Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T09:39:29.452Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Myles Burnyeat, The Theaetetus of Plato, with a translation of Plato's Theaetetus by M. J. Levett, revised by Myles Burnyeat. Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett 1990. Pp. xiv + 351.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

James Dybikowski*
Affiliation:
University of British ColumbiaVancouver, BCCanadaV6T 1W5

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Critical Notice
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Since then, the publisher has reissued the Levett translation as revised by Burnyeat with a brief, but characteristically insightful, introduction by Williams.

2 As Burnyeat remarks about the passage which introduces the image of Socrates as an intellectual midwife: ‘it should be read with feeling as well as thought’ (6). Later Burnyeat notes more generally that ‘a great work of philosophy demands a response which is more than merely intellectual’ (39). He makes it amply clear, however, that this outlook does not sanction the ignoring of argument. As he later observes: ‘the business of philosophy is argument, not preference’ (54).

3 It is summarized in an extended note in ‘Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed,’ Philosophical Review 91 (1982) 6-7, and informs his analyses in other articles.

4 Cornford, Francis M. Plato's Theory of Knowledge (Indianapolis: Liberal Arts Press 1957), 49Google Scholar

5 Protagoras's doctrine has been dealt with in the preceding sentence.

6 McDowell, John Plato: Theaetetus (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1973), 196–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Here McDowell, however, only characterizes such a principles as ‘plausible.’

7 Later Burnyeat describes how Wittgenstein's (as well as Ryle's) semantic approach to Part III of the dialogue — and of the dream in particular — has been historically influential, indeed ‘spellbinding,’ in inducing commentators to approach Plato's text in this light rather than the epistemological approach he argues that Plato follows (150-1).