Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-vpsfw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T11:29:09.507Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Literal versus Careful Interpretations of Scientific Theories: The Vacuum Approach to the Problem of Motion in General Relativity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

The problem of motion in general relativity is about how exactly the gravitational field equations, the Einstein equations, are related to the equations of motion of material bodies subject to gravitational fields. This article compares two approaches to derive the geodesic motion of (test) matter from the field equations: the ‘T approach’ and the ‘vacuum approach’. The latter approach has been dismissed by philosophers of physics because it apparently represents material bodies by singularities. I argue that a careful interpretation of the approach shows that it does not depend on introducing singularities at all and that it holds at least as much promise as the T approach.

Type
Physical Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank my colleagues at Caltech and at the Einstein Papers Project for many discussions about the problem of motion and the Einstein-Grommer approach in particular. Thanks are due especially to Diana Kormos-Buchwald, Frederick Eberhardt, and Daniel Kennefick. I would also like to thank audiences at Caltech, Oxford, Irvine, the BSPS 2016 conference in Cardiff, at the 8th Quadrennial Pittsburgh Fellows conference in Lund, Sweden, and of course at the PSA 2016 for many helpful discussions on the topic. I would like to thank especially Sam Fletcher, David Malament, and Jim Weatherall for carefully reading earlier versions of this article and for the extremely helpful comments they gave me. Finally, I would like to thank Dana Tulodziecki for pointing my attention to the link between posit realism and what I was saying in this article.

References

Abbott, B., Abbott, R., Abbott, T., Abernathy, M., Acernese, F., Ackley, K., Adams, C., Adams, T., Addesso, P., Adhikari, R., et al. 2016. “Observation of Gravitational Waves from a Binary Black Hole Merger.” Physical Review Letters 116 (6): 061102.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bonnor, W. 1992. “Physical Interpretation of Vacuum Solutions of Einstein’s Equations.” Pt. 1, “Time-Independent Solutions.” General Relativity and Gravitation 24 (5): 551–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, H. R. 2007. Physical Relativity: Space-Time Structure from a Dynamical Perspective. Rev. ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Curiel, E. 2017. “A Primer on Energy Conditions.” In Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories, ed. Lehmkuhl, D., Schiemann, G., and Scholz, E. Einstein Studies 13. Boston: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar
Earman, J. 1995. Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks: Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J., and Janssen, M. 1993. “Einstein’s Explanation of the Motion of Mercury’s Perihelion.” In The Attraction of Gravitation: New Studies in the History of General Relativity, ed. Earman, J., Janssen, M., and Norton, J. D., 129–72. Einstein Studies 5. Boston: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar
Ehlers, J., and Geroch, R. 2004. “Equation of Motion of Small Bodies in Relativity.” Annals of Physics 309:232–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Einstein, A. 1915. Erklärung der perihelbewegung des merkur aus der allgemeinen relativitätstheorie. Berlin: Akademie der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
Einstein, A. 1922. Vier Vorlesungen über Relativitätstheorie: Gehalten im Mai 1921 an der Universität Princeton. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
Einstein, A. 1934. “On the Method of Theoretical Physics.” Philosophy of Science 1 (2): 163–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Einstein, A. 1936. “Physics and Reality.” Journal of the Franklin Institute 221:349–82.Google Scholar
Einstein, A., and Grommer, J. 1927. “Allgemeine Relativitätstheorie und Bewegungsgesetz.” Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-Mathematische Klasse, 1927, 213. Repr. as Vol. 15, doc. 443 in Collected Papers of Albert Einstein.Google Scholar
Eisenstaedt, J. 1989. “The Early Interpretation of the Schwarzschild Solution.” In Einstein and the History of General Relativity, ed. Howard, D. and Stachel, J. J., 213–33. Boston: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar
Geroch, R., and Jang, P. 1975. “Motion of a Body in General Relativity.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 16:6567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Havas, P. 1989. “The Early History of the ‘Problem of Motion’ in General Relativity.” In Einstein and the History of General Relativity, ed. Howard, D. and Stachel, J. J., 234–76. Boston: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar
Kennefick, D. 2005. “Einstein and the Problem of Motion: A Small Clue.” In The Universe of General Relativity, ed. Kox, A. J. and Eisenstaedt, J., 109–24. Boston: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar
Lehmkuhl, D. 2014. “Why Einstein Did Not Believe That General Relativity Geometrizes Gravity.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science B 46:316–26.Google Scholar
Malament, D. B. 2012. “A Remark about the ‘Geodesic Principle’ in General Relativity.” In Analysis and Interpretation in the Exact Sciences, ed. Frappier, M., Brown, D. H., and DiSalle, R., 245–52. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Pickering, A. 1999. Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Saunders, S., Barrett, J., Kent, A., and Wallace, D. 2010. Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory, and Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tamir, M. 2012. “Proving the Principle: Taking Geodesic Dynamics Too Seriously in Einstein’s Theory.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 43 (2): 137–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Torretti, R. 1996. Relativity and Geometry. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
van Dongen, J. 2010. Einstein’s Unification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vickers, P. 2013. “A Confrontation of Convergent Realism.” Philosophy of Science 80 (2): 189211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weatherall, J. O. 2011. “On the Status of the Geodesic Principle in Newtonian and Relativistic Physics.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science B 42 (4): 276–81.Google Scholar
Weatherall, J. O. 2017. “Inertial Motion, Explanation, and the Foundations of Classical Spacetime Theories.” In Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories, ed. Lehmkuhl, D., Schiemann, G., and Scholz, E. Einstein Studies 13. Boston: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar