Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qs9v7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T12:27:47.491Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fables and Symbols—I

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 July 2024

Extract

Whatever future judgments may be on our contemporary Western culture and education, we cannot be accused of denying a major, even a predominating role, to the life of the artistic imagination (though when one turns from stated aim to present practice, in primary schools and elsewhere, the position may be less satisfactory). In the last forty years philistinism has quietly died after a few rearguard actions and many whimpers; the ultimate success of the opponents of censorship in the cases over Lady Chatterley and Last Exit to Brooklyn was due in the first place to this triumphant antiphilistinism and only secondly to a climate of increasing moral permissiveness: the argument that carried the day with people of all shades of ethical opinion was that the artist could get away with it.

The high claims made for poetry and the imagination by the Romantics and their successors have led us into a position where poets and novelists have been studied in a manner formerly thought suitable for moral teachers. Arnold’s plea for a poetry of the emotions which would provide a substitute for religion was a landmark along the way. Arnold declared that ‘the strongest part of our religion today is its unconscious poetry’: the increase in the authority granted to the insights of the artist has often advanced in a ratio with the declining authority of dogmatic belief.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1969 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This article is based on a paper originally given as one of the Blackfriars-Pusey Lectures at Oxford in the Michaelmas term, 1968, and since considerably revised.

References

page 233 note 2 ‘On the Study of Poetry’, in Essays in Criticism, Second Series (1888).

page 233 note 3 R. J. White ed., Political Tracts of Wordsworth, Coleridge and Southey, ‘The Statesman's Manual’, pp. 24–5.

page 234 note 1 Edwyn Bevan, Symbolism and Belief, pp. 151–205; C. S. Lewis, The Allegory of Love, pp. 44–111.

page 234 note 2 Northrop Frye, Anatomy of Criticism (1957).

page 236 note 1 Lewis, Cecil Day, The Poetic Image (Clark Lectures, 1947)Google Scholar, perhaps because it is a not very original though attractive treatment, may be mentioned as a typical statement of the contemporary tendency to give central importance to the symbolic image.

page 237 note 1 Sidney, , A Defence of Poetry, ed, Dorsten, J. A. Van (Oxford, 1966), p. 40Google Scholar.

page 238 note 1 Hume, Treatise on Human Nature, I.i.I.

page 238 note 2 Sartre, , L'Imaginaire (Paris, 1940), p. 127Google Scholar. I am indebted in this paragraph both to what Sartre says on the role of intentionality and to the comments on L'Imaginaire by Anthony Manser in his Sartre: a Philosophic Study (1966), pp. 20–38.

page 238 note 3 L'Imaginaire, p. 236.