Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T01:55:23.927Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justice, Fairness, and Membership in a Class: Conceptual Confusions and Moral Puzzles in the Regulation of Human Subjects Research

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Extract

Much of the human research conducted in the United States or by U.S. researchers is regulated by the Common Rule. The Common Rule reflects the decision of 17 federal agencies, including the Department of Health and Human Services (whose regulations appear at 45CFR46), to require that investigators follow the same rules for conducting human research. (The Food and Drug Administration [FDA] has its own rules (at 21CFR50 and 21CFR56), though there is significant overlap with the Common Rule.) Many of the obligations delineated in the Common Rule can be traced back to the work of the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research (hereafter the National Commission). The National Commission was appointed in 1974 as part of the National Research Act (P.L. 93-348) in response to revelations about serious abuses involving human subjects, most notably the Tuskegee/United States Public Health Service Syphilis Study.

Type
Independent
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

The 17 federal agencies are the following: Departments of Agriculture, Energy, Commerce, Housing and Urban Development, Justice, Defense, Education, Veterans Affairs, Health and Human Services, Transportation, and the National Aeronautics and Space Administration, Consumer Product Safety Commission, Agency for International Development, Environmental Protection Agency, National Science Foundation, Social Security Administration, and Central Intelligence Agency. “Federal Policy for the Protection of Human Subjects; Notices and Rules,” 56 Fed. Reg. 28002–28032 (June 18, 1991).Google Scholar
For further discussion of this study, see Jones, J., Bad Blood: The Tuskegee Syphilis Experiment (New York: The Free Press, 1981).Google Scholar
National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Research on the Fetus (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1975); National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Research Involving Prisoners (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1976); National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Research Involving Children (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1977); National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Research Involving Those Institutionalized as Mentally Infirm (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1978).Google Scholar
National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research, The Belmont Report (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1979).Google Scholar
Kopelman, L., “What Conditions Justify Risky Nontherapeutic or ‘No Benefit’ Pediatric Studies: A Sliding Scale Analysis,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 32, no. 4 (2004): 749758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See supra note 5, at 19.Google Scholar
See supra note 4 (1977), at 78.Google Scholar
Research involving greater than minimal risk and offering subjects no prospect of direct benefit may be approved only if: (a) The risk represents a minor increase over minimal risk; (b) The intervention or procedure presents experiences to subjects that are reasonably commensurate with those inherent in their actual or expected medical, dental, psychological, social, or educational situations; (c) The intervention or procedure is likely to yield generalizable knowledge about the subjects' disorder or condition which is of vital importance for the understanding or amelioration of the subjects' disorder or condition; and (d) Adequate provisions are made for soliciting assent of the children and permission of their parents or guardians, as set forth in §46.408. (45CFR46.406).Google Scholar
Ross, L. F., “Convening a 407 Panel for Research Not Otherwise Approvable: ‘Precursors to Diabetes in Japanese American Youth’ as a Case Study,” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 14, no. 2 (2004): 165186; Infectious Diseases Society of America, “Grinding to a Halt: The Effects of the Increasing Regulatory Burden on Research and Quality Improvement Efforts,” Clinical Infectious Disease 49, no. 3 (2009): 328–335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alternatively, IRBs may be interpreting the definition of “minimal risk” very broadly to avoid recommending review under 45CFR46.407. If this is the case, then children may be included in research that allegedly poses minimal risk when it does not.Google Scholar
For further discussion of risk, see Kopelman, L., “When Is the Risk Minimal Enough for Children to be Research Subjects?” in Children and Health Care: Moral and Social Issues, Kopelman, L. M. Moskop, J. C., eds. (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989): At 8999; Wendler, D. Emanuel, E., “What Is a ‘Minor’ Increase Over Minimal Risk?” Journal of Pediatrics 47 (2005): 575–578; Weijer, C., “The Ethical Analysis of Risk,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 28, no. 4 (2000): 344–361; Wendler, D. Belsky, L. Thompson, K. Emanuel, E., “Quantifying the Federal Minimal Risk Standard: Implications for Pediatric Research without a Prospect of Direct Benefit,” JAMA 294 (2005): 826–832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
For further discussion of benefit in research, see Churchill, L. R. Nelson, D. K. Henderson, G. E. King, N. M. P. Davis, A. M. Leahey, E. Wilfond, B. S., “Assessing Benefits in Clinical Research: Why Diversity in Benefit Assessment Can Be Risky,” IRB: Ethics & Human Research 25, no. 3 (2003): 1–8. N. M. P. King, “Defining and Describing Benefit Appropriately in Clinical Trials,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 28 no. 4 (2000): 332–343; King, N. M. P. Henderson, G. E. Churchill, L. R. Davis, A. M. Hull, S. C. Nelson, D. Parham-Vetter, P. C. Rothschild, B. B. Easter, M. Wilfond, B. S., “Consent Forms and the Therapeutic Misconception,” IRB: Ethics & Human Research 27, no. 1 (2005): 1–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
United Nations, Convention on the Rights of the Child, Ratified November 20, 1989.Google Scholar
Jonas, H., “Philosophical Reflections on Experimenting with Human Subjects,” Daedalus 98, no. 2 (1969): 219247, at 237.Google Scholar
Id., at 238.Google Scholar
Id., at 239–40.Google Scholar
Id., at 241.Google Scholar
Id., at 242.Google Scholar
Id., at 230.Google Scholar
Ramsey, P., The Patient as Person (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1970); Ramsey, P., “The Enforcement of Morals: Non-therapeutic Research on Children,” Hastings Center Report 6, no. 4 (1976): 21–30; Ramsey, P., “Children as Research Subjects: A Reply,” Hastings Center Report 7, no. 2 (1977): 40–41; McCormick, R. A., “Proxy Consent in the Experimentation Situation,” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 18, no. 1 (1974): 2–23; McCormick, R., “Experimentation in Children: Sharing Sociality,” Hastings Center Report 6, no. 6 (1976): 41–46.Google Scholar
There has been much discussion of and speculation regarding the relationship between the work of the National Commission and Beauchamp and Childress’ Principles of Biomedical Ethics (Beauchamp, T. Childress, J. F., Principles of Biomedical Ethics [New York: Oxford University Press, 1979, 1983, 1989, 1994, 2001, 2008]). Beauchamp has explained that he was working with Childress on their volume at the same time that he was working with the National Commission and that while the two projects influenced each other, the Principles did not grow out of the National Commission's work (Beauchamp, T., “The Origins and Evolution of the Belmont Report,” in Childress, J. F. Meslin, E. Shapiro, H., eds., Belmont Revisited: Ethical Principles for Research with Human Subject [Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2005]: 12–25).Google Scholar
Id. (Beauchamp), at 15.Google Scholar
Yesley, M., “Oral History of the Belmont Report and the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research: Interview with Michael Yesley, April 19, 2004,” Office of Human Research Protections, at 67, available at <http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/archive/bel*-montArchive.html#histArchive2> (last visited June 28, 2011).+(last+visited+June+28,+2011).>Google Scholar
Toulmin, S., “Oral History of the Belmont Report and the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research: Interview with Stephen Toulmin,” May 14, 2004, Office of Human Research Protections, at 9, available at <http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/archive/belmontArchive.html#histArchive2> (last visited June 28, 2011).+(last+visited+June+28,+2011).>Google Scholar
See supra note 4 (1977), at 146178.Google Scholar
It is important to note that I am using “class cures” as shorthand for allowing research that poses a minor increase over minimal risk and no prospect of direct benefit with the review and approval of a local IRB.Google Scholar
See supra note 4 (1977), at 127.Google Scholar
Id. According to the National Commission, “Minimal risk is the probability and magnitude of physical or psychological harm that is normally encountered in the daily lives, or in the routine medical or psychological examination, of healthy children” (see supra note 4 [1977], at xx). This definition was not incorporated into the Common Rule, Subpart D, which regulates pediatric research. According to the Common Rule, “Minimal risk means that the probability and magnitude of harm or discomfort anticipated in the research are not greater in and of themselves than those ordinarily encountered in daily life or during the performance of routine physical or psychological examinations or tests” (45 C.F.R. 46.102.i). For research involving prisoners, the Common Rule stipulates that “Minimal risk is the probability and magnitude of physical or psychological harm that is normally encountered in the daily lives, or in the routine medical, dental, or psychological examination of healthy persons” (45 C.F.R. 46.303.d). The indexing to healthy persons in the definition of minimal risk in research regarding prisoners but not children has been the subject of extensive discussion.Google Scholar
See supra note 4 (1977), at 127.Google Scholar
There is an additional requirement that appears in the report that serves as a further side-constraint on such research. When research that involves procedures or interventions “that are reasonably commensurate with those inherent in their actual or expected medical, psychological or social situations,” children who can assent may be better able “to make a knowledgeable decision about their participation in research, based on some familiarity with the intervention or procedure and its effects,” and requiring commensurability can “assure that participation in research will be closer to the ordinary experience of the subjects.” The Commission added a requirement that the research procedures be reasonably commensurate with their actual or expected situations and “the anticipated knowledge is of vital importance for understanding or amelioration of the subjects' disorder or condition” (see supra note 4 [1977], at 78). The commensurability requirement tells us that when research participation is more like the subjects' daily lives, children who can assent can make better decisions. The requirement that research experiences be commensurate with subjects' actual or expected situations raises several questions about the premise. It is unclear how a child might use anticipated future experiences to assent (or dissent). Moreover, are children who do not yet have a disorder or condition but are expected to develop it expected to undergo certain procedures so that they, too, qualify under the commensurability requirement? Insofar as the commensurability requirement helps potential subjects assent (or dissent), it may help prevent inappropriate inclusion, i.e., inclusion without proper permission. But inclusion in research posing a minor increase over minimal risk and no prospect of direct benefit is not limited to children who can assent, so the commensurability requirement does nothing to avoid their inappropriate inclusion. At best, commensurability appears to be a requirement because it might help some children some of the time to decide whether to give or withhold assent. Commensurability does not justify restricting participation only to children with the disorder or condition under investigation. Children with other disorders or conditions might have commensurable experiences such that they might meet the commensurability requirement. As long as those other children are scientifically appropriate subjects, it seems that children with other disorders or conditions might qualify for research participation in studies on other disorders or conditions. The National Commission implicitly refutes the possibility that commensurability might justify including children who do not have the disorder or condition under investigation by stating that commensurability should not be used to justify doing research but rather should be treated as an additional requirement that should be met when the other conditions are met. So it is not part of the argument for a class-based exception but rather an additional requirement that must be met when attempting to invoke the class-based exception. Class membership is necessary even though others might have commensurable experiences.Google Scholar
For a discussion of this point as it relates to global poverty, see Pogge, T., World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002).Google Scholar
We see discussions about the appropriateness of wanting to help people we think are “like us” in important ways rather than a more general desire or willingness to help people in need in debates about the permissibility of directed organ donation. See, for example, Ankeny, R., “The Moral Status of Preferences for Directed Donation: Who Should Decide Who Gets Transplantable Organs?” Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics 10 (2001): 387398; Hillhorst, M., “Directed Altruistic Living Organ Donation: Partial but Not Unfair,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (2005): 197–215; Spital, A., “Should People Who Donate a Kidney to a Stranger Be Permitted to Choose Their Recipients? Views of the United States Public,” Transplantation 76, no. 8 (2003): 1252–1256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wertheimer, A., Exploitation (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
If one wishes to reject this conclusion, one should be able to specify which premise is false. I would argue that if one rejects this argument, one also is likely to have to reject the class-based exception to the exclusion rule since class plays no essential role in justifying the exception. For example, it may be the case that parents in fact do not have the authority to expose children to a minor increase over minimal risk without the prospect of direct benefit. If that is the case, then one must reject the class-based exception to the exclusion rule.Google Scholar
We should note that the same justification used for children would not work for prisoners or the institutionalized as mentally infirm, despite the fact that the National Commission's Report on Research Involving the Institutionalized as Mentally Infirm specifically refers to the Report on Research Involving Children in addressing the exclusion rule and exceptions to it. Neither prisoners nor the institutionalized mentally ill have anyone in authority over them in quite the same way that parents are in authority over their children.Google Scholar