Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-fv566 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-19T23:50:02.017Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Four Conclusions about Violence of the Left

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Ted Honderich*
Affiliation:
University College London

Extract

It is a terrible fact of this time, not much lessened by there having been similar facts in the past, or by the likelihood of there being more in the future, that men make uses of destructive force against persons and things, force condemned by ordinary law but directed to changing societies in certain ways. Certain of these changes in societies, although typically they are sought for themselves, may be taken to make for progress toward a certain goal, well-being for all persons without exception, all persons in whatever societies. The uses of force related in this way to the goal of well-being are of a general course political violence of the Left. My purpose in this essay is to say some things in advocacy of a certain response, in good part a sceptical one, to the general moral question of what is to be said against such violence, and what for it.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1979

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 This essay is much better as a result of what was said by critics in university audiences. I wish to thank in particular those who made acute objections during my visit to the University of Lethbridge in September, 1978, aided by the Canada Council. The essay was first read to a UNESCO meeting in Paris earlier in 1978.

2 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, chaps. 26 and 30.

3 John Locke, Second Treatise of Government, chaps. 16-19.

4 J. J. Rousseau, A Discourse on Political Economy.

5 Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Oxford, 1972).Google Scholar

6 Cf., Peter Singer, Democracy and Disobedience (Oxford, 1973).Google Scholar

7 Cf. J. L., Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford, 1962).Google Scholar

8 There are insuperable difficulties in trying to argue from these three considerations to the existence of an actual agreement, as distinct from a general expectation. To mention a less obvious one of these difficulties, the Agreement Argument presumably requires that the state or society make a uniform offer to all members of society, the same offer for each member. What is it? Is any uniform thing that can be found also substantial? Certainly we can find a far from uniform pattern in the actual provision of opportunities, protections, roles and so on to individuals by the state.

9 See R.M., Hare, ‘Political Obligation', in Honderich, Ted (ed.) Social Ends and Political Means (london, 1976).Google Scholar

10 Cf. Singer, op. cit.

11 Stuart Hampshire, Morality and Pessimism, the Leslie Stephen Lecture, 1972 (Cambridge, 1972). Mr. Hampshire has not written substantially about political violence, but I have (since writing this essay) come upon a transcript of a television talk by him. (The New Review 2, no. 24 (March 1976)). He says in part:

… a moral rule against all assassinations for political reasons is needed, even though there will be very unusual and extreme circumstances in which an assassination in peace-time is justified. For example, if a group of prominent Germans had arranged the assassination of Hitler in August, 1939, with a view to making peace, it is my opinion that they would have acted rightly; the prolonged horrors and the vast cruelties avoided would have outweighed the evil example in this extreme and exceptional case. Moreover, he was already a multiple murderer. But I still think, from my own moral position, that one ought to be shocked by the idea of political assassination, and that there ought to be a strongly felt rule against it, in spite of these extreme, exceptional cases. One has to have moral rules, backed by moral feeling attached to the rules, even if in very exceptional circumstances, such as the Hitler one, it may be permissible to break the rule ….

… the straight, clear question in the title of this series ('Does a political cause ever give us the right to kill?’) deserves a straight, clear answer; or at least a fairly clear one, if the issue is too complex for complete clarity; yes, a political cause does sometimes give us the right to kill: in a war for the defence of one's country, but not in an unnecessary, unjust, undeclared, useless war, as in Vietnam. I will suggest the beginnings of a rough criterion for justified killing in very extreme situations in peacetime. Four conditions are necessary: first, that it is a response to a great injustice and oppression, as of a resistance movement against a foreign power ruling by force and terror so that the victim is the reverse of innocent; secondly, that it is certain that no lawful and non-violent means of remedying the injustice and oppression will be given: thirdly, that the political killing will certainly cause far less suffering, and less widespread suffering than the present injustice and cruelty are causing: lastly, that it really is very probable that the killing will end the oppression, and that it will not provoke more violence and more horror; this last condition is very rarely satisfied, but sometimes it may have been. These principles give the outline of a possible morality of political violence, though of course a highly disputable one.

12 Views and problems of this kind are admirably discussed by Glover, Jonathan in Causing Death and Saving Lives (Harmondsworth, 1977).Google Scholar

13 Cf., James Griffin's excellent inquiry,’ Are There Incommensurable Values?', Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (1977).Google Scholar

14 See my Violence For Equality: Inquiries in Political Philosophy (Hitarmonds worth, 1979)Google Scholar

15 Ibid.

16 See, for example, A. B., Atkinson, Wealth, Income and Inequality (Harmondsworth, 1973)Google Scholar; Atkinson, and A. J., Harrison, Distribution of Personal Wealth in Britain (Cambridge, 1977).Google Scholar See also The Times, 2 june 1978, for related figures.

17 Lampman, Robert J., ‘Income and Inequality: the 1930's to the 1960's', in Poverty and Affluence, ed. Will, Robert E. and Vatter, Harold G., 2nd ed. (New York, 1970).Google Scholar

18 Atkinson, op. cit., p. 21.

19 Lampman, op. cit., p. 51.

20 In order to arrive at some guess as to the state of incomes twenty years from now, if an unprecedented change does not occur, let us again look to the past. The top tenth of British families, according to one calculation (H. F., Lydall, ‘The Long-Term Trend in the Size-Distribution of Income', Royal Statistical Society journal (1959), p. 14)Google Scholar, received roughly these percentages of the total income after tax in the years in question:

1938 34 %

1949 27 %

1957 23.5 %

During the same period, no doubt, there was some increase in the percentage income that was received by the one-tenth British families with the worst income. Given the record, and the calculation that the top tenth now receives about 25 percent of the total and the bottom tenth about 2 or 3 percent, it is a reasonable guess that in twenty years the top tenth of British families will receive something of the order of 15 percent of the income and the bottom tenth something like 5 percent.

In the United States, according to one calculation (Scoville, James G., (ed.), Perspectives on Poverty and Income Distribution (lexington, Mass., 1971, p.18)Google Scholar, the best-paid and the worst-paid fifths (not tenths) of families received these percentages of total income in the years mentioned:

1937 52% 4%

1947 46 % 5%

1962 45 % 5%

To return to our chosen categories, tenths of American families, we have it that the top tenth now has about 27 percent of the total income and the bottom tenth about 1 percent. The state of affairs in 20 years, if there is no radical transformation of American society, may be that the top tenth will have something like 23 percent of the total income and the bottom tenth will have something like 3 percent.

21 Coles, Robert, Still Hungry in America (Cleveland, 1969), p.Google Scholar

22 Bhagwati, Jagdish, The Economics of Underdeveloped Countries (London, 1971), p.Google Scholar

23 See the third of my Three Essays on Political Violence (Oxford, 1977).Google Scholar

24 Paul Wilkinson, Cf., Terrorism and the Liberal State (london, 1977), pp. 8283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

25 See my Violence For Equality: Inquiries in Political Philosophy, Ch. 4.