Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qlrfm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T08:17:22.606Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Causal Efficacy of Space

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Dudley Shapere*
Affiliation:
The University of Chicago

Abstract

Through an analysis of conditions under which the question of spatial anisotropy can be raised, the present paper brings out intimate conceptual relationships between the scientific concept of space and the concepts of entities, behavior, and explanation specified by scientific theories. Thus scientific departures from ordinary usage (or from usage in other scientific theories) of the term “space” entail corresponding shifts in the use of other terms not generally seen to be connected. As a case study of the relations between these terms, and of the refusal to allow the possibility of spatial anisotropy, Newtonian mechanics is examined.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association 1964

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Bondi, H., Cosmology, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1960.Google Scholar
[2] Clagett, M., The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press, 1959.Google Scholar
[3] Dicke, R. H., “The Many Faces of Mach,” in Chiu, H. and Hoffmann (eds.), Gravitation and Relativity, New York, Benjamin, 1964.Google Scholar
[4] Einstein, A., Essays in Science, New York, Philosophical Library, 1934.Google Scholar
[5] Einstein, A., The Meaning of Relativity, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1946.Google Scholar
[6] Grosser, M., The Discovery of Neptune, Cambridge, Harvard, 1962.Google Scholar
[7] Hall, A. R., and Hall, (eds.), Unpublished Scientific Papers of Isaac Newton, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1962.Google Scholar
[8] Heckmann, O., “General Review of Cosmological Theories,” in McVittie, G. C. (ed.), Problems of Extra-Galactic Research, New York, Macmillan, 1962.Google Scholar
[9] Hempel, C., “Deductive-Nomological vs. Statistical Explanation,” in Feigl, H. and Maxwell, (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. III, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press, 1962.Google Scholar
[10] Hesse, M., Forces and Fields, London, Nelson, 1961.Google Scholar
[11] Jammer, M., Concepts of Space, Cambridge, Harvard, 1954.Google Scholar
[12] McVittie, G. C., Fact and Theory in Cosmology, New York, Macmillan, 1961.Google Scholar
[13] Newton, I., Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy and His System of the World, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1947.Google Scholar
[14] Newton, I., Opticks, New York, Dover, 1952.Google Scholar
[15] Shapere, D., “Space, Time, and Language,” in Baumrin, B. (ed.), Philosophy of Science: The Delaware Seminar, Vol. II, New York, Wiley, 1963.Google Scholar
[16] Tolman, R., Relativity, Thermodynamics, and Cosmology, Oxford, Clarendon, 1958.Google Scholar
[17] Whitrow, G., The Structure and Evolution of the Universe, London, Hutchinson, 1959.Google Scholar