: Dover.Google Scholar
Wagner, Steven J., and Warner, Richard (1993), “Introduction”, in Wagner, Steven J. and Warner, Richard (eds.), Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Wandell, Brian A. (1995), Foundations of Vision. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar