Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-dnltx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T00:08:26.727Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Lotteries, Knowledge, and Irrelevant Alternatives

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 August 2013

RACHEL MCKINNON*
Affiliation:
University of Calgary

Abstract

The lottery paradox plays an important role in arguments for various norms of assertion. Why is it that, prior to information on the results of a draw, assertions such as, “My ticket lost,” seem inappropriate? This paper is composed of two projects. First, I articulate a number of problems arising from Timothy Williamson’s analysis of the lottery paradox. Second, I propose a relevant alternatives theory, which I call the Non-Destabilizing Alternatives Theory (NDAT), that better explains the pathology of asserting lottery propositions, while permitting assertions of what I call fallible propositions such as, “My car is in the driveway.”

Le paradoxe de la loterie joue un rôle important dans l’argumentation visant à défendre diverses normes de l’assertion. Comment se fait-il que, avant que les résultats d’un tirage soient connus, des assertions comme «Mon billet a perdu» semblent inappropriées? Cet article se compose de deux projets. Premièrement, je relève certains problèmes issus de l’analyse du paradoxe de la loterie par Timothy Williamson. Deuxièmement, je propose une théorie des alternatives pertinentes que j’appelle la «théorie des alternatives non-déstabilisantes» (NDAT), et qui explique d’une meilleure façon la pathologie de l’assertion de propositions concernant la loterie, tout en permettant des assertions faillibles, telles que «Ma voiture est dans l’entrée».

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Philosophical Association 2013 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, J. L. 1946 Other Minds. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. 20, 148187.Google Scholar
DeRose, Keith 1991 Epistemic Possibilities. Philosophical Review, 100 (4), 581605.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith 1996 Relevant Alternatives and the Context of Knowledge Attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56 (1), 193197.Google Scholar
Dodd, Dylan 2007 Why Williamson Should be a Sceptic. Philosophical Quarterly, 57 (229), 635649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, Trent and Rysiew, Patrick 2009 Fallibilism, Epistemic Possibility, and Concessive Knowledge Attributions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78 (1), 123132.Google Scholar
Douven, Igor 2006 Assertion, Knowledge, and Rational Credibility. Philosophical Review, 115 (4), 449485.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred 1971 Conclusive Reasons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49, 122.Google Scholar
Fantl, Jeremy and McGrath, Matthew 2009 Knowledge in an Uncertain World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert 1973 Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hawthorne, John 2004 Knowledge and Lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hendricks, Vincent 2006 Mainstream and Formal Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hill, Christopher and Schechter, Joshua 2007 Hawthorne’s Lottery Puzzle and the Nature of Belief. Philosophical Issues, 17, 102122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kindred, Dave 1999 Against All Odds–Hole-in-One Records. http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m0HFI/is_1_50/ai_54390606/ Last accessed December 2010.Google Scholar
Kvanvig, Jonathan 2009 Assertion, Knowledge, and Lotteries. Greenough, P. and Pritchard, D. (Eds.), Williamson on Knowledge (pp. 140160). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kyburg, Henry 1961 Probability and the Logic of Rational Belief. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer 2007 Norms of Assertion. Nous, 41 (4), 594626.Google Scholar
Lewis, David 1996 Elusive Knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 549567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayr, Ernst 1991 One Long Argument: Charles Darwin and the Genesis of Modern Evolutionary Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
McKinnon, Rachel 2013a The Supportive Reasons Norm of Assertion. American Philosophical Quarterly, 50 (2), 121135.Google Scholar
McKinnon, Rachel 2013b Getting Luck Properly Under Control. Metaphilosophy, 44 (4), 496511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan 2008 Knowledge in the Image of Assertion. Philosophical Issues, 18, 119.Google Scholar
Smith, Michael 2010 What Else Justification Could Be. Nous, 44 (1), 1031.Google Scholar
Stine, Gail 1976 Skepticism, Relevant Alternatives, and Deductive Closure. Philosophical Studies, 29, 249261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogel, Jonathan 1990 Are There Counterexamples to the Closure Principle?Roth, M. and Ross, G. (Eds.), Doubting: Contemporary Perspectives in Skepticism. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Vogel, Jonathan 1999 The New Relevant Alternatives Theory. Philosophical Perspectives, 13 (13), 155180.Google Scholar
Whewell, William 1840 The Philosophy of Inductive Sciences. London: J. and J. J. Deighton.Google Scholar
Williamson, Timothy 2000 Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, E. O. 1998 Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: A. A. Knopf Inc.Google Scholar