Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-5mhkq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-12T02:51:32.158Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Welfare Rights in Canadian and German Constitutional Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

According to liberal political theorists, such as John Locke and Adam Smith, liberty and equality are competing values. In Canadian constitutional law, the commitment to liberal individualism has pushed questions of socio-economic rights from the constitutional sphere into the political one.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2011 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Grundgesetz für Die Bundesrepublik Deutschland [Grundgesetz] [GG] [Basic Law], 23 May 1949, BGBl. I (Ger.).Google Scholar

2 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] 9 Feb. 2010 (Hartz IV), 125 Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 175 (__), 1 BvL 1/09 of 9 Feb. 2010, para. 134, 2010 (Ger.), available at http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/ls20100209_1bvl000109.html (last visited 7 Nov. 2011).Google Scholar

3 Gosselin v. Quebec (Att'y Gen.), [2002] 4 S.C.R. 429 (Can.).Google Scholar

4 R. v. Kapp, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483 (Can.).Google Scholar

5 Law v. Canada, [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497 (Can.).Google Scholar

6 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R 429, para. 112 (Can.).Google Scholar

7 John Rawls, Political Liberalism (1993).Google Scholar

8 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 15(1), Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act, 1982, c. 11 (U.K.).Google Scholar

9 Regulation Respecting Social Aid, R.R.Q., 1981, c. A-16, r. 1, §. 29, amended by 113 O.G. II 4118 (Can.).Google Scholar

10 Gwen Brodsky & Shelagh Day, Women's Poverty Is an Equality Violation, in Making Equality Rights Real: Securing Substantive Equality under the Charter 323 (Fay Faraday, Margaret Denike & M. Kate Stephenson eds. 2006).Google Scholar

12 Id.; see also Gosselin v. Quebec (Att'y Gen.), [2002] 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 130 (Can.) (L'Heureux-Dubé, J. dissenting).Google Scholar

13 See Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429 (Can.) (explaining that the Court split 5-4 on the decision with L'Heureux-Dubé, Bastarache, Arbour, & LeBel, JJ., dissenting).Google Scholar

14 Law v. Canada (Minister of Emp't & Immigration), [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 7 (Can.).Google Scholar

15 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429, paras. 42–44 (Can.).Google Scholar

17 Law, 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 105 (Can.).Google Scholar

18 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 55 (Can.).Google Scholar

21 Id. at para. 8.Google Scholar

22 See id. at para. 64 (noting that “the availability of other resources, like family assistance” likely mitigated any adverse impacts of the law).Google Scholar

23 Id. at para. 44.Google Scholar

25 Id. at para. 27.Google Scholar

26 Id. at paras. 43–44.Google Scholar

29 Id.; see, e.g., id. at para. 65.Google Scholar

30 Id. at para. 47.Google Scholar

31 Id. at paras. 131–32.Google Scholar

32 Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, s. 7, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule B to the Canada Act, 1982, c. 11 (U.K.).Google Scholar

33 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 75 (Can.).Google Scholar

34 Id. (L'Heureux-Dubé, J., concurring in the dissent).Google Scholar

35 Id. at para. 75.Google Scholar

37 Id. at para. 80 (McLachlin, C.J.) (quoting Irwin Toy Ltd. v. Quebec (Att'y Gen.), [1989] 1 S.C.R. 927, 1003 (Can.)).Google Scholar

39 Id. at para. 81:Google Scholar

40 Id. at para. 83.Google Scholar

41 Id. (Arbour, J., dissenting).Google Scholar

42 See id. (“The right to a minimum level of social assistance … can be readily accommodated under the s. 7 rights to ‘life, liberty and security of the person’ without the need to constitutionalize ‘property’ rights or interests.”).Google Scholar

43 In Dunmore v. Ontario (Att'y Gen.), [2001] 3 S.C.R. 1016 (Can.), the Supreme Court recognized that constitutional violations are not limited to instances of government misfeasance, but that legislative nonfeasance can also invite Charter scrutiny.Google Scholar

44 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429Google Scholar

45 Id. (Arbour, J., dissenting).Google Scholar

48 See S. Afr. Const., 1996; see also Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217 (III), U.N. Doc. A/RES/217(III), (10 Dec. 1948), available at http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Pages/Language.aspx?LangID=eng (last visited 7 Nov. 2011); Kende, Mark S., The South African Constitutional Court's Embrace of Socio-Economic Rights: A Comparative Perspective, 6 Chap. L. Rev. 137 (2003).Google Scholar

49 Human dignity has a long-standing history, however, as a conceptual value and the “lodestar” of Charter rights interpretation. See R. v. Kapp, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483, para. 21 (Can.). In R v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, 136 (Can.), Justice Dickson stated: “The Court must be guided by the values and principles essential to a free and democratic society which I believe embody, to name but a few, respect for the inherent dignity of the human person, commitment to social justice and equality … and faith in social and political institutions which enhance the participation of individuals and groups in society.”Google Scholar

50 Law v. Canada, [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 51 (Can.).Google Scholar

52 Id. at para. 39.Google Scholar

55 Id. at paras. 62–74.Google Scholar

56 R. v. Kapp, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483, para. 23 (Can.).Google Scholar

57 Id. at para. 15.Google Scholar

58 Andrews v. Law Soc'y of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, para. 17 (Can.); see also Kapp, 2 S.C.R. 483 at para. 23 (Can.).Google Scholar

59 Andrews, 1 S.C.R. 143, para. 17 (Can.).Google Scholar

60 Notably, in the Supreme Court's more recent decision in Ermineskin Indian Band and Nation v. Canada, [2009] 1 S.C.R. 222 (Can.), the Court did not refer to Law, “human dignity”, or the four contextual factors for a finding of discrimination employed in Law. The removal of human dignity as a legal principle from s. 15 Charter analysis would appear complete.Google Scholar

61 Kapp, 2 S.C.R. 483, para. 20 (Can.).Google Scholar

62 Id. (emphasis added).Google Scholar

63 Id. at para. 22.Google Scholar

64 Id. at para. 23.Google Scholar

65 Id. at para. 24.Google Scholar

66 Id. at para. 23.Google Scholar

67 Gosselin v. Quebec (Att'y Gen.), [2002] 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 112 (Can.).Google Scholar

68 Law v. Canada, [1999] 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 10 (Can.).Google Scholar

69 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 55 (Can.).Google Scholar

70 Law, 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 10 (Can.).Google Scholar

71 Id. (emphasis added).Google Scholar

72 Ontario (Disability Support Program) v. Tranchemontagne (2010), O.A.C. 593, paras. 90–91 (Can. Ont. C.A.), may be a source of optimism. Although directly concerned with a challenge to the equality guarantees of the Human Rights Code, the court noted that:Google Scholar

73 Gosselin, 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 136 (Can.) (L'Heureux-Dubé, J., dissenting).Google Scholar

74 Id. at para. 113. Under R v. Oakes, [1986] 1 S.C.R. 103, 136 (Can.), “the analysis of the right at issue should be kept separate from the inquiry into an impugned distinction's justification.” See also Andrews v. Law Soc'y of British Columbia, [1989] 1 S.C.R. 143, para. 182 (Can.).Google Scholar

75 In Law, 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 10 (Can.), the Court emphasized that “There is [sic] a variety of factors which may be referred to by a s. 15(1) claimant in order to demonstrate that legislation demeans his or her dignity. The list of factors is not closed ….”Google Scholar

76 See id. at para. 7 (Iacobucci, J.) (“The contextual factors which determine whether legislation has the effect of demeaning a claimant's dignity must be construed and examined from the perspective of the claimant. The focus of the inquiry is both subjective and objective. The relevant point of view is that of the reasonable person ….”). This was echoed by Justice L'Heureux-Dubé in her dissent in Gosselin:Google Scholar

77 For a useful analysis, see Denise Réaume, Discrimination and Dignity, 63 La. L. Rev. 1 (2004), which describes protection against the denial of dignity constituting benefits as a key feature of the Section 15 equality guarantee. See also Chris Essert, Dignity and Membership, Equality and Egalitarianism: Economic Rights and Section 15, 19 Can. J. L. & Juris. 407 (2006).Google Scholar

78 Law, 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 10 (Can.) (emphasis added).Google Scholar

79 See generally Essert, supra note 77.Google Scholar

80 Law, 1 S.C.R. 497, para. 51 (Can.).Google Scholar

81 R. v. Kapp, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 483, para. 23 (Can.).Google Scholar

82 See Hunter et al. v. Southam Inc., [1984] 2 S.C.R. 145, 156 (Can.) (Laskin, C.J., taking no part in the decision) (“The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms is a purposive document. Its purpose is to guarantee and to protect, within the limits of reason, the enjoyment of the rights and freedoms it enshrines. It is intended to constrain governmental action inconsistent with those rights and freedoms.”).Google Scholar

83 Rösler, Hannes, Harmonizing the German Civil Code of the Nineteenth Century with a Modern Constitution—The Lüth Revolution 50 Years Ago in Comparative Perspective, 23 Tul. Eur. & Civ. L.F. 4 (2008).Google Scholar

84 Article 48 is well-known for giving the President extensive powers in times of emergency, including the authority to rule the Republic without the Reichstag.Google Scholar

87 Markovitz, Inga, Constitution Making After National Catastrophes: Germany in 1949 and 1990, 49 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 1309 (2008).Google Scholar

90 Id. at 1310.Google Scholar

91 GG, 23 May 1949, BGBl. I, art. 1(1) (Ger.).Google Scholar

92 Kommers notes that the FCC has characterized human dignity as both “an objective and a subjective right:” Objective, because it imposes a positive obligation on the state to establish the prerequisite conditions of its realization, and subjective because it restrains the state from interfering with personal dignity and autonomy. See Donald P. Kommers, The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany 312 (2d ed. 1997).Google Scholar

93 See BVerfG 15 Jan. 1958 (Lüth), 7 BVerfGE 198, (__), 1 BvR 400/51 of 15 Jan. 1958 (Ger.).Google Scholar

94 The Constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany 12 (Ulrich Karpen ed., Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft Baden-Baden 1988).Google Scholar

95 L. Weinrib, Constitutional Courts and Constitutional Rights (Fall 2010) (unpublished handout) (on file with author).Google Scholar

96 L. Weinrib, Original Preamble to the German Basic Law, 1949 (Fall 2010) (unpublished handout) (on file with author).Google Scholar

97 See Rösler, supra note 83, at 10; see also Ingo Müller, Hitler's Justice: The Courts of the Third Reich (Deborah Lucas Schneider trans., Harvard Univ. Press 1991); Michael Stolleis, The Law Under the Swastika: Studies on Legal History in Nazi Germany (Thomas Dunlap trans., Univ. of Chicago Press 1998); Dubber, Markus Dirk, Judicial Positivism and Hitler's Injustice, 93 Col. L. R. 1807 (1993) (reviewing Müller, surpa).Google Scholar

98 GG, 23 May 1949, BGBl. I, art. 93(1) (Ger.).Google Scholar

99 Rösler, supra note 83, at 14.Google Scholar

100 Id. at 13.Google Scholar

101 Over 96% of the cases filed with the FCC since its establishment have been complaints of this nature. Id. at 14.Google Scholar

102 BVerfG 15 Jan. 1958 (Lüth), 7 BVerfGE 198 (__), 1 BvR 400/51 of 15 Jan. 1958 (Ger.).Google Scholar

103 Mann, Dennis-Jonathan, Legalization and Juridification: Judicial Review as a Catalyst of Institutional Change 4 (European University Institute Draft), available at http://www.eui.eu/Personal/Researchers/mann/pdf/Mann,-Dennis-Jonathan_Judicial-Review_Catalyst_Institutional-Change.pdf (last visited 9 Nov. 2011).Google Scholar

104 “Every person shall have the right freely to express and disseminate his opinions in speech, writing and pictures, and to inform himself without hindrance from generally accessible sources. Freedom of the press and freedom of reporting by means of broadcasts and films shall be guaranteed. There shall be no censorship.” GG, 23 May 1949, BGBl. I, art. 5(1) (Ger.).Google Scholar

105 See Kommers, supra note 92, at 363.Google Scholar

106 Lüth, 7 BVerfGE 198 (__), 1 BvR 400/51 of 15 Jan. 1958, para. 1 (Ger.) (translated by Tony Weir).Google Scholar

107 Id. at para. 4.Google Scholar

108 Id. at para. 1.Google Scholar

109 Id. at para. 3.Google Scholar

110 Id. Google Scholar

111 Engle, Eric Allen, Third Party Effect of Fundamental Rights (Drittwirkung), 5 Hanse L. R. 165 (2009).Google Scholar

112 Lüth, 7 BVerfGE 198 (__), 1 BvR 400/51 of 15 Jan. 1958 (Ger.), translated in Kommers, supra note 92, at 363; see also Engle, supra note 111, at 165–66.Google Scholar

113 Weir, supra note 106, at 5.Google Scholar

114 Rösler, supra note 83, at 31.Google Scholar

115 See id. at 32; see also RWDSU v. Dolphin Delivery Ltd., [1986] 2 S.C.R. 573 (Can.).Google Scholar

116 Mann, supra note 103, at 4.Google Scholar

117 See id. for further development of this argument.Google Scholar

118 Weir, supra note 106, at 4.Google Scholar

119 Id. Google Scholar

120 “Property and the right of inheritance shall be guaranteed. Their content and limits shall be defined by the laws.” GG, 23 May 1949, BGBl. I, art. 14(1) (Ger.). “The Federal Republic of Germany is a democratic and social federal state” Art. 20(1) GG; “The constitutional order in the Länder must conform to the principles of a republican, democratic and social state governed by the rule of law, within the meaning of this Basic Law … “ Id. art. 28(1).Google Scholar

121 Id. art. 14(1).Google Scholar

122 See, e.g., Codetermination case, 50 BVerfGE 290 (339) (1979); Hamburg Flood Control case, 24 BVerfGE 367 (389) (1968); see also Gregory S. Alexander, Property As a Fundamental Constitutional Right? The German Example, 88 Cornell L. Rev. 5 (2003).Google Scholar

123 GG, 23 May 1949, BGBl. I, art. 14(2) (Ger.).Google Scholar

124 “Expropriation shall only be permissible for the public good. It may only be ordered by or pursuant to a law that determines the nature and extent of compensation. Such compensation shall be determined by establishing an equitable balance between the public interest and the interests of those affected.” Id. art. 14(3).Google Scholar

125 Kommers, supra note 92, at 241.Google Scholar

126 Id. at 242.Google Scholar

127 Alexander, supra note 122, at 5.Google Scholar

128 Kommers, supra note 92, at 242.Google Scholar

129 BVerfG 9 Feb. 2010 (Hartz IV), 125 BVerfGE 175 (__), 1 BvL 1/09 of 9 Feb. 2010, para. 118, 2010 (Ger.), available at http://www.bverfg.de/entscheidungen/ls20100209_1bvl000109.html (last visited 7 Nov. 2011).Google Scholar

130 Id. at para. 120.Google Scholar

131 Id. Google Scholar

132 Id. Google Scholar

133 Id. Google Scholar

134 Id. Google Scholar

135 Id. at para. 121.Google Scholar

136 Id. Google Scholar

137 Id. at para. 122.Google Scholar

138 Id. Google Scholar

139 Id. at para. 124.Google Scholar

140 Id. at para. 121.Google Scholar

141 Id. at para. 122.Google Scholar

142 “Abstract review” is a procedural practice, similar to the Canadian reference jurisdiction, which allows the FCC to review the constitutional compliance of a specific law without the requirement of an individual litigant bringing a positive complaint to the court.Google Scholar

143 Rawls, supra note 7, at 156.Google Scholar

144 See Heller, Hermann, The Nature and Structure of the State, 18 Cardozo L. Rev. 1139, 1185–86, 1191 (David Dyzenhaus trans., 1996); see also David Schneiderman, Social Rights and “Common Sense”: Gosselin Through a Media Lens, in Poverty: Rights, Social Citizenship, Legal Activism 58 (Margot Young et al. eds., UBC Press 2007) (discussing Heller's social theory of law as it relates to the Gosselin case).Google Scholar

145 Dyzenhaus, David, Hermann Heller and the Legality of Legitimacy, 16 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 645 (1996) [hereinafter Legality of Legitimacy].Google Scholar

146 Heller, supra note 144, at 1157.Google Scholar

147 Dyzenhaus, Legality of Legitimacy, supra note 145, at 653.Google Scholar

148 Id. at 652.Google Scholar

149 Id. at 653; see also Rawls supra, note 7 (explaining how Rawls dealt at length with the potential problems pluralism posed for modern political regimes).Google Scholar

150 Dyzenhaus, Legality of Legitimacy, supra note 145, at 654.Google Scholar

151 Id. at 656.Google Scholar

152 Heller, supra note 144, at 1185–86; see also Schneiderman, supra note 144, at 58.Google Scholar

153 Dyzenhaus, David, Hermann Heller: An Introduction, 18 Cardozo L. Rev. 1129, 1131 (1996).Google Scholar

154 Id. Google Scholar

155 Id. Google Scholar

156 Heller, supra note 144, at 1191; see also Schneiderman, supra note 144, at 59.Google Scholar

157 Scott, Craig & Macklem, Patrick, Constitutional Ropes of Sand or Justiciable Guarantees? Social Rights in a New South African Constitution, 141 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1, 6 (1992).Google Scholar

158 Id. Google Scholar

159 In Kant's original conception, individual autonomy is limited by the categorical imperative to treat persons as ends in and of themselves. Indeed, Kant, more than any other natural law thinker, was concerned with human dignity in his defense of private reason.Google Scholar

160 Schneiderman, supra note 144, at 57.Google Scholar

161 Id. at 58.Google Scholar

162 Dyzenhaus, Legality of Legitimacy, supra note 145, at 645.Google Scholar

163 Id. Google Scholar

164 Gosselin v. Quebec (Att'y Gen.), [2002] 4 S.C.R. 429, para. 27 (Can.).Google Scholar

165 See Schneiderman, supra note 144, at 61–63 (expanding on this point).Google Scholar

166 Dyzenhaus, Legality of Legitimacy, supra note 145, at 645; see also Schneiderman, supra note 144, at 61–63.Google Scholar

167 Rawls, supra note 7, at 166.Google Scholar

168 Id. Google Scholar

169 Id. Google Scholar

170 See Berlin, Isaiah, Two Concepts of Liberty, in Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford Univ. Press 1969).Google Scholar

171 Berlin saw in positive liberty the potential for political totalitarianism, and seemed to prefer the negative conception of this value—although he recognized that both forms of liberty were necessary to secure the conditions of free political society. Id. Google Scholar

172 Rawls, supra note 7, at 166.Google Scholar

173 Examples include Rawls, Schneiderman, Réaume, Brodsky and Day, as well as Justices L'Heureux-Dubé and Arbour in Gosselin. Google Scholar