Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-9q27g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-21T16:54:03.989Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Purposive vagueness: an evaluative dimension of vague quantifying expressions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 November 2008

Mava Jo Powell
Affiliation:
The University of British Columbia

Extract

Extending Montague's (1974) framework, Barwise and Cooper (1981) argue that some generalized expressions (which I shall call vague quantifying expressions), such as most, many ana few, correspond not to quantifiers, but to determiners within noun phrases. They argue that we need not determine the meanings of these expressions by logic; rather, we may draw upon an idea similar to the one we employ when interpreting the meaning of the quantifier Qxø(x), that is, we may appeal to an underlying topology for their interpretation (1981: 161). Similarly, they invoke one of the ‘simplifying assumptions often made in model theory’; namely, … that one has a fixed context which determines the meaning of the basic expressions. We can think of this context as providing an interpretation for non-logical determiners… We shall assume… that there is a rich context held fixed that determines the PRECISE MEANING [my emphasis here] for the basic expressions, even those like ‘most’, ‘many’ and ‘few’. We refer to this as the fixed context assumption

The fixed context assumption is our way of finessing the vagueness of non-logical determiners. We think that a theory of vagueness like that given by Kamp (1975) for other kinds of basic expressions could be superimposed on our theory (1981: 163).

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Barwise, J. & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. LaPh 4. 159219.Google Scholar
Black, M. (1949). Language and philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Dowty, D. (1979). Word meaning and Montague grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dowty, D., Wall, R. & Peters, S. (1981). Introduction to Montague semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Grice, H. (1975). Logic and conversation. In Cole, P. & Morgan, J. (eds.), Syntax and semantics, vol. 3: Speech acts. New York: Academic Press. 4158.Google Scholar
Hall-Partee, B. (1979). Montague grammar, mental representations, and reality. In Öhmann, S. & Kanger, S. (eds.), Philosophy and grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel. 195208.Google Scholar
Kamp, J. (1975). Two theories about adjectives. In Keenan, E. (ed.) Formal semantics of natural languages. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 123155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kempson, R. (1977). Semantic theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (1975). Hedges: a study in meaning criteria and the logic of fuzzy concepts. In Hockney, D., Harper, W. & Freed, B. (eds.), Contemporary research in philosophical logic and linguistic semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel. 221271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, J. (1977). Semantics, vols. 1 & 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. (1981). Language, meaning and context. London: Fontana/Collins.Google Scholar
Lyons, J. (1982). Deixis and subjectivity: loquor, ergo sum? In Jarvella, R. & Klein, W. (eds.), Speech, place and action. New York: Wiley. 101124.Google Scholar
McCawley, J. (1980). Everything that linguists have always wanted to know about logic* but were ashamed to ask. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Montague, R. (1974). Formal philosophy. (Thomason, R. (ed.)). New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Powell, M. (1983). The notion of literal meaning in contemporary linguistic semantics. D.Phil. dissertation, University of Sussex.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language and reality, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadock, J. (1977). Truth and approximations. Proc. Third Annual Meeting Berkeley Linguistics Soc. 3. 430439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sampson, G. (1979). The indivisibility of words. JL 15. 3947.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar