Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-q6k6v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T06:34:26.707Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Old Weimar Meets New Political Economy: Democratic Representation in the Party State

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 March 2019

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

One of the prominent questions surrounding Weimar Theory of the State was that of the significance and influence of the political parties within the state. From the perspective of constitutional law, parties were as undesirable as they were an “inescapable” fact of modern statehood. They appeared to be an absolutely necessary consequence of the emancipation of all classes and social strata: Legitimation of state rule was no longer conceivable merely as a natural rule from above; on the other hand, there was no longer a unified bourgeoisie, and it thus seemed impossible for the political whole to be represented by people who felt beholden exclusively to the common weal. The homogeneous “people” had become a heterogeneous “mass.” The parties seemed to be a necessity, on the one hand, for active citizens to articulate themselves in the political system and, on the other hand, for state unity not to be torn apart by the power of a plurality of interests leaning in many different directions. Parties could therefore be conceived of as a prerequisite for state organisation: The idea of the “party state” was born. One important protagonist in the discussion on the status of parties within the state structure was the constitutional legal scholar Gerhard Leibholz (1901–1982). In Weimar times, he was the most prominent representative of party state theory (Parteienstaatslehre), and as someone who “had somehow fallen between the eras,” he also actively shaped the party state of the Bonn Republic for over twenty years (1951–1971), as a judge at the Federal Constitutional Court (Bundesverfassungsgericht), by significantly influencing legislation on parliamentary, party, and electoral law. His persona was therefore a particularly important bridging link between the Weimar Republic and the Federal Republic of Germany, and even today, his theses are highly topical: “Beyond all eras, Gerhard Leibholz stands for the great tradition of German constitutional theory.”

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © 2012 by German Law Journal GbR 

References

1 Leibholz, Gerhard, Die Wahlrechtsreform und ihre Grundlagen, 7 Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 159, 181 (1931) [hereinafter Leibholz, Wahlrechtsreform].Google Scholar

2 For biographical material, see Anna-Bettina Kaiser, Gerhard Leibholz, in Handbuch Staatsdenker 231 (Rüdiger Voigt & Ulrich Weiß eds., 2010).Google Scholar

3 This phrase, coined by Rudolf Smend on the occasion of Leibholz's 65th birthday, can be found, amongst other sources, in Peter Unruh, Erinnerungen an Gerhard Leibholz (1901–1982)—Staatsrechtler zwischen den Zeiten, 126 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 61, 90 (2001).Google Scholar

4 Klein, Hans, Gerhard Leibholz (1901–1982). Theoretiker der Parteiendemokratie und politischer Denker—ein Leben zwischen den Zeiten, in Rechtswissenschaft in Göttingen 528 (Fritz Loos ed., 1987).Google Scholar

5 Hecker, Jan, Die Parteienstaatslehre von Gerhard Leibholz in der wissenschaftlichen Diskussion, 34 Der Staat 287 (1995).Google Scholar

6 Bertolt Brecht, Stories of Mr. Keuner 64 (Martin Chalmers trans., City Lights Books 2001) (“Mr. Keuner ran into Mr. Muddle, the fighter against newspapers. ‘I am a great opponent of newspapers,’ said Mr. Muddle. ‘I don't want any newspapers.’ Mr. Keuner said, ‘I am a greater opponent of newspapers: I want different newspapers.'”).Google Scholar

7 Leibholz, Gerhard, Repräsentation und der Gestaltwandel der Demokratie im 20. Jahrhundert (3d ed. 1966) [hereinafter Leibholz, Repräsentation]. The first edition of his habilitation was published in 1929 and was entitled Das Wesen der Repräsentation unter besonderer Berücksichtigung des Repräsentativsystems. Ein Beitrag zur allgemeinen Staats- und Verfassungslehre. The second edition was published—unchanged, one might add—in 1960, with the title used here and maintained in the third edition; it was merely expanded by the lecture Der Gestaltwandel der Demokratie im 20. Jahrhundert from 1955. The third edition was published in 1966 and expanded by yet another lecture, Verfassungsrecht und politische Wirklichkeit, which Leibholz had held in 1965. It is remarkable that, in the respective prefaces, Leibholz comments on the reception and discussion of his work to date, thus himself testifying, as it were, to its continuity (beyond constitutions). For further central works in the context of the party state theory, see Leibholz, Wahlrechtsreform, supra note 1; Gerhard Leibholz, Volk und Partei im neuen deutschen Verfassungsrecht, 1950 Deutsches Verwaltungsblatt 194 [hereinafter Leibholz, Volk und Partei]; Gerhard Leibholz, Parteienstaat und Repräsentative Demokratie, 1951 Deutsches Verwaltungsblatt 1 [hereinafter Leibholz, Parteienstaat].Google Scholar

8 Leibholz, Wahlrechtsreform, supra note 1, at 159–60.Google Scholar

9 Leibholz, Parteienstaat, supra note 7, at 3.Google Scholar

10 Leibholz, Wahlrechtsreform, supra note 1, at 188.Google Scholar

11 See Leibholz, Parteienstaat, supra note 7, at 4.Google Scholar

12 Leibholz quotes a minister of education named Grimme as a political referee. Liebholz, Wahlrechtsreform, supra note 1, at 180.Google Scholar

13 Leibholz, Parteienstaat, supra note 7, at 7.Google Scholar

14 Leibholz, Repräsentation, supra note 7, at 98.Google Scholar

15 Leibholz, Repräsentation, supra note 7, at 103.Google Scholar

16 Hecker, supra note 5, at 289.Google Scholar

17 Id. at 299; Kaiser, supra note 2, at 231.Google Scholar

18 Hecker, supra note 5, at 287, 291.Google Scholar

19 On the development of Leibholz's theses and their reception, see Hecker, supra note 5, at 287.Google Scholar

20 Köttgen, Arnold, 19 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 290 (1930).Google Scholar

21 Wolff, Hans, 24 Archiv für Rechts- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie 392 (1930).Google Scholar

22 Nawiasky, Hans, 26 Leipziger Zeitschrift für deutsches Recht 130 (1932).Google Scholar

23 Wolff, supra note 21, at 397.Google Scholar

24 Köttgen, supra note 20, at 291.Google Scholar

25 Hofmann, Hasso, Parlamentarische Repräsentation in der parteienstaatlichen Demokratie, in Recht—Politik—Verfassung. Studien zur Geschichte der politischen Philosophie 249, 255 (1986).Google Scholar

26 Cf. Hesse, Konrad, Die verfassungsrechtliche Stellung der politischen Parteien im modernen Staat, 17 Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 10, 21 (1959). Hesse refers directly to Leibholz's writings on the Federal state. See, e.g., infra notes 28, 37.Google Scholar

27 Leibholz, Parteienstaat, supra note 7, at 4.Google Scholar

28 Hesse, supra note 26, at 10. In several elaborations, one can sense how Hesse, usually without being explicit, develops his model as a form of dissociation from Leibholz. Very often, Hesse employs arguments that render Leibholz's reflections even in the way they are phrased. Nonetheless, as his footnotes show, he barely deals explicitly with Leibholz or with the ample Weimar discussion; rather, he celebrates the caesura of the Grundgesetz—even though the title of his work, with its recourse to the “modern state,” might have suggested otherwise. See infra note 26.Google Scholar

29 Hesse, supra note 26, at 21.Google Scholar

30 Leibholz, Repräsentation, supra note 7, at 254.Google Scholar

31 Leibholz, Repräsentation, supra note 7, at 254.Google Scholar

32 Stolleis, Michael, Parteienstaatlichkeit—Krisensymptome des demokratischen Verfassungsstaats?, 44 Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 7 (1986).Google Scholar

33 Hesse, supra note 26, at 19.Google Scholar

34 Stolleis, supra note 32, at 33.Google Scholar

35 Id. at 36.Google Scholar

36 Instead of citing later scholars, I refer the reader to Volker Mittendorf, Die Qualität kollektiver Entscheidungen 25 (2009). Further sources are provided there.Google Scholar

37 See, e.g., Möllers, Christoph, Expressive versus repräsentative Demokratie, in Transnationale Verrechtlichung. Nationale Demokratien im Kontext globaler Politik 160 (Regina Kreide & Andreas Niederberger eds., 2008).Google Scholar

38 As an introduction to the themes dealt with here, see Towfigh, Emanuel & Petersen, Niels, Ökonomische Methoden im Recht. Eine Einführung für Juristen 133 (2010).Google Scholar

39 Proponents of the emerging public choice theory referred to the classic image political science had of the political actors as “romantic”; such actors could be “voters,” “politicians,” and “bureaucrats.” See, e.g., Gordon Tullock, The Politics of Bureaucracy (1965).Google Scholar

40 For the (limited) aims of this contribution, it should suffice to discuss only the central and most basic presumptions; many of these presumptions and models have been developed and further refined since the inception of public choice theory some six decades ago, or else they have been modified to suit special applications. All this, however, cannot be dealt with in depth here.Google Scholar

41 See Hartmann, Bernd, Eigeninteresse und Gemeinwohl bei Wahlen und Abstimmungen, 134 Archiv des öffentlichen Rechts 1 (2009).Google Scholar

42 Finally, it should be added that the party list system intensifies the political effects generated by the parties. For this institutional organization means that the party becomes more important for the candidate than the voters, because the party can secure a seat even if the candidate is unsuccessful with the voters; the party provides him not only with the logistical and financial means to campaign for votes, but it can also assure him of a promising position on the party list much the way insurance works. Yet, only such parties can offer a promising place on a party list in electoral system with proportional representation whose elected representatives convince the electorate. In this text, I can of course only rudimentarily touch upon these aspects that have been subject to intensive research in political science and political economy.Google Scholar

43 It seems important to note that the median voter theorem, giving expression to a strong political intuition, can only be proven mathematically with a number of restricting assumptions, among which are a one-dimensional policy space, a majoritarian two-party first-past-the-post system, and single-peaked voter preferences that in this pure form might only be rarely met in reality.Google Scholar

44 Downs, Anthony, An Economic Theory of Democracy (1957).Google Scholar

45 Hotelling, Harold, Stability in Competition, 39 Econ. J. 41 (1929).Google Scholar

46 E.g., Schumpeter, Joseph, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy 269 (1975).Google Scholar

47 Leibholz, Repräsentation, supra note 7, at 246.Google Scholar

48 See Hirschman, Albert, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organisations, and States (1970).Google Scholar

49 See supra Part C.I.2.Google Scholar

50 Cf. Olson, Mancur, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups (1965).Google Scholar

51 Cf. Petersen, Niels, Demokratie und Grundgesetz—Veränderungen des Demokratieprinzips in Art. 20 Abs. 2 GG angesichts der Herausforderungen moderner Staatlichkeit, 58 Jahrbuch des öffentlichen Rechts 137 (2010).Google Scholar

52 In the literature on Public Choice, this phenomenon is called logrolling. An impressive current example from the United States Senate may be consulted, Senate Fiscal Year 2010 Budget Markup, Part 1, (C-SPAN television broadcast Mar. 26, 2009), available at http://www.c-spanvideo.org/program/284890-1 (last visited Mar. 14, 2012).Google Scholar

53 In political economy scholarship, the relation between citizens and state organs is regarded as being analogous to a principal-agent relation. Here, the citizens are seen as principals and the state organs are seen as agents. See more details on this in James Buchanan, The Limits of Liberty (1975).Google Scholar

54 Cf. Nicklisch, Andreas & Petersen, Niels, Vertragstheorie, in Towfigh & Petersen, supra note 38, at 121. Adverse selection describes a mechanism in which there is a downward spiral as a result of information asymmetry between the principal (e.g., a buyer who is ultimately not capable of reliably determining the quality of a product) and the agent (e.g., a seller who knows the product and its quality well). Worse and worse goods are sold at ever lower prices, because the average price (the weighted average of the relation between good and poor products on the market) offered by the buyer, who is burdened with an information risk, is only attractive for those buyers whose product is poor, i.e., worth less than the average price. Those who have good products stay away from the market, which is why we speak of a market mechanism leading to an adverse selection.Google Scholar

55 Cf. Akerlof, George, The Market for “Lemons”: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism, 84 Q.J. Econ. 488 (1970).Google Scholar

56 Accession to a party might well be such a signal. Cf. Snyder, James & Ting, Michael, An Informational Rationale for Political Parties, 46 Am. J. Pol. Sci. 90 (2002).Google Scholar

57 Scores of mathematicians and economists attempt to sidestep this implacable insight by developing models that try to soften individual criteria—so far, without much success. For the dictator and the Pareto criterion, a modification is not up for discussion. With transitivity, compromises might indeed be reached—perhaps it suffices merely to determine the winner of an election—but further developments of Arrow's theorem have shown that there are significant difficulties even then. Whether the criterion of independence of irrelevant alternatives should be softened or given up altogether is indeed being discussed; however, what are still lacking are good reasons that may rationalize an election procedure that contravenes this criterion. With regard to the criterion of universality, there is hope: Much research is being conducted to develop models offering—for certain situations—procedures that could avoid our problems. For the political theory discourse, a set of alternative models seems interesting that does not presuppose completely arbitrary preference orders of voters but well-ordered political conflicts. On this, see also the synopsis in Amartya Sen, The Possibility of Social Choice, 89 Am. Econ. Rev. 349 (1999). Moreover, for the sake of completeness, it shall be noted that the Downsian median voter theorem described above may be considered one solution to the Arrow theorem: If an aggregation of preferences at the median is successful, this preference order meets all criteria postulated by Arrow. However, the Downsian model assumptions, especially the one-dimensional policy space and the single-peaked preferences of voters, may hardly be met in reality.Google Scholar

58 Hartmann, supra note 41, at 22.Google Scholar