Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-nwzlb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T02:39:09.036Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Intentionality and Phenomenality: A Phenomenological Take on the Hard Problem

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Get access

Extract

In his book The Conscious Mind David Chalmers introduced a now-familiar distinction between the hard problem and the easy problems of consciousness. The easy problems are those concerned with the question of how the mind can process information, react to environmental stimuli, and exhibit such capacities as discrimination, categorization, and introspection (Chalmers 1996, 4; 1995, 200). All of these abilities are impressive, but they are, according to Chalmers, not metaphysically baffling, since they can all be tackled by means of the standard repertoire of cognitive science and explained in terms of computational or neural mechanisms. This task might still be difficult, but it is within reach. In contrast, the hard problem — also known as the problem of consciousness (Chalmers 1995, 201) — is the problem of explaining why mental states have phenomenal or experiential qualities. Why is it like something to ‘taste coffee,’ to ‘touch an ice cube,’ to ‘look at a sunset,’ etc.? Why does it feel the way it does? Why does it feel like anything at all?

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Authors 2003

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Carruthers, P. (1998). “Natural Theories of Consciousness,European Journal of Philosophy 6: 203–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. (1995). “Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness,Journal of Consciousness Studies 2(3): 200–19.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. In Search of a Fundamental Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, D. J. (1997). “Moving Forward on the Problem of Consciousness,Journal of Consciousness Studies 4(1): 346.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Flanagan, O. (1992). Consciousness Reconsidered. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Freud, S. (1945). Gesammelte Werke VIII. Werke aus den Jahren 1909-1913. S. Fischer: Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar
Goldman, A. I. (1997). “Consciousness, Folk Psychology, and Cognitive Science.“ In The Nature of Consciousness, ed. Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G.. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 111-25.Google Scholar
Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and Time. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Hodgson, D. (1996). “The Easy Problems Ain't So Easy,Journal of Consciousness Studies 3(1): 6975.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1959). Erste Philosophie II (1923-24) [Husserliana VIII]. Den Haag: >M. Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1973). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vortriige (Husserliana I). Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie I (Husserliana III/1-2). Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Husserl, E. (1984). Logische Untersuchungen II (Husserliana XIX/1-2). Den Haag: M. Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacob, P. (1998). “What Is the Phenomenology of Thought?Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58: 443–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lyons, W. (1995). Approaches to Intentionality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McGinn, C. (1991). The Problem of Consciousness: Essays Toward a Resolution. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Mcintyre, R. (1999). “Naturalizing Phenomenology? Dretske on Qualia.” In Naturalizing Phenomenology, ed. Petitot, J., Varlea, F. J., Pachoud, B., and Roy, J.-M.. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 429–39.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of Perception. Trans. Colin Smith.London: Routledge Press.Google Scholar
Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). Sense and Non-Sense. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1903). “The Refutation of Idealism,” Mind 12:433–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Shaughnessy, B. (2000). Consciousness and the World. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1999). The Threefold Cord. Mind, Body, and World. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rudd, A. J. (1998). “What It's Like and What's Really Wrong with Physicalism: A Wittgensteinian Perspective,Journal of Consciousness Studies 5(4): 454–63.Google Scholar
Sartre, J.-P. (1956). Being and Nothingness. Trans. Hazel Barnes. New York: Philosophical Library.Google Scholar
Scheler, M. (1973). Wesen und Formen der Sympathie. Bern/München: Francke Verlag.Google Scholar
Searle, J. R. (1998). Mind, Language and Society. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Siewert, C. P. (1998). The Significance of Consciousness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, D. W. (1989). The Circle of Acquaintance. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G. (1994). Mental Reality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Tye, M. (1995). Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Van Gulick, R. (1997). “Understanding the Phenomenal Mind: Are We All Just Armadillos?” In Block, N., Flanagan, O., and Güzeldere, G., eds., The Nature of Consciousness, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 559–66.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-awareness and Alterity. A Phenomenological Investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2001a). “Beyond Empathy: Phenomenological Approaches to Intersubjectivity,” Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5-7): 151–67.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2001b). Husserl and Transcendentallntersubjectivity. Athens, OH: Ohio University Press.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2002). “Phenomenology of the Self.” In David, A. and Kircher, T., eds., The Self and Schizophrenia. A Neuropsychological Perspective, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2003a). Husserl's Phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2003b). “Natural Realism, Anti-reductionism, and Intentionality: The “Phenomenology’ of Hilary Putnam.” In Carr, David and Cheung, Chan Fai, eds., Time, Space and Culture. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar