Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-sjtt6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-20T01:53:12.907Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Free Will Skepticism and Personhood as a Desert Base

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Benjamin Vilhauer*
Affiliation:
William Paterson University, Wayne, NJ07470, USA

Extract

In contemporary free will theory, a significant number of philosophers are once again taking seriously the possibility that human beings do not have free will, and are therefore not morally responsible for their actions. (Free will is understood here as whatever satisfies the control condition of moral responsibility.) Free will theorists commonly assume that giving up the belief that human beings are morally responsible implies giving up all our beliefs about desert. But the consequences of giving up the belief that we are morally responsible are not quite this dramatic. Giving up the belief that we are morally responsible undermines many, and perhaps most, of the desert claims we are pretheoretically inclined to accept. But it does not undermine desert claims based on the sheer fact of personhood. Even in the absence of belief in moral responsibility, personhood-based desert claims require us to respect persons and their rights. So personhood-based desert claims can provide a substantial role for desert in free will skeptics’ ethical theories.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Campbell, J.K. 1997. ‘A Compatibilist Theory of Alternative Possibilities.Philosophical Studies 88 (1997): 319–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, J.K. 2005. ‘Compatibilist Alternatives.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (2005): 387406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwall, S. 1977. ‘Two Kinds of Respect.Ethics 88.1 (1977): 3649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, J. 1963. ‘Justice and Personal Desert.’ In Nomos VI: Justice, Friedrich, C.J. and Chapman, J.W. eds. New York: Atherton Press.Google Scholar
Feldman, F. 1996. ‘Responsibility as a Condition for Desert.Mind 105.417 (1996): 165–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, F. 1995. ‘Desert: Reconsideration of Some Received Wisdom.Mind 104.413 (1995): 6377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischer, J.M. 1995. The Metaphysics of Free Will (Aristotelian Society Series v. 14). Malden, MA: Blackwell Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1969. ‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.Journal of Philosophy 66 (1969): 829–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankfurt, H. 1971. ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person,’ Journal of Philosophy 68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ginet, C. 1996. ‘In Defense of the Principle of Alternative Possibilities: Why I Don't Find Frankfurt's Argument Convincing.Philosophical Perspectives 10 (1996): 403–17.Google Scholar
Hume, D. 1975. Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, L.A., Selby-Bigge ed. New York: Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kane, R. 1996. The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, E. 2002. ‘Doing Without Desert.Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 83 (2002): 180205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1981. ‘Are We Free to Break the LawsヨTheoria 47 (1981): 113121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. 1976. Social Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G.E. 1911. Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1977. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Pereboom, D. 2001. Living Without Free Will. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pereboom, D.Is Our Conception of Agent-Causation CoherentヨPhilosophical Topics 32 (2006): 275–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rachels, J. 1978. ‘What People Deserve.’ In Justice and Economic Distribution, Arthur, J. and Shaw, W.H. eds. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Rawls, J. 1999. A Theory of Justice, Revised Edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Belknap.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sadurski, W. 1985. Giving Desert Its Due: Social Justice and Legal Theory. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandel, M. 1998. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, 2nd Edition. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slote, M. 2001. Morals from Motives. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Slote, M. 1990. ‘Ethics Without Free Will.Social Theory and Practice 16.3 (1990): 369383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. 1996. ‘Responsibility and Desert: Defending the Connection.Mind 105.417 (1996): 157–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smilansky, S. 2000. Free Will and Illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Smilansky, S. 2005. ‘Free Will and Respect for Persons.Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29 (2005): 248261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommers, T. 2007. ‘The Objective Attitude.The Philosophical Quarterly 57.228 (2007): 321–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, P.F. 1963. ‘Freedom and Resentment.Proceedings of the British Academy 48 (1963): 125.Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter. 1983. An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Vihvelin, K. 1994. ‘Stop Me Before I Kill Again.Philosophical Studies 75 (1994): 115148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vihvelin, K. 2004. ‘Free Will Demystified: A Dispositional Account.Philosophical Topics 32 (2004): 427–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Widerker, D. 1995. ‘Libertarianism and Frankfurt's Attack on the Principle of Alternative Possibilities.The Philosophical Review 104 (1995): 247–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar