Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-25T01:50:05.180Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Teleosemantics and the Epiphenomenality of Content

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

The naturalistically inclined philosopher of mind faces two related challenges: (1) show how mental content could be part of the natural world, and (2) show how content can be one of the factors responsible for producing (causing) behaviour, that is, show that content is not epiphenomenal. One might pursue the first goal with the intent of showing that mental content is epiphenomenal, but it is more likely that the philosopher concerned with showing how content can be naturalized also expects content to be causally efficacious. Indeed, why pursue the first challenge while holding that content is epiphenomenal? Thus these two challenges overlap: show how content can be naturalized without making content epiphenomenal.

Type
II. Teleosemantics
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2001

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baker, Lynne Rudder 1991. “Dretske on the Explanatory Role of Belief,” Philosophical Studies 63, 99–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bigelow, John and Pargetter, Robert 1987. “Functions,” Journal of Philosophy 83, 181–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, Robert 1975. “Functional Analysis,” Journal of Philosophy 72, 741–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald 1963. “Actions, Reasons, and Causes,” Journal of Philosophy 60. Reprinted in Davidson, DonaldEssays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980.Google Scholar
Davies, Paul Sheldon This volume. “The Excesses of Teleosemantics.”Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred. 1988. Explaining Behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Davies, Paul Sheldon 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Davies, Paul Sheldon 1990. “Reply to Reviewers,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50, 819–39.Google Scholar
Davies, Paul Sheldon 1991a. “How Beliefs Explain: Reply to Baker,” Philosophical Studies 63, 113–17.Google Scholar
Davies, Paul Sheldon 1991b. “Dretske's Replies.” In Dretske and his Critics. McLaughlin, Brian ed. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell, pp. 180–221.Google Scholar
Davies, Paul Sheldon. 1996. “How Reasons Explain Behaviour; Reply to Melnyk and Noordhof,” Mind and Language 11, 223–29.Google Scholar
Enç, Berent and Fred, Adams 1992. “Functions and Goal-Directedness,” Philosophy of Science 59, 635–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter 1994. “A Modern History Theory of Functions,” Nous 28, 344–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence 1991. “Actions, Reasons, and the Explanatory Role of Content.” In Dretske and his Critics. McLaughlin, Brian ed. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell, pp. 73101.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon 1991. “Dretske on How Reasons Explain Behavior,” in Dretske and his Critics. McLaughlin, Brian ed. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell, pp. 5272.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett 1989. “Biosemantics,” Journal of Philosophy 86, 281–97. Reprinted in Millikan (1993a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett 1990. “Compare and Contrast Dretske, Fodor, and Millikan on Teleosemantics,” Philosophical Topics 18, 151–61. Reprinted in Millikan (1993a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett 1993a. White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett 1993b. “Explanation in Biopsychology.” In Mental Causation. Heil, John and Mele, Alfred eds. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reprinted in Millikan (1993a).Google Scholar
Neander, Karen 1991. “Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defense,” Philosophy of Science 58, 168–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neander, Karen 1995. “Misrepresenting and Malfunctioning,” Philosophical Studies 79, 109–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David 1987. Reality and Representation. New York: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip 1986. “Broad-Minded Explanation and Psychology.” In Subject, Thought, and Content, Pettit, Phillip and McDowell, John eds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott 1995. “Natural Selection and Distributive Explanation: A Reply to Neander,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46, 384–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stampe, Dennis 1990. “Desires as Reasons- Discussion Notes on Fred Dretske's ‘Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes',” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50, 787–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim 1990. The Representational Mind. New York: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Walsh, Denis 1996. “Fitness and Function,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47, 553–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, Larry 1973. “Functions,” Philosophical Review 82, 139–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar