Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-tn8tq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T04:59:14.869Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Degree of Factual Support

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

John G. Kemeny
Affiliation:
Princeton, New Jersey
Paul Oppenheim
Affiliation:
Princeton, New Jersey

Extract

We wish to give a precise formulation of the intuitive concept: The degree to which the known facts (the evidence) support a given hypothesis.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1952, The Williams & Wilkins Company

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

In the main the contribution of Paul Oppenheim was limited to propounding some of the fundamental ideas.

References

2 Russell, Bertrand, Human Knowledge, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1948.

3 Carnap, Rudolf, Logical Foundations of Probability, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1950.

4 Helmer, Olaf and Oppenheim, Paul. “A Syntactical Definition of Probability and of Degree of Confirmation,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, X, 1945, pp. 25–60.

5 This condition will be somewhat restricted later, see Part 2.

6 ‘⊢W’ expresses that W is a theorem, i.e., that it is an analytic consequence of our dependency-postulates, or simply analytic if there are no dependencies.

7 This CA serves to illustrate the relation between F and C. We see that F does not satisfy one of the fundamental C-principles, namely that if H 1 follows from H 2, then its C is at least as great as that of H 2 with respect to any evidence. Consider the historical example: H 1 is the bending of light-rays in a gravitational field, while H 2 is the General Theory of Relativity, and the evidence is the evidence before 1919. Certainly F(H 2, E) is much greater than F(H 1, E) since H 1 was not supported by any observation up to that time. Yet if we assigned say 80% credibility to H 2, we would have to assign at least that much to any of its consequences. Here is a case where H 1 has a high credibility (C) in spite of a very low degree of factual support (F)! The reasoning must be as follows: On the basis of its F-value and other considerations, simplicity of the hypothesis being the most important in this case, we assign by induction a high C-value to H 2, and consequently H 1 must get a C-value at least as high.

8 Church, Alonzo, Introduction to Mathematical LogicPart I, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1944, p. 91.

9 A theorem due to Gödel, ibid., pp. 73ff.

10 Theorems 9 and 10 hold, of course, only if the variables remain within the bounds specified in theorem 5.

11 A function is homogeneous to degree k if multiplying its arguments by c multiplies the value by ck.

12 In order to avoid quotation marks, we will use w.f.f. as names for themselves.