Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-wxhwt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T04:30:27.987Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Languages of Thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Lawrence J. Kaye*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy University of Massachusetts at Boston

Abstract

I critically explore various forms of the language of thought (LOT) hypothesis. Many considerations, including the complexity of representational content and the systematicity of language understanding, support the view that some, but not all, of our mental representations occur in a language. I examine several arguments concerning sententialism and the prepositional attitudes, Fodor's arguments concerning infant and animal thought, and Fodor's argument for radical concept nativism and show that none of these considerations require us to postulate a LOT that is innate or otherwise distinct from spoken languages. Instead, I suggest that we maintain the more conservative hypothesis, supported by introspection, that some of our thoughts occur in the languages that we speak.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Many thanks to Nancy Daukas for her helpful comments on the manuscript. Thanks also to Nelson Lande, Bob Rosenfeld and Bob Stalnaker for useful discussion of the issues.

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Massachusetts at Boston, 100 Morrissey Blvd., Boston, MA 02125-3393, USA.

References

Church, A. (1950), “On Carnap's Analysis of Statements of Assertion and Belief”, Analysis 10: 9799.10.1093/analys/10.5.97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. (1989), Meaning and Mental Representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1978), Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Finke, R. A. (1989), Principles of Mental Imagery. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975), The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1981), Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/5684.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1990), A Theory of Content and Other Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. and Pylyshyn, Z. (1988), “Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis”, Cognition 28: 371.10.1016/0010-0277(88)90031-5CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kaye, L. J. (1993), “Are Most of Our Concepts Innate?”, Synthese 95: 187217.10.1007/BF01064588CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kosslyn, S. M. (1980), Image and Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1981), “The Imagery Debate: Analogue Media versus Tacit Knowledge”, Philosophical Review 88: 1645.Google Scholar
Richard, M. (1990), Propositional Attitudes: An Essay on Thoughts and How We Ascribe Them. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511625282CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seymour, M. (1992), “A Sententialist Theory of Propositional Attitudes”, Journal of Philosophy 89: 181201.10.2307/2026640CrossRefGoogle Scholar