Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-v5vhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-17T01:12:46.617Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Expressive Dimension of Free Exercise

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 April 2024

David Golemboski*
Affiliation:
Associate Professor of Government and International Affairs, Augustana University, USA

Abstract

Expressivist theories of law focus not only on what legal arrangements do but also what they communicate. The expressivist view has gained special currency in the context of religious establishment. Even when governmental involvement with religion is not coercive or does not materially violate anyone’s rights, it may nevertheless be undesirable by virtue of expressing a preference for a certain religion or a privileged status for certain religious groups over others. The existing literature, however, lacks an equivalent expressivist analysis of the related but distinct domain of free exercise of religion. What is expressed when a religious individual or group is granted special relief from the legal requirements that would otherwise apply to them? I argue that just like religious establishments, religious exemptions not only implicate rights and material interests but also have important expressive dimensions that both help account for their value and impose limits on their desirability.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Epstein, Lee and Posner, Eric A., “The Roberts Court and the Transformation of Constitutional Protections for Religion: A Statistical Portrait,” Supreme Court Review 2021 (2021): 315–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 Rothschild, Zalman, “Free Exercise Partisanship,” Cornell Law Review 107, no. 4 (2022): 10671135 Google Scholar.

3 Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission, 138 S. Ct. 1719 (2018).

4 Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 140 S. Ct. 1104 (2021).

5 Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, 573 U.S. 682 (2014).

6 This dynamic is characteristic of many First Amendment claims more generally. Barclay, Stephanie H., “First Amendment Harms,’Indiana Law Journal 95, no. 2 (2020): 331–88Google Scholar.

7 See, for example, Anderson, Elizabeth S. and Pildes, Richard H., “Expressive Theories of Law: A General Restatement,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148, no. 5 (2000): 1503–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sunstein, Cass R., “On the Expressive Function of Law,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 144, no. 5 (1996): 2021–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 2021; Hellman, Deborah, “The Expressive Dimension of Equal Protection,” Minnesota Law Review 85, no. 1 (2000): 170 Google Scholar.

8 Pildes, Richard H., “Why Rights Are Not Trumps: Social Meanings, Expressive Harms, and Constitutionalism,” Journal of Legal Studies 27, no. 2 (1998): 725–63, at 760CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 County of Allegheny v. American Civil Liberties Union, 492 U.S. 573 (1989).

10 Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668 (1984).

11 See, for example, Adler, Matthew D., “Expressive Theories of Law: A Skeptical Overview,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148, no. 5 (2000): 13631501 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 Richard C. Schragger and Micah Schwartzman, “Establishment Clause Inversion in the Bladensburg Cross Case,” ACS Supreme Court Review 2018–19 (2019): 21–58, at 27; Kennedy v. Bremerton School District, 142 S. Ct. 2407 (2022).

13 McAdams, Richard H., The Expressive Powers of Law: Theories and Limits (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2017), 142 Google Scholar.

14 Sunstein, “On the Expressive Function of Law,” 2024.

15 Sunstein, 2044.

16 Anderson and Pildes, “Expressive Theories of Law,” 1525; see also Lessig, Lawrence, “The Regulation of Social Meaning,” University of Chicago Law Review 62, no. 3 (1995): 9431045 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

17 Lawrence Lessig offers some additional examples. Lessig, “The Regulation of Social Meaning,” 952–55.

18 See, for example, Koppelman, Andrew, “Endorsing the Endorsement Test,” Charleston Law Review 7, no. 4 (2013): 719–25Google Scholar; Koppelman, Andrew, Defending American Religious Neutrality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2013), 8796 Google Scholar; Abrams, Paula L., “The Reasonable Believer: Faith, Formalism, and Endorsement of Religion,” Lewis & Clark Law Review 14, no. 4 (2010): 1537–56Google Scholar; May, Simon Căbulea, “Democratic Legitimacy, Legal Expressivism, and Religious Establishment,” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15, no. 2 (2012): 219–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Lægaard, Sune, “What’s the Problem with Symbolic Religious Establishment?,” in Religion in Liberal Political Philosophy, ed. Laborde, Cécile and Bardon, Aurelia (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017), 118–31Google Scholar; Bardon, Aurélia, “Christmas, Crescents, and Crosses: When Is Symbolic Religious Establishment Permissible?,” American Journal of Political Science 66, no. 1 (2022): 255–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ahmed, Farrah, “What Establishment Expresses,” International Journal of Constitutional Law 20, no. 2 (2022): 818–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

19 Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 688 (1984).

20 Lynch, 465 U.S. at 701.

21 Chemerinsky, Erwin, “Why Justice Breyer Was Wrong in Van Orden v. Perry,” William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal 14, no. 1 (2005): 116, at 4Google Scholar.

22 Capitol Square Review and Advisory Board v. Pinette, 515 U.S. 753, 779 (1995).

23 County of Allegheny v. American Civil Liberties Union, 492 U.S. 573, 620, 631 (1989).

24 Capitol Square Review and Advisory Board, 515 U.S. at 779–80.

25 Hill, B. Jessie, “Anatomy of the Reasonable Observer,” Brooklyn Law Review 79, no. 4 (2014): 1407–53, at 1439Google Scholar.

26 Capitol Square Review and Advisory Board, 515 U.S. at 780.

27 See, for example, Oleske, James M., “Free Exercise (Dis)Honesty,” Wisconsin Law Review 2019, no. 4 (2019): 689744 Google Scholar.

28 For an illustration of one aspect of the dissensus, see McConnell, Michael W., “The Origins and Historical Understanding of Free Exercise of Religion,” Harvard Law Review 103, no. 7 (1990): 14091517 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hamburger, Philip A., “A Constitutional Right of Religious Exemption: An Historical Perspective,” George Washington Law Review 60, no. 4 (1992): 915–48Google Scholar.

29 Locke, John, “A Letter Concerning Toleration,” in John Locke: Political Writings, ed. Wootton, David (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2003), 390436 Google Scholar; Davis, James Calvin, ed., “The Bloody Tenent Yet More Bloody,” in On Religious Liberty: Selections from the Works of Roger Williams, by Roger Williams (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2008), 167226 Google Scholar; also see Nussbaum, Martha C., Liberty of Conscience: In Defense of America’s Tradition of Religious Equality (New York: Basic Books, 2008), 3471 Google Scholar.

30 See, for example, Horwitz, Paul, First Amendment Institutions (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2013), 174–93Google Scholar.

31 Brady, Kathleen A., The Distinctiveness of Religion in American Law: Rethinking Religion Clause Jurisprudence (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2015)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

32 Koppelman, Defending American Religious Neutrality, 26.

33 Wilson, Robin Fretwell, “The Calculus of Accommodation: Contraception, Abortion, Same-Sex Marriage, and Other Clashes between Religion and the State,” Boston College Law Review 53, no. 4 (2012): 14171514 Google Scholar, at 1431; also see Koppelman, Andrew, “Gay Rights, Religious Accommodations, and the Purposes of Antidiscrimination Law,” Southern California Law Review 88, no. 3 (2015): 619–59Google Scholar; Berg, Thomas C., “What Same-Sex-Marriage and Religious-Liberty Claims Have in Common,” Northwestern Journal of Law and Social Policy 5, no. 2 (2010): 206–35Google Scholar.

34 See Galston, William A., Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political Theory and Practice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Levy, Jacob T., Rationalism, Pluralism, and Freedom (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015)Google Scholar.

35 See their contributions to Corvino, John, Anderson, Ryan T., and Girgis, Sherif, Debating Religious Liberty and Discrimination (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017)Google Scholar.

36 Ryan T. Anderson and Sherif Girgis, “Against the New Puritanism: Empowering All, Encumbering None,” in Debating Religious Liberty and Discrimination 108–206, at 108.

37 Golemboski, David, Religious Pluralism and Political Stability: Obligations in Agreement (New York: Routledge, 2022), 119–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

38 Golemboski, Religious Pluralism and Political Stability, 139–42.

39 The specific phrase comes from Engel v. Vitale, 370 U.S. 421, 428 (1962).

40 Dunn v. Ray, 139 S. Ct. 661 (2019).

41 Murphy v. Collier, 139 S. Ct. 1475 (2019).

42 See, for example, Nina Totenberg, “Supreme Court Sees 2 Similar Death Penalty Questions Very Differently,” NPR, March 30, 2019, https://www.npr.org/2019/03/30/708238203/supreme-court-sees-2-similar-death-penalty-questions-very-differently.

43 Abrams, Meredith, “Empirical Analysis of Religious Freedom Restoration Act Cases in the Federal District Courts Since Hobby Lobby,” Columbia Human Rights Law Review Online 4, no. 1 (2019): 5588 Google Scholar.

44 Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 687 (1984).

45 Over three decades ago, Douglas Laycock wrote that “judges are more likely to respond sympathetically to religious claims that are familiar, easily understood, and unthreatening.” Laycock, Douglas, “The Remnants of Free Exercise,” Supreme Court Review 1990, no. 1 (1990): 168 CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 14. See also Su, Anna, “Judging Religious Sincerity,” Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 5 (2016): 2848 CrossRefGoogle Scholar. See, generally, Sullivan, Winnifred Fallers, The Impossibility of Religious Freedom (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007)Google Scholar.

46 As in, for example, Church of Lukumi Babalu Aye v. City of Hialeah, 508 U.S. 520 (1993).

47 Burwell v. Hobby Lobby Stores, 573 U.S. 682 (2014).

48 On complicity claims generally, see NeJaime, Douglas and Siegel, Reva B., “Conscience Wars: Complicity-Based Conscience Claims in Religion and Politics,” Yale Law Journal 124, no. 7 (2015): 2516–91Google Scholar.

49 Burwell, 573 U.S. at 760 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting).

50 Golemboski, David, “Judicial Evaluation of Religious Belief and the Accessibility Requirement in Public Reason,” Law and Philosophy 35, no. 5 (2016): 435–60CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 693 (1986); Lyng v. Northwest Indian Cemetery Protective Association, 485 U.S. 439 (1988).

52 Lyng, 485 U.S. at 449.

53 Su, Anna, “Varieties of Burden in Religious Accommodations,” Journal of Law and Religion 34, no. 1 (2019): 4263, at 53CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Many others have argued the general case that US courts have failed adequately to protect Native American religious liberty. See, for example, Barclay, Stephanie Hall and Steele, Michalyn, “Rethinking Protections for Indigenous Sacred Sites,” Harvard Law Review 134, no. 4 (2021): 1295–359Google Scholar; Carpenter, Kristen A., “Limiting Principles and Empowering Practices in American Indian Religious Freedoms,” Connecticut Law Review 45, no. 2 (2012): 387481 Google Scholar; and Beaman, Lori G., “Aboriginal Spirituality and the Legal Construction of Freedom of Religion,” Journal of Church and State 44, no. 1 (2002): 135–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

54 Leiter, Brian, Why Tolerate Religion? (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2013), 99 Google Scholar.

55 This claim is implicitly at odds with approaches that would distinguish between those exemptions that are burden-shifting and those that are not. See, for example, Leiter, Why Tolerate Religion? For reasons of space, however, I do not attempt a full defense here. On the topic, see McConnell, Michael W., “Why Protect Religious Freedom?,” Yale Law Journal 123, no. 3 (2013): 770810 Google Scholar; Tebbe, Nelson, Schwartzman, Micah, and Schragger, Richard, “When Do Religious Accommodations Burden Others?,” in The Conscience Wars, ed. Mancini, Susanna and Rosenfeld, Michel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018), 328–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56 Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 224–26 (1972).

57 Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977), 227 Google Scholar.

58 Employment Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990).

59 Oleske, “Free Exercise (Dis)Honesty,” 731.

60 Tebbe, Nelson, Schwartzman, Micah, and Schragger, Richard, “How Much May Religious Accommodations Burden Others?,” in Law, Religion, and Health in the United States, ed. Sepper, Elizabeth, Lynch, Holly Fernandez, and Cohen, I. Glenn (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017), 215–29CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Tebbe, Schwartzman, and Schragger, “When Do Religious Accommodations Burden Others?”; Schwartzman, Micah, Tebbe, Nelson, and Schragger, Richard, “The Costs of Conscience,” Kentucky Law Journal 106, no. 4 (2018): 781812 Google Scholar.

61 Epstein and Posner, “The Roberts Court and the Transformation of Constitutional Protections for Religion,” 315–16.

62 See, for example, Howard Gillman and Erwin Chemerinsky, “The Weaponization of the Free-Exercise Clause,” Atlantic, September 18, 2020.

63 Sunstein, “On the Expressive Function of Law,” 2044.

64 See, for example, Newman v. Piggie Park Enterprises, Inc., 390 U.S. 400 (1968); Bob Jones University v. United States, 461 U.S. 574 (1983).

65 Masterpiece Cakeshop v. Colorado Civil Rights Commission, 138 S. Ct. 1719 (2018); Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 140 S. Ct. 1104 (2021); 303 Creative LLC v. Elenis, 143 S. Ct. 2298 (2023).

66 See, for instance, the account given in Greenhouse, Linda, Justice on the Brink: The Death of Ruth Bader Ginsburg, the Rise of Amy Coney Barrett, and Twelve Months That Transformed the Supreme Court (New York: Random House, 2021)Google Scholar.

67 Masterpiece Cakeshop, 138 S. Ct. at 1728–29 (2018).

68 Barak-Corren, Netta, “Religious Exemptions Increase Discrimination toward Same-Sex Couples: Evidence from Masterpiece Cakeshop ,” Journal of Legal Studies 50, no. 1 (2021): 75110 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Barak-Corren, “Religious Exemptions Increase Discrimination toward Same-Sex Couples,” 105.

70 Roger Severino, “Why Unanimity Was So Important in the Fulton Case,” National Review, June 17, 2021, https://www.nationalreview.com/bench-memos/why-unanimity-was-so-important-in-the-fulton-case/.

71 Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137, 177 (1803).

72 Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S. 644, 741 (2015).

73 Brief of Amicus Curiae Sherif Girgis Supporting Petitioners at 17, Masterpiece Cakeshop, 138 S. Ct. 1719.

74 See, for example, Smith, Steven D., “Symbols, Perceptions, and Doctrinal Illusions: Establishment Neutrality and the ‘No Endorsement’ Test,” Michigan Law Review 86, no. 2 (1987): 286–95CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

75 Elaine Photography v. Willock, 309 P.3d 53 (N.M. 2013).

76 See McClain, Linda C., Who’s the Bigot? Learning from Conflicts over Marriage and Civil Rights Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2020), 181210 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Thomas, George, “Religious Liberty, Same-Sex Marriage and Public Accommodations,” Perspectives on Politics 16, no. 1 (2018): 5872 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

77 West Virginia Board of Education v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 624 (1943).

78 Elaine Photography, 309 P.3d at 78.

79 Elaine Photography, 309 P.3d at 79.

80 McClain, Who’s the Bigot?, 190.

81 Brownstein, Alan Edward and Amar, Vikram D., “Locating Free-Exercise Most-Favored-Nation-Status (MFN) Reasoning in Constitutional Context,” Loyola University Chicago Law Journal 54, no. 2 (2023): 777820 Google Scholar.

82 Fulton v. City of Philadelphia, 140 S. Ct. 1104 (2021); Trinity Lutheran Church v. Comer, 582 U.S. 449 (2017); Espinoza v. Montana Department of Revenue, 140 S. Ct. 2246 (2020); Carson v. Makin, 142 S. Ct. 1987 (2022).

83 Roman Catholic Diocese of Brooklyn v. Cuomo, 141 S. Ct. 63 (2020); Tandon v. Newsom, 141 S. Ct. 1294 (2021).

84 Tandon, 141 S. Ct. at 1296 (emphasis added).

85 Roman Catholic Diocese of Brooklyn, 141 S. Ct. at 69 (Gorsuch J, concurring).

86 Dr. A v. Hochul, 142 S. Ct. 552 (2021).

87 Dr. A, 142 S. Ct. at 556 (Gorsuch, J., dissenting).

88 Dr. A, 142 S. Ct. at 557 (Gorsuch, J., dissenting).

89 Katherine Franke, “What Conservative Justices Talk about When They Talk about Religious Liberty,” Nation, January 6, 2022, https://www.thenation.com/article/society/supreme-court-religion/.

90 Corporation of Presiding Bishop of Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints v. Amos, 483 U.S. 327 (1986).

91 Zelman v. Simmons-Harris, 536 U.S. 639 (2002).

92 Charles McCrary, “The Antisocial Strain of Sincere Religious Beliefs Is on the Rise,” New Republic, April 4, 2022, https://newrepublic.com/article/165942/sincerely-held-religious-belief-law.

93 McCrary, “The Antisocial Strain” (emphasis added).

94 Gowder, Paul explores this dynamic in “Why Majority Religions Should Not Be Accommodated,” Iowa Law Review 108, no. 5 (2023): 2153–87Google Scholar.