Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-m9kch Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-05-28T20:49:14.928Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Casaubon's ghosts: the haunting of legal scholarship

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Allan C Hutchinson*
Affiliation:
Osgoode Hall Law School, York University, Toronto

Abstract

Much academic work continues to operate within the cramping and pervasive spirit of a black-letter mentality that encourages scholars and jurists to maintain legal study as an inward-looking and self-contained discipline. There is still a marked tendency to treat law as somehow a world of its own that is separate from the society within which it operates and purports to serve. This is a disheartening and disabling state of affairs. Accordingly, this article will offer both a critique of the present situation and suggest an alternative way of proceeding. The writer recommends a shift from philosophy to democracy so that legal academics will be less obsessed with abstraction and formalism and more concerned with relevance and practicality. In contrast to the hubristic and occasionally mystical aspirations of mainstream scholars, it presents a more humble depiction of the worth and efficacy of the jurisprudential and scholarly project in which ‘usefulness’ is given pride of place. Of course, these fundamental charges are not applicable to all legal scholars. Many scholars are engaged in work that not only challenges the prevailing paradigm of legal scholarship, but also explores exciting new directions for legal study. It will be part of the essay to acknowledge those contributions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society of Legal Scholars 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Rorty, R Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought In Twentieth Century America (Cambridge, Mass: 1998). pp 91, 105Google Scholar.

2. George Eliot Middlemarch: A Study Of Provincial Life 26–27 (M Drabble (ed), 1985). Originally published in 1871 by Mary Ann Evans, it is described by Virginia Woolf as ‘one of the few English novels written for grown-up people’. Woolf, VGeorge Eliot’ in The Common Reader (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1925), pp 166–176 Google Scholar. Of course, the issue of what counts as a ‘great novel’ and what follows form that is a contested matter. Although I would defend the claims of Middlemarch for inclusion in a canon of English novels, I do not do so in any final, essential or objective manner. For a conventional assessment of Middlemarch's literary merits, see Leavis, F R The Great Tradition (London: Chatto & Windus, 1960)Google Scholar and, for a less conventional one, see Gilbert, S and Gubar, S The Madwoman In The Attic: The Woman Writer And The Nineteenth-Century Literary Imagination (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2nd edn, 2000)Google Scholar. There are several critiques of Eliot that challenge its merits and worth.

3. Id at 7, I9 and 184. Casaubon is also the hero of Umberto Eco's Foucault's Pendulum (W Weaver trans) (San Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanich, 1989) who is involved in the search for the One True Meaning of Things. For a postmodern reading of this novel, see Rorty, RThe Pragmatist's Progress’ in Interpretation And Overinterpretation Collini, S (ed) (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992)Google Scholar. Eco insists that his Casaubon is not named after Eliot's clergyman, but after the great philologist Isaac Casaubon. See U Eco ‘The Text and Author’ in ibid at pp 81–82.

4. Holmes, O W The Collected Legal Papers (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1920) p 202 Google Scholar.

5. Eliot, above n 2 p 13.

6. Garner, B (ed) A Dictionary Of Modern Legal Usage (New York: Oxford University Press, 2nd edn, 1995) pp 109–110 Google Scholar.

7. Blackstone's Commentaries 1, 2 and 11, 425 and IV, 435. See also Fisher v Prince (1762) 3 Burr 1363, per Lord Mansfield (‘the reason and spirit of cases make law, not the letter of particular precedents’); Jones v Randall (1774) Cowp 37, per Lord Mansfield (‘precedents serve to illustrate principles and to give them fixed certainty’); M Hale History Of The Common Law 67 (4th edn, 1739) (Though such decisions are less than a law, yet they are greater evidence thereof); and Allen, C K Law In The Making (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 6th edn, 1958) p 213 Google Scholar.

8. Smith, J and Hogan, B Criminal Law (London: Butterworths, 8th edn, 1996)Google ScholarPubMed. This is especially so on so-called unnatural offences (pp 492–497), although they note that while this term may be ‘offensive, but it is in the heading of the Act’ (p 492, n 20). See also Bum, E H Cheshire and Bum's Modem Law of Real Property (London: Butterworths, 15th edn, 1994)Google Scholar (no account of what is idea of property or homelessness, but lots on estates and titles); Treitel, G Law of Contract (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 9th edn, 1995)Google Scholar; Beatson, J Anson's Law of Contract (London: Sweet, 27th edn, 1998)Google Scholar (account of contract as a single body of general principles); and Brazier, M and Murphy, J Street on Torts (London: Sweet, 10th edn, 1999)Google Scholar. There are a number of texts that offer a more contextual approach, but this is usually token and used to explain deviations as though the general principles simply just are. See Atiyah, P An Introduction to the Law of Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 5th edn, 1995)Google Scholar; Furmston, J Cheshire, Fifoot and Furmston on Law of Contract (London: Butterworths, 13th edn, 1996)Google Scholar; and Dias, R and Markesinis, B Tort Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2nd edn, 1995)Google Scholar.

9. P Birks ‘Adjudication and Interpretation in the Common Law: A Century of Change’ (1994) 14 LS 156 at 168 and 176. In a similar vein, see R Goff ‘In Search of Principle’ (1983) 69 Procs Brit Acad 169 and J Beatson ‘Has the Common Law a Future?’ (1997) 56 CLJ 291.

10. Hart, H L A The Concept Of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press, 2nd edn, 1994)Google Scholar. I say ‘too many qualms’ because Hart's work can be read as being much more subversive and unsettling than many jurists allow. See A Hutchinson ‘A Postmodern's Hart: Taking Rules Sceptically’ (1995) 58 MLR 788.

11. K Llewellyn Jurisprudence (1962) p 372.

12. Boyle, JThe Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought’ (1985) 133 UPALR 685 at 779Google Scholar. See generally R Tur ‘Jurisprudence and Practice’ (1976) 14 JSPTL 38 and ‘What is Jurisprudence?’ (1978) 28 Phil Q 149. This tendency towards arid conceptualism and abstract coherence is particularly marked in traditional jurisprudence textbooks and courses. See H Barnett ‘The Province of Jurisprudence Determined—Again!’ (1995) 15 LS 88.

13. Eliot, above n 2 p 19.

14. Omychund v Barker (1744) 26 ER 15 at 23 (emphasis added).

15. Weinrib, E The Idea Of Private Law (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1995) pp 3 and 13Google Scholar.

16. Dworkin, R A Matter of principle (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1985) p 146 Google Scholar.

17. Dworkin, R Law's Empire (London: Fontana, 1986) pp 407, 400 and 220Google Scholar. This kind of hubris is not uncommon in law or other fields and, indeed, explains some of its appeal. For instance, in his best-seller, Stephen Hawking states that his goal is ‘nothing less than a complete description of the universe we live in’: see Hawking, S A Brief History of Time (London; New York: Bantam Books, 1989) p 13 Google Scholar. He concludes the book with the opinion that the discovery of why the universe exists will be equivalent to knowing ‘the mind of God’ (p 175).

18. R Dworkin ‘In Praise of Theory’ (1997) 29 Ariz St LJ 353 at 356–357.

19. Above n 18 at 359.

20. Eliot, above n 2 p 19.

21. Eliot, above n 2 pp 12, 19, 23, 22. 17 and 765.

22. Eliot, above n 2 pp 28, 179, 250 and 255.

23. R Rorty Representation, Social Practice, and Truth’ in Objectivity, relativism and truth (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991) vol 1, p 154. See also Rorty, R Contingency, Irony, Solidarity (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989) pp 5–13 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For my own attempt to elaborate on this approach for jurisprudence, see Hutchinson, A It's All In The Game: A Non-Foundationalist Account Of Law And Adjudication (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24. Fernandez-Armesto, F Truth: A History And A Guide For The Perplexed (London; New York: Bantam Press, 1997) pp 216–220 Google Scholar. For a good introduction to these philosophical difficulties in jurisprudence, see Leiter ‘Objectivity And The Problems of Jurisprudence’ (1993) 72 Tex LR 187 and J Coleman and B Leiter ‘Determinacy, Objectivity and Authority’ (1993) 142 U Pa LR 549 at 600.

25. For a general account of coherence theories in moral and legal reasoning, see Hanen, MJustification as Coherence’ in Stewart, M A (ed) Law, Morality And Rights (Dordrecht, 1983) p 67 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Stick, JCan Nihilism Be Pragmatic?’ (1986) 100 Harv LR 332 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Rescher, N The Coherence Theory Of Truth (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973)Google Scholar; Wright, C Truth And Objectivity (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1992)Google Scholar; and Kress ‘Coherence’ in D Patterson (ed) A Companion To Philosophy Of Law And Legal Theory (Cambridge, Mass: Blackwell Publishers, 1996) pp 533–552.

26. For a defence of the view that truth is explained by resort to something that is beyond a particular practice and that there are moral facts which can be accessed in similar ways to other facts, see Moore, MThe Interpretative Turn in Modern Theory: a Turn for the Worse’ (1989) 41 Stan LR 871 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; ‘A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation’ (1985) 58 S Cal LR 277; and ‘Moral Reality Revisited’ (1992) 90 Mich LR 2424. D Brink ‘Legal Theory, Legal Interpretation and Judicial Review’ (1988) 17 Phil & Pub Affs 105. For examples of more axiomatic accounts, see Weinrib and Brudner, above n 15.

27. See Dworkin, above n 17 at 218–219 and generally 213–228. Dworkin explicitly resists categorisation as a pragmatists if that means sharing views with Rorty and other ‘new pragmatists’, whose views he describes as comprising ‘a dog's dinner’ . See ‘Pragmatism, Rights Answers and True Banality’ in Brint, M and Weaver, W (eds) Pragmatism In Law And Society (Boulder: Westview Press, 1991) pp 359 at 360Google Scholar and generally 366–369. Dworkin has never abandoned the one-right-answer thesis, although he has modified it. As he states, ‘for better or for worse, I have not [changed my mind about the character and importance of the one-right-answer thesis]’: Ibid at p 382, n 1. See also Dworkin, R Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1978) chs 4 and 13Google ScholarPubMed; Dworkin, above n 16 at ch 5; and Dworkin, above n 17 at ch 7.

28. Rorty, R Philosophy And The Mirror Of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979) p 209 Google Scholar. See also R Rorty ‘Texts and Lumps’ in Philosophical Papers (1991) vol 1, 81; Rorty, R Objectivity, Realism And Truth (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991) pp 2224 Google Scholar; Putnam, H Representation And Reality (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1988) p 115 Google Scholar and Quine, WTwo Dogmas of Empiricism’ in From A Logical Point Of View (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1953) pp 20–46 Google Scholar.

29. See Fish, S The Trouble With Principle (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1999)Google Scholar.

30. See Hutchinson, AIn Praise of Leading Cases’ in O'Dell, E (ed) Leading Cases Of The Twentieth Century (Dublin: Roundhall, 2000)Google Scholar.

31. Dworkin, RObjectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It’ (1996) 25 Phil & Public Affs 87 at 133CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32. Above n 31 at 133–134.

33. See Twining, W Blackstone's Tower: The English Law School (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1994) pp 130–132 Google Scholar and generally Kennedy ‘The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries’ (1979) 28 Buff LR 205.

34. Schlag, P The Enchantment Of Reason (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1998) p 99 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

35. Posner, R The Problematics Of Moral And Legal Theory (Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999) pp 133, 227 and 262Google Scholar. See also Sunstein, C Legal Reasoning And Political Conflict (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar and One Case At A Time: Judicial Minimalism On The Supreme Court (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1999). For once, I fully agree with Dworkin when he argues that Posner's claims about the political process are not descriptive or technical. but moral in the sense that they are not only judgments about how best to achieve stipulated goals, but rather highly controversial claims about the distribution and exercise of government powers and the limits imposed by respect for individual moral rights: ‘[Posner] calls for the death of moral theory, but, like all of philosophy's would-be undertakers, he only means the triumph of his own theory.’ R Dworkin ‘Darwin's New Bulldog’ (1998) 111 Harv LR 1718 at 1738–1739.

36. See DiSanto v Pennsylvania (1927) 273 US 34 at 43, per Brandeis J dissenting.

37. Thompson, E P Whigs And Hunters: The Origins Of The Black Act (London: Allen Lane, 1975) p 250 Google Scholar.

38. Dworkin, above n 18 at 375–376.

39. Eliot, above n 2 at 179.

40. Ibid at 44, 199, 436 and 766.

41. Dworkin, above n 31 at 92. See also Farber, D and Sherry, S Beyond All Reason: The Radical Assault On Truth In American Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997) pp 7, 22, 73, 119 and 133.Google Scholar

42. Rorty, Objectivity, above n 28 at 23–24.

43. Rorty, R Philosophy And Social Hope (New York: Penguin, 1999) pp xxxii and xxixGoogle Scholar.

44. Rorty, above n 1 at 28.

45. For a more elaborate defence of this position and some suggestions for its implementation, see Hutchinson, Game, above n 23 at 288–319 and Hutchinson, A Waiting For Coraf A Critique Of Law And Rights (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1995) pp 172–83Google Scholar. It might be claimed that this essay itself is long on formal exhortations, but short on substantive recommendations. I am sensitive to this charge and am presently writing a book along such lines, entitled Work-In-Progress: Theory, Law and Politics.

46. See Lacey, N and Wells, C Reconstructing Criminal Law (London: Butterworths, 2nd edn, 1998)Google Scholar.

47. Rorty, above n 43 at 87.

48. O W Holmes, Jr ‘The Profession of the Law (Conclusion of a Lecture Delivered to Undergraduates of Harvard University, February 17, 1886)’ in R A Posner (ed) The Essential Holmes: Selection From Letters, Speeches, Judicial Opinions, And Other Writing Of Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992) p 218.

49. I borrow the idea for this taxonomy from Roithmayr, although I organise it in a slightly different way. See D Roithmayr ‘Guerrillas in Our Midst: The Assault on Radicals in American Law’ (1998) 96 Mich LR 1658.

50. See Sunstein, C Legal Reasoning And Political Conflict (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996)Google Scholar and Posner, R The Problems Of Jurisprudence (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1990) and Overcoming Law (1995)Google Scholar.

51. Rorty, above n 1 at 35 and generally Anderson, C Pragmatic Liberalism (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1990)Google Scholar. For a representative jurisprudential rendition of liberal pragmatism, see Farber and Sherry, above n 41.

52. See Kennedy, D A Critique Of Adjudication Fin De Siecle (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1998)Google Scholar.

53. Rorty Contingency above n 23 at 60. As for Rorty himself, there seems to be something of shift taking place in his thinking. He used to argue that consensus about conflicting vocabularies is generated through a ‘free and open encounter’ undistorted by power. However, in his more recent work, while he still occasionally talks about ‘inter-subjective consensus’ as a purely ethical ideal, he seems more willing to follow the more radical intimations of his pragmatic critique. For instance, he talks much more about public measures required to achieve ‘a classless and casteless society’: the exclusive concern with private efforts at transformation has been replaced with a much more encompassing account of political action as a public responsibility. See Rorty, above nn 1 and 28.

54. Kennedy, DA Cultural Pluralist Case for Affirmative Action in Legal Academia’ (1990) Duke LJ 705 at 733CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

55. Nietzsche, F The Gay Science (W Kaufmann trans) (New York: Random House, 1974) s 108.Google Scholar

56. Rushdie, S Shame (London: Jonathan Cape, 1995) p 116 Google Scholar.